Skip to main content
Log in

The Impact of Explicit Teaching of Methodological Aspects of Physics on Scientistic Beliefs and Interest

  • Article
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We assessed the impact of teaching methodological aspects of physics on students’ scientistic beliefs and subject interest in physics in a repeated-measurement design with a total of 142 students of upper secondary physics classes. Students gained knowledge of methodological aspects from the pre-test to the post-test and reported reduced scientistic beliefs, both from their own views and from their presumed prototypical physicists’ views. We found no direct impact of teaching on students’ subject interest in physics. As path analysis indicates, this result can be traced back to opposing paths: Lower scientistic beliefs of students attenuate subject interest while lower presumed scientistic beliefs that they hold of physicists foster subject interest. This finding is in accordance with the self-to-prototype matching theory that predicts an impact of the overlap between students’ self-image and their prototypical image on subject interest in physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In addition to ontological and epistemological presuppositions, a scientistic worldview may include additional components, e.g., expressing the superiority of science over other different approaches to describe reality (in-depth discussions of different scientistic positions can be found in Stenmark (1997) and Mutschler (2002); see also Appendix 3). Considered a philosophical position, scientism is closely related to materialism, physicalism (see Section 4.2), and ontological naturalism (Papineau 2007).

  2. Intersubjective testability is what is generally meant by objectivity. We will use the term intersubjective that stresses the social nature of the scientific enterprise (Feigl 1981, p. 369).

  3. This seems especially to be the case for the field of physics. In recent years—with the advent of rather speculative theories in high-energy physics and cosmology—empirical testability has been defended as an important criterion for science by a number of physicists (e.g., Ellis and Silk 2014).

  4. We talk about “laws of nature” instead of physical theories in the teaching unit. In our opinion, this is a justifiable simplification for a first approach to this topic. Especially as differentiating between laws and theories seems to be difficult for many students (Lederman, Abd-El-Khalick, Bell and Schwartz 2002). Nevertheless, this is an important goal for NOS education and should be dealt with in subsequent teaching units.

  5. This property is exactly what defines “metaphysical” for Popper (2005). Historically, there has been some debate, and still is, whether science relies on certain indispensable metaphysical assumptions, e.g., that there is regularity and causality in nature. A detailed account of this debate is provided by Gauch (2003; see also Margenau 1977). For recent summaries on this topic, see Hansson and Lindahl (2010) and Hansson (2014).

  6. In a saturated model, there are as many estimated parameters as data points. Per definition, this leads to a perfect fit.

References

  • Allen, C., Bekoff, M., & Lauder, G. (Eds.). (1998). Nature’s purposes. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (1993). Benchmarks for science literacy. Project 2061. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Aronson, E. (2002). Building empathy, compassion, and achievement in the jigsaw classroom. In J. Aronson (Ed.), Improving academic achievement. Impact of psychological factors on education (pp. 209–225). San Diego: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Aronson, E., Blaney, N., Stephan, C., Sikes, J., & Snapp, M. (1978). The jigsaw classroom. Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., & Moulines, C. U. (Eds.). (1996). Structuralist theory of science: focal issues, new results. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumert, J., & Köller, O. (1998). Interest research concerning secondary level I: An overview. In L. Hoffmann, A. Krapp, K. A. Renninger, & J. Baumert (Eds.), Interest and learning. Proceedings of the Seeon-conference on Interest and Gender (pp. 241–256). IPN: Kiel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bendixen, L. D., & Rule, D. C. (2004). An integrative approach to personal epistemology : a guiding model. Educational Psychologist, 39, 69–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. S., Kornell, N., Bjork, E. L., & Bjork, R. A. (2013). Why interleaving enhances inductive learning: the roles of discrimination and retrieval. Memory & Cognition, 41, 392–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichroth, W., Dahncke, H., Jung, W., Kuhn, W., Merzyn, G., & Weltner, K. (1999). Fachdidaktik Physik. Köln: Aulis.

  • Bogen, J. (2014). Theory and observation in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2014 edition). Retrieved September 26, 2016, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/science-theory-observation.

  • Chinn, C. A., & Brewer, W. F. (1993). The role of anomalous data in knowledge acquisition: a theoretical framework and implications for science instruction. Review of Educational Research, 63, 1–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clough, M. P. (2006). Learners’ responses to the demands of conceptual change: considerations for effective nature of science instruction. Science Education, 15, 463–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W. W. (1996). Worldview theory and conceptual change in science education. Science Education, 80, 579–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W. W., & Loving, C. C. (1998). The card exchange: introducing the philosophy of science. In W. F. McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education. Rationales and strategies (pp. 73–82). Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, Z. (2008). Entwicklung schulischer Interessen im Jugendalter [Development of academic interests within adolescence]. Münster: Waxmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits: human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry, 11, 227–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deng, F., Chen, D.-T., Tsai, C.-C., & Chai, C. S. (2011). Students’ views of the nature of science: a critical review of research. Science Education, 95, 961–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denissen, J. H., Zarrett, N. R., & Eccles, J. S. (2007). I like to do it, I’m able, and I know I am: longitudinal couplings between domain-specific achievement, self-concept, and interest. Child Development, 78, 430–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeWitt, J., Osborne, J., Archer, L., Dillon, J., Willis, B., & Wong, B. (2013). Young children’s aspirations in science: the unequivocal, the uncertain and the unthinkable. International Journal of Science Education, 35, 1037–1063.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duit, R., Gropengießer, H., Kattmann, U., Komorek, M., & Parchmann, I. (2012). The model of educational reconstruction—a framework for improving teaching and learning science. In D. Jorde & J. Dillon (Eds.), Science education research and practice in europe—retrospective and prospective (pp. 13–37). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

  • Ellis, G., & Silk, J. (2014). Scientific method: defend the integrity of physics. Nature, 516, 321–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, D. (2007). Student interests—The German and Austrian ROSE Survey. Journal of Biological Education, 42(1), 5–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1981). Inquiries and provocations: selected writings 1929–1974. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gadermann, A. M., Guhn, M., & Zumbo, B. D. (2012). Estimating ordinal reliability for Likert-type and ordinal item response data: a conceptual, empirical, and practical guide. Practical Assessment, Research & Evaluation, 17(3), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H. G. (2003). Scientific method in practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H. G. (2009). Science, worldviews, and education. Science & Education, 18, 667–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gill, M. G., Ashton, P. T., & Algina, J. (2004). Changing preservice teacher’s epistemological beliefs about teaching and learning in mathematics: an intervention study. Contemporary Educational Psychology, 29, 164–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guzzetti, B. J., Snyder, T. E., Glass, G. V., & Gamas, W. S. (1993). Promoting conceptual change in science: a comparative meta-analysis of instructional interventions from reading education and science education. Reading Research Quarterly, 28, 116–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haeussler, P., & Hoffmann, L. (1998). Qualitative differences in students’ interest in physics and the dependence on gender and age. In L. Hoffmann, A. Krapp, K. A. Renninger, & J. Baumert (Eds.), Interest and learning. Proceedings of the Seeon-conference on Interest and Gender (pp. 280–289). IPN: Kiel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannover, B., & Kessels, U. (2004). Self-to-prototype matching as a strategy for making academic choices. Why high school students do not like math and science. Learning and Instruction, 14, 51–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, L. (2014). Students’ views concerning worldview presuppositions underpinning science: is the world really ordered, uniform, and comprehensible? Science Education, 98, 743–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, L., & Lindahl, B. (2010). I have chosen another way of thinking’. Students’ relations to science with a focus on worldview. Science & Education, 19, 895–918.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, L., & Redfors, A. (2007a). Physics and the possibility of a religious view of the universe: Swedish upper secondary students’ views. Science & Education, 16, 461–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, L., & Redfors, A. (2007b). Upper secondary students in group discussions about physics and our presuppositions of the world. Science & Education, 16, 1007–1025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, M. (2010). Adolescents’ development of individual interests: a product of multiple goal regulation? Educational Psychologist, 45, 149–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Höttecke, D., & Silva, C. C. (2011). Why implementing history and philosophy in school science education is a challenge: an analysis of obstacles. Science & Education, 20, 293–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hynd, C. R. (2001). Refutational texts and the change process. International Journal of Educational Research, 35, 699–714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G., & Nola, R. (2014). New directions for nature of science research. In M. R. Matthews (Ed.), International handbook of research in history, philosophy and science teaching (pp. 999–1021). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Kampourakis, K. (2016). The “general aspects” conceptualization as a pragmatic and effective means to introducing students to nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 53, 667–682.

  • Kessels, U., & Taconis, R. (2012). Alien or alike? How the perceived similarity between the typical science teacher and a student’s self-image correlates with choosing science at school. Research in Science Education, 42, 1049–1071.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kienhues, D., Bromme, R., & Stahl, E. (2008). Changing epistemological beliefs: the unexpected impact of a short-term intervention. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 78, 545–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korte, S. (2015). Die Grenzen der Naturwissenschaft als Thema des Physikunterrichts. [The limitations of science as topic in physics education]. Berlin: Logos.

  • Korte, S., Berger, R., Imwalle, C., & Hänze, M. (2016). Entwicklung und erste Validierung eines Fragebogens zur Erfassung von Szientismus. [Development and validation of a questionnaire to assess scientism]. Diagnostica, 63, 42–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krapp, A. (2002). An educational-psychological theory of interest and its relation to SDT. In E. L. Deci & R. M. Ryan (Eds.), Handbook of self-determination research (pp. 405–427). Rochester: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In S. G. Harding (Ed.), Can theories be refuted? (pp. 205–259). Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lavonen, J., Byman, R., Uitto, A., Juuti, K., & Meisalo, V. (2008). Students’ interest and experiences in physics and chemistry related themes: reflections based on a ROSE-survey in Finland. Themes in Science and Technology Education, 1, 7–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (2007). Nature of science: past, present, and future. In S. K. Abell & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 831–880). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G., Abd-El-Khalick, F., Bell, R. L., & Schwartz, R. S. (2002). Views of nature of science questionnaire: toward valid and meaningful assessment of learners’ conceptions of nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 39, 497–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M. (2006). Metaphysics: a contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. (1998). Philosophy of science: an overview for educators. Science & Education, 7, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mamlok-Naaman, R., Ben-Zvi, R., Hofstein, A., Menis, J., & Erduran, S. (2005). Learning science through a historical approach: does it affect the attitudes of non-science-oriented students towards science? International Journal of Science and Mathematics Education, 3, 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margenau, H. (1977). The nature of physical reality. Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (Ed.). (1998). Constructivism and science education: a philosophical examination. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2012). Changing the focus: from nature of science (NOS) to features of science (FOS). In M. S. Khine (Ed.), Advances in nature of science research (pp. 3–26). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F. (2008). Seeking historical examples to illustrate key aspects of the nature of science. Science & Education, 17, 249–263.

  • McNeill, K. L., & Krajcik, J. (2007). Middle school students’ use of appropriate and inappropriate evidence in writing scientific explanations. In M. Lovett & P. Shah (Eds.), Thinking with data (pp. 233–265). New York: Taylor & Francis Group, LLC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mosterín, J. (2005). Anthropic explanations in cosmology. In P. Háyek, L. Valdés, & D. Westerstahl (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science: Proceedings of the 12th International Congress of the LMPS (pp. 441–473). London: King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, P. K., & Mason, L. (2006). Changing knowledge and beliefs. In P. A. Alexander & P. H. Winne (Eds.), Handbook of educational psychology (2nd ed., pp. 305–324). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mutschler, H.-D. (2002). Naturphilosophie [Natural philosophy]. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council. (1996). National science education standards. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J., Collins, S., Ratcliffe, M., Millar, R., & Duschl, R. (2003a). What “ideas-about-science” should be taught in school science? A Delphi study of the expert community. Journal of Research in Science Education, 40, 692–720.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J., Simon, S., & Collins, S. (2003b). Attitudes towards science: a review of the literature and its implications. International Journal of Science Education, 25, 1049–1079.

  • Paas, F., Renkl, A., & Sweller, J. (2003). Cognitive load theory and instructional design: recent developments. Educational Psychologist, 38, 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2007). Naturalism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2007 Edition). Retrieved February, 16, 2017, from plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/naturalism/.

  • Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo, J. T. (1986). The elaboration likelihood model of persuasion. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 19, 123–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Philosophy of Science. (2016). In Wikipedia. Retrieved February 16, 2017, from https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophy_of_science.

  • Piaget, J. (1985). The equilibration of cognitive structures: the central problem of intellectual development. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietschmann, H. (1997). Three limits of scientific knowledge. In G. Costa, G. Calucci, & M. Giorgi (Eds.), Conceptual tools for understanding nature (pp. 11–20). Singapore: World Scientific Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poole, M. W. (1998). Science and science education: a Judeo-Christian perspective. In W. W. Cobern (Ed.), Socio-cultural perspectives on science education (pp. 181–201). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2005). The logic of scientific discovery. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A., Hewson, P. W., & Gertzog, W. A. (1982). Accommodation of a scientific conception: toward a theory of conceptual change. Science Education, 66, 211–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, M. H., Earman, J., Glymour, C., Lennox, J. G., Machamer P., McGuire J. E. et al. (1999). Introduction to the philosophy of science. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Schecker, H., Fischer, H. E., & Wiesner, H. (2004). Physikunterricht in der gymnasialen Oberstufe. In H.-E. Tenorth (Ed.), Kerncurriculum Oberstufe II (pp. 148–234). Weinheim: Beltz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiefele, U. (2009). Situational and individual interest. In K. R. Wentzel & A. Wigfield (Eds.), Handbook of motivation in school (pp. 197–223). New York: Taylor Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiefele, U., Krapp, A., Wild, K.-P., & Winteler, A. (1993). Der “Fragebogen zum Studieninteresse” (FSI). Diagnostica, 39, 335–351 (An english version is available [Retrieved February 16, 2017, from https://www.unibw.de/sowi1_1/interest/fields/siq]).

  • Schreiner, C., & Sjøberg, S. (2007). Science education and youth’s identity construction—two incompatible projects? In D. Corrigan, J. Dillon, & R. Gunstone (Eds.), The re-emergence of values in the science curriculum (pp. 231–247). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sjøberg, S., & Schreiner, C. (2007). Young learners’ attitudes and interests: results and perspectives from the project ROSE (The Relevance of Science Education). International Newsletter on Physics Education, 54, 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Springer, L., Stanne, M. E., & Donovan, S. (1999). Effects of small-group learning on undergraduates in science, mathematics, engineering and technology: a meta-analysis. Review of Educational Research, 69, 21–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stack, G. J. (1998). Materialism. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy: Luther to Nifo, 6 (pp. 171–172). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenmark, M. (1997). What is scientism? Religious Studies, 33, 15–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, D., & Blocker, H. G. (2006). Fundamentals of philosophy. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2015). Physicalism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (spring 2015 edition). Retrieved February, 16, 2017, from plato.stanford.edu/entries/physicalism/.

  • Su, R., Rounds, J., & Armstrong, P. I. (2009). Men and things, women and people: a meta-analysis of sex differences in interests. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 859–884.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tippett, C. D. (2010). Refutation text in science education: a review of two decades of research. International Journal of Science and Mathematics Education, 8, 951–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wigfield, A., & Cambria, J. (2010). Students’ achievement values, goal orientations, and interest: definitions, development, and relations to achievement outcomes. Developmental Review, 30, 1–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roland Berger.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that there is no conflict of interest.

Appendices

Appendix 1

Three sample problems for subsequent classroom discussions of the aspect “intersubjective empirical testability of physical theories”:

  1. (1)

    In court, a single testimony is considered as important evidence. It can lead to a conviction, even if no other “traces” point to the perpetrator. Compare this with physics and discuss possible similarities and differences!

  2. (2)

    What is your view: Could feelings like love or hate be subjects of physics research? Take the criterion of empirical testability into account and try to substantiate your position. Discuss it with your classmates!

  3. (3)

    At the research center CERN in Genova exists the world’s largest accelerator for elementary particles (such particles are, e.g., electrons, protons, or neutrons of which atoms are composed). This machine—called LHC (Large Hadron Collider)—can accelerate particles to kinetic energies much higher than accessible with any other scientific device. It is unique in the world due to its gigantic dimensions and enormous costs. Discuss to which extent this could be a problem with respect to the empirical testability criterion.

Appendix 2: Example of a jigsaw NOS teaching text

1.1 Expert group 3: “All-statements” are not provable.

Many people believe that physics can provide answers to all of life’s questions. To decide which questions can be answered by physics and which cannot, one has to address the characteristics of physics methodology.

First, in the expert group, you will learn about one characteristic of physics methodology. Subsequently, in “jigsaw groups,” you will teach the other group members this characteristic. Hence, a lot depends on your expertise of the following information.

1.1.1 Information for characteristic 3: “All-statements” are not provable.

Many statements in physics are all-encompassing, e.g., “All galaxies at all times depart from each other.” We qualify these statements as “all-statements” because they are all-encompassing generalizations. The example statement encompasses all galaxies at all times.

However, “all-statements” are not provable. Why is this? We can explain it with the following example. First, we are not able to investigate the vast number of galaxies for practical reasons. Second, investigating galaxies for all times even in the remote past or future is impossible as a matter of principle.

Laws of nature are “all-statements,” e.g., the law of gravitation states that all released objects are accelerated to Earth by the force of gravity. Hence, the law of gravitation provides statements about the past and the future. For us, however, a test can only be conducted in the present. Hence, laws of nature are not provable. But, although laws of nature are not provable, one assumes that they are true because they are confirmed many times.

However, they can be rejected by a single counterexample. If one day in the distant future a stone is launched from the Earth’s surface, the law of gravitation would be shown to be false or, at least, must be limited.

Please note that the word “all” is not necessarily for “all-statements,” e.g., “Warm food cools in a cold surrounding.” This assertion applies to all warm food. Probably, one will never have warm food that becomes warmer in a cold surrounding. Yet, the statement is not provable because one cannot be absolutely sure. It is not completely impossible that someday a temperature of warm meal increases by absorption of energy from a colder surrounding.

Therefore, we conclude with the following summary: Physics cannot prove “All-statements.”

Appendix 3

Table 2 Items in the scientistic beliefs questionnaire and the corresponding labeling according to Stenmark (1997)

Appendix 4: Performance test on methodological aspects of physics

(sample solutions are in italics)

  1. (1)

    Are the following statements provable? Please justify your answer.

    1. a.

      There are substances that have higher temperatures in a liquid state than in a solid state.

    2. b.

      All substances have higher temperatures in a liquid state than in a solid state.

Statement b is not provable because one does not have access to all substances. Statement a is provable; e.g., the temperature of liquid water is higher than that of ice from the refrigerator. [1 point]

  1. (2)

    Are the following statements testable by physics? Please justify your answer.

    1. a.

      Today, the temperature in Hamburg is lower than in Munich.

    2. b.

      Today, the temperature in Hamburg is more comfortable than in Munich.

Statement a is testable but not statement b because all persons would agree only in the first case. [1 point]

  1. (3)

    Do the following questions ask for physical causation? Please justify your answer.

    1. a.

      What is the purpose of a thermometer?

    2. b.

      What is the reason for the expansion of the liquid in a thermometer?

The expansion of a liquid (question b) can be traced back to a physical reason. By contrast, the purpose of the thermometer cannot be deduced from physical theory. [1 point]

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Korte, S., Berger, R. & Hänze, M. The Impact of Explicit Teaching of Methodological Aspects of Physics on Scientistic Beliefs and Interest. Sci & Educ 26, 377–396 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-017-9899-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-017-9899-x

Navigation