Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

The received view is that the VP pro-form do so cannot be a verbal passive, although it can be unaccusative. I show that this is incorrect: do so can be passive. It can also take a raising to subject verb as its antecedent. This means that do so is compatible with all types of A-movement, although it does not permit A-bar movement of an object. I construct an analysis of do so where it is simply an intransitive verb plus an adverb. Do so combines with a Voice head, which can be unaccusative, passive, or active transitive. The subject of do so is base-generated in Spec-VoiceP, and does not move in unaccusatives or passives. Instead, do so must copy a function from its antecedent in the semantics. The subject of do so can be interpreted semantically as an internal argument if Voice is passive or unaccusative and the antecedent includes a trace, because of the way lambda abstraction works in A-movement. This analysis reconciles the evidence against movement in do so itself with arguments for A-movement in its antecedent. The copy mechanism explains voice and category mismatches, as well as split antecedents and ellipsis-containing antecedents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Examples presented in this paper without a citation represent the native speaker intuitions of the author. Typically they have been checked with a handful of other native speakers.

  2. http://shannaro.wordpress.com/2012/11/30/ All web sources cited accessed 2 March 2018.

  3. http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/when-food-is-family/201208/reflections-the-2012-olympics.

  4. http://www.glahaiti.org/words-of-encouragement-adds-sunshine-to-our-day1.

  5. Quote attributed to Anand Wilder, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Yeasayer.

  6. http://theboar.org/2013/04/19/denis-avey-believe-or-not-believe/.

  7. Tobias Churton, http://www.bonisteelml.org/invisible_history_of_rosicrucians.pdf.

  8. Archive available at https://web.archive.org/web/20150804171820/https://roadtrippers.com/stories/harvard-discovers-three-of-its-library-books-are-bound-in-human-flesh.

  9. http://www.entrepreneur.com/article/197692.

  10. Corpus available at http://corpus.byu.edu/coca/.

  11. I also propose that researchers start indicating numerical scores where they are available. For instance, a sentence could be marked “1/7‡” to indicate that the mean acceptability assigned to the sentence by speakers was one on a scale of one to seven.

  12. http://www.entrepreneur.com/article/197692.

  13. I have only come across one attested example of cataphoric do so:

    1. (i)

      Having failed to do so because of a space crunch last issue, I must review the ground rules this time. (MIT Technology Review, Nov/Dec 2016, Puzzle Corner)

    This example seems perfectly acceptable, so there must be others.

  14. A logical alternative would be that passive and stative do so are ungrammatical, but can be judged acceptable due to extragrammatical factors. Arregui et al. (2006) suggest such an account of certain patterns of VP ellipsis. I will not address this possibility further here. For some criticism of this account of VP ellipsis, see Kertz (2013).

  15. See also Heim (1996), Johnson (2001). These works all assume that the contrast condition is a matter of grammaticality. I take it to be a matter of acceptability, instead. See the works cited for a formalization of the condition in terms of Rooth’s (1992b) theory of focus.

  16. The reviewer who suggested a dialect difference based on age reports that he or she finds all cases of passive do so unacceptable, but unaccusative do so is acceptable. I have not encountered any other speakers who have this judgment. At present, I have no good explanation for any speaker with this pattern of judgments. One possibility is that, for speakers with this pattern of judgments, the Action Factor needs to be split into two different factors, one referring to eventive versus stative, and the other referring to active versus passive. The latter would not be overridden by the Contrast Factor.

  17. http://www.check-six.com/lib/origin.htm.

  18. http://www.majorleagueeating.com/contests.php?action=detail&eventID=437.

  19. https://beavercountian.com/content/daily/bank-slips-show-3-4-million-unilaterally-withdrawn-by-financial-administrator-lavalle-treasurer-javens.

  20. http://isportsweb.com/2016/02/07/arizona-diamondbacks-projected-batting-lineup/.

  21. Japan at War: An Encyclopedia, p. 170. Accessed at https://books.google.com/books?id=RHXG0JV9zEkC.

  22. http://www.redchairblogs.com/starstruck/2015/04/24/a-cosmic-dance/.

  23. http://www.hitechbloodstock.com/coat%20colour.htm.

  24. Adding a full relative clause in (65) forces these sentences to be monoclausal expletive passives, and not reduced relative clauses (see Deal 2009:note 28), which would require be because they are copular sentences. These are not copular sentences, and so it is significant that get is not allowed.

  25. While I believe this argument for a movement derivation of passives to be solid, I should also note that it would be straightforward to translate the analysis of do so proposed in Sect. 3 to a lexical analysis. Passive and unaccusative do so would simply take an external argument that maps to a logical internal argument, exactly like passives and unaccusatives generally in lexical analyses.

  26. I have modified Kratzer’s denotation to existentially quantify over t. In Kratzer’s analysis, the adjective denotes a set of time intervals (λxλt.∃e,y…).

  27. In the analysis in Bruening (2013), and in the analysis of adjectival passives in Bruening (2014), existential quantification is accomplished not by Voice itself, but by an additional head selecting an unsaturated projection of active Voicetr as its complement. This approach would also be compatible with the proposal regarding do so here.

  28. https://www.thedivorcemagazine.co.uk/do-what-you-love/.

  29. An object of a preposition is also possible, in the pseudopassive or prepositional passive:

    1. (i)

      What was stepped on was done so in a very deliberate manner.

    I assume the head Pass just needs to attract some NP, but that NP does not need to be the object of the verb.

  30. An anonymous reviewer suggests that this base-generation analysis predicts that VP idioms will be unacceptable with do so. Hallman (2013) claims that they are unacceptable. However, it is well-known that idiom chunks can antecede pro-forms and are not limited to movement dependencies (e.g., Nunberg et al. 1994). This analysis therefore makes no predictions concerning idioms, and idioms are indeed acceptable with do so, as in The shit hits the fan with astonishing regularity around here; how can it do so so frequently? Idioms are also compatible with get passives (Fox and Grodzinsky 1998), which were shown in Sect. 2.7 to also have a base-generation analysis.

  31. Another possibility is that traces can be treated as pronouns, as in Fiengo and May (1994). The pronoun can then be either bound like a variable as in (100), or be referential, as in (99). It could also be an e-type pronoun, which might be necessary for certain cases of quantificational objects. For instance:

    1. (i)

      A: Some types of evidence should not be used at trial. B: Even when it’s legal to do so?

    In (i), the interpretation of do so must be ‘use them’, where ‘them’ refers to the types of evidence introduced in the previous sentence. See more on quantifiers in Sect. 3.11.

  32. A reviewer suggests that this approach to do so might predict that Relativized Minimality could be circumvented in passives of double object constructions in a case of a voice mismatch. The following examples were provided by the reviewer. In (ia), the second object of a double object construction cannot passivize across the first object, for most speakers of English. This might be analyzed as a locality effect on movement specifically, and as such it should not hold if the subject of passive do so is base-generated rather than moved. In (ib), the second object is the subject of passive do so, with an active antecedent, and the example seems much improved:

    1. (i)
      1. a.

        *The money was given the children of the orphanage.

      2. b.

        The money that we gave the children of the orphanage was done so with help from a foundation.

    I will leave a full exploration of this to future work.

  33. Houser’s example in (108) is presented as an example of a middle. However, it appears to be an example of a causative-inchoative verb instead. Houser also presents the opposite order as grammatical:

    1. (i)

      The N800 pairs with other devices easily, and I do so all the time.

    This is not my judgment, however. I find this example as unacceptable as Bouton’s examples in (109). Judgments on mismatches with true middles are not clear to me:

    1. (ii)
      1. a.

        Politicians bribe easily, so don’t fail to do so while you’re in Washington.

      2. b.

        They were able to bribe that politician, because, as everyone knows, politicians do so easily.

    I think these are unacceptable, but I will leave investigation of middles to future work.

  34. A reviewer points out that we ought to expect do so to be able to take an adjective as antecedent. There are very few attested examples of this, but there are a few. Houser (2010:49, (33h,i)) cites two naturally occurring examples. One I found on the web is the following:

    1. (i)

      You do more for your team and for your company if you focus on being instrumental—even when doing so requires an unpopular decision or a bit of radical candor.

    A possible antecedent, and perhaps the most salient one in (i), is being instrumental. The reviewer provides the example in (iia), which he or she judges unacceptable. I disagree with this judgment. Such examples are even more acceptable if the antecedent is embedded within the subject of do so, as in (iib):

    1. (ii)
      1. a.

        John was being very polite. ??He was doing so because he knew how important it was for his future job prospects.

      2. b.

        The students who are being polite to the substitute are only doing so because they have been bribed.

    It appears to me that adjectives can serve as the antecedent for do so, but I will leave a full exploration of this to future work.

  35. However, at least some speakers find the following examples acceptable:

    1. (i)
      1. a.

        The restaurants that sell no alcohol do so because they couldn’t get a liquor license.

      2. b.

        The refugees that kept not a single personal belonging regretted doing so.

    In these examples, do so is not interpreted as including a definite description, instead it includes a negative object. I will have to leave a full exploration of quantificational objects to future work.

References

  • Akmajian, Adrian, and Thomas Wasow. 1975. The constituent structure of VP and AUX and the position of the verb BE. Linguistic Analysis 1: 205–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arregui, Ana, Charles Clifton Jr., Lyn Frazier, and Keir Moulton. 2006. Processing elided verb phrases with flawed antecedents: The recycling hypothesis. Journal of Memory and Language 55: 232–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baltin, Mark R. 2012. Deletion versus pro-forms: An overly simple dichotomy? Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 30: 381–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouton, Lawrence. 1969. Identity constraints on the do-so rule. Research on Language and Social Interaction 1: 231–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouton, Lawrence. 1970. Do so: Do + adverb. In Studies presented to Robert B. Lees by his students, eds. Jerrold M. Sadock and Anthony L. Vanek, 17–38. Edmonton: Linguistics Research, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowers, John. 2010. Arguments as relations. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan, Joan. 1982. The passive in lexical theory. In The mental representation of grammatical relations, ed. Joan Bresnan, 3–86. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruening, Benjamin. 2013. By-phrases in passives and nominals. Syntax 16: 1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruening, Benjamin. 2014. Word formation is syntactic: Adjectival passives in English. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 32: 363–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruening, Benjamin. 2015. Depictive secondary predicates, light verb give, and theories of double object constructions. Ms., University of Delaware. Available at http://udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/DepictivesDOCs2.pdf. Accessed 28 February 2018.

  • Bruening, Benjamin, and Thuan Tran. 2015. The nature of the passive, with an analysis of Vietnamese. Lingua 165: 133–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1957. Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1977. On wh-movement. In Formal syntax, eds. Peter Culicover, Thomas Wasow, and Adrian Akmajian, 71–132. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1993. A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In The view from building 20: Essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvain Bromberger, eds. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, 1–52. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. Michael Kenstowicz, 1–52. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chung, Sandra, William Ladusaw, and James McCloskey. 1995. Sluicing and logical form. Natural Language Semantics 3: 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornish, Francis. 1992. So Be It: The discourse-semantic roles of so and it. Journal of Semantics 9: 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culicover, Peter W., and Ray Jackendoff. 2005. Simpler syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dalrymple, Mary, Stuart Shieber, and Fernando Pereira. 1991. Ellipsis and higher-order unification. Linguistics and Philosophy 14: 399–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deal, Amy Rose. 2009. The origin and content of expletives: Evidence from “selection”. Syntax 12: 285–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doggett, Teal Bissell. 2004. All things being unequal: Locality in movement. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Elbourne, Paul. 2001. E-type anaphora as NP-deletion. Natural Language Semantics 9: 241–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne, Paul. 2008. Ellipsis sites as definite descriptions. Linguistic Inquiry 39: 191–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Embick, David. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic Inquiry 35: 355–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiengo, Robert, and Robert May. 1994. Indices and identity. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 1999. Reconstruction, binding theory and the interpretation of chains. Linguistic Inquiry 30: 157–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2002. Antecedent contained deletion and the copy theory of movement. Linguistic Inquiry 33: 63–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny, and Yosef Grodzinsky. 1998. Children’s passive: A view from the by-phrase. Linguistic Inquiry 29: 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, Edward, Steve Piantadosi, and Kristina Fedorenko. 2011. Using mechanical Turk to obtain and analyze English acceptability judgments. Language and Linguistics Compass 5: 509–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haddican, William. 2007. The structural deficiencies of verbal pro-forms. Linguistic Inquiry 38: 539–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hallman, Peter. 2004. Constituency and agency in VP. In West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL) 23, eds. Vineeta Chand, Ann Kelleher, Angelo J. Rodríguez, and Benjamin Schmeiser, 304–317. Somerville: Cascadilla Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallman, Peter. 2013. Predication and movement in passive. Lingua 125: 76–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hankamer, Jorge, and Ivan Sag. 1976. Deep and surface anaphora. Linguistic Inquiry 7: 391–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardt, Daniel. 1993. Verb phrase ellipsis: Form, meaning and processing. PhD diss., University of Pennsylvania.

  • Hardt, Daniel. 1999. Dynamic interpretation of verb phrase ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy 22: 185–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1990. E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy 13: 137–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1996. Predicates or formulas? evidence from ellipsis. In Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 7, eds. Aaron Lawson and Eun Cho, 197–221. Ithaca: Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houser, Michael John. 2010. The syntax and semantics of do so anaphora. PhD diss., University of California, Berkeley. Available at http://linguistics.berkeley.edu/~mhouser/Papers/do_so_anaphora.pdf. Accessed 28 February 2018.

  • Huang, C.-T. James. 2013. Variations in non-canonical passives. In Non-canonical passives, eds. Artemis Alexiadou and Florian Schäfer, 95–114. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Huddleston, Rodney, and Geoffrey K. Pullum. 2002. The Cambridge grammar of the English language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jayaseelan, K. A. 1990. Incomplete VP deletion and Gapping. Linguistic Analysis 20: 64–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Kyle. 2001. What VP ellipsis can do, and what it can’t, but not why. In The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, eds. Mark Baltin and Chris Collins, 439–479. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Kyle. 2009. Gapping is not (VP-) ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 40: 289–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kehler, Andrew, and Gregory Ward. 1999. On the semantics and pragmatics of identifier so. In The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view, ed. Ken Turner, 233–256. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher. 2008. Argument contained ellipsis. In Topics in ellipsis, ed. Kyle Johnson, 95–131. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kertz, Laura. 2013. Verb phrase ellipsis: The view from information structure. Language 89: 390–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koizumi, Masatoshi. 1994. Secondary predicates. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 3: 25–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Phrase structure and the lexicon, eds. John Rooryck and Laurie Zaring, 109–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2005. Building resultatives. In Event arguments: Foundations and applications, eds. Claudia Maienborn and Angelika Wöllstein, 177–212. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George. 1971. On generative semantics. In Semantics: An interdisciplinary reader in philosophy, linguistics and psychology, eds. Danny D. Steinberg and Leon A. Jakobovits, 232–296. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George, and John Robert Ross. 1966. Criterion for verb phrase constituency. In Mathematical linguistics and automatic translation, ed. Anthony G. Oettinger, 1–11. Cambridge: Harvard Computational Laboratory.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George, and John Robert Ross. 1976. Why you can’t do so into the sink. In Notes from the linguistic underground, ed. James D. McCawley. Vol. 7 of Syntax and semantics, 101–111. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, Meredith. 2006. Variables in natural language. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Lappin, Shalom. 1984. VP anaphora, quantifier scope, and logical form. Linguistic Analysis 13: 273–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasnik, Howard. 1995. A note on pseudogapping. In Papers on minimalist syntax, eds. Rob Pensalfini and Hiroyuki Ura. Vol. 27 of MIT working papers in linguistics, 143–164. Cambridge: MITWPL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasnik, Howard, and Robert Fiengo. 1974. Complement object deletion. Linguistic Inquiry 5: 535–571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasnik, Howard, and Mamoru Saito. 1992. Move α: Conditions on its application and output. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity: At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Robert. 1977. The grammar of quantification. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Merchant, Jason. 2008. An asymmetry in voice mismatches in VP-ellipsis and pseudogapping. Linguistic Inquiry 39: 169–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2013. Voice and ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 44: 77–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Philip. 2011. The choice between verbal anaphors in discourse. In Anaphora processing and applications: 8th Discourse Anaphora and Anaphor Resolution Colloquium (DAARC) 2011, eds. Iris Hendrickx, Sobha Lalitha Devi, António Branco, and Ruslan Mitkov, 82–95. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Philip. 2013. Usage preferences: The case of the English verbal anaphor do so. In 20th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), ed. Stefan Müller, 121–139. Stanford: CSLI Publications. Available at http://csli-publications.stanford.edu/HPSG/2013. Accessed 28 February 2018.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanan, K. P. 1983. Functional and anaphoric control. Linguistic Inquiry 14: 641–674.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulton, Keir. 2013. Raising from the dead. Linguistic Inquiry 44: 157–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Stefan. 2006. Phrasal or lexical constructions? Language 82: 850–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Stefan, and Stephen Wechsler. 2014. Lexical approaches to argument structure. Theoretical Linguistics 40: 1–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, Geoffrey, Ivan A. Sag, and Thomas Wasow. 1994. Idioms. Language 70: 491–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perlmutter, David M. 1978. Impersonal passives and the unaccusative hypothesis. In Annual meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (BLS) 4, 157–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlmutter, David M., and Paul M. Postal. 1984. The 1-Advancement Exclusiveness Law. In Studies in relational grammar 2, eds. David M. Perlmutter and Carol G. Rosen, 81–125. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1994. Head-driven phrase structure grammar. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylkkänen, Liina. 2008. Introducing arguments. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramchand, Gillian Catriona. 2008. Verb meaning and the lexicon: A first-phase syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, Lisa A. 2011. Get-passives. The Linguistic Review 28: 41–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, Mats. 1992a. Ellipsis redundancy and reduction redundancy. In Stuttgart Ellipsis Workshop, eds. Steve Berman and Arild Hestvik. Stuttgart: Universitäten Stuttgart und Tübingen in Kooperation mit der IBM Deutschland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, Mats. 1992b. A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics 1: 117–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, Peter. 1967. The grammar of English predicate complement constructions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, John Robert. 1972. Act. In Semantics of natural language, eds. Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, 70–126. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sag, Ivan. 1976. Deletion and logical form. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Sag, Ivan, Thomas Wasow, and Emily Bender. 2003. Syntactic theory: A formal introduction. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, Bernhard. 2000. Topics in ellipsis. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Stroik, Thomas. 2001. On the light verb hypothesis. Linguistic Inquiry 32: 362–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, Anna. 1997. Strategies for scope taking. In Ways of scope taking, ed. Anna Szabolcsi, 109–154. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tomioka, Satoshi. 2008. A step-by-step guide to ellipsis resolution. In Topics in ellipsis, ed. Kyle Johnson, 210–228. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, Gregory L., and Andrew Kehler. 2005. Syntactic form and discourse accessibility. In Anaphoric processing: Linguistic, cognitive, and computational modelling, eds. António Branco, Tony McEnery, and Ruslan Mitkov, 365–384. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wasow, Thomas. 1977. Transformations and the lexicon. In Formal syntax, eds. Peter Culicover, Adrian Akmajian, and Thomas Wasow, 327–360. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber, Bonnie Lynn. 1978. A formal approach to discourse anaphora. PhD diss., Harvard University.

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful comments, the author would like to thank the anonymous reviewers and the associate editor, Kyle Johnson.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin Bruening.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bruening, B. Passive do so. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 37, 1–49 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-9408-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-9408-1

Keywords

Navigation