Skip to main content

Changing the Focus: From Nature of Science (NOS) to Features of Science (FOS)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Advances in Nature of Science Research

Abstract

This chapter argues that one weakness of the important and influential nature of science (NOS) research in science education is that it is crucially ambiguous and unclear on important philosophical points, and that a more informed understanding of the history and philosophy of science can rectify these problems. Further it is argued that NOS research would be improved by changing its focus from the essentialist efforts to delineate the nature of science (and associated research on factors affecting its teaching and learning), to a wider and more relaxed programme of enunciating important features of science (FOS) that can contribute to teachers and students having a better and more complex appreciation of the subject they are teaching and learning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I have surveyed and commented on this history in Matthews (1994, Chaps. 4, 5).

  2. 2.

    See Lederman (1986, 1992, 2004, 2007) and contributions to Flick and Lederman (2004).

  3. 3.

    This point has been persuasively argued by Gürol Irzik and Robert Nola (2011).

  4. 4.

    An accessible source for some of Whewell’s historical and philosophical studies is Elkana (1984). This includes selections from his Bridgewater Treatises on natural theology.

  5. 5.

    On this, see Elkana (1984, Chap xxii), Laudan (1981) and Yeo (1993).

  6. 6.

    Some excellent recent books on the Enlightenment include Dupré (2004), Hankins (1985), Himmelfarb (2004), Israel (2001) and Porter (2000).

  7. 7.

    One of numerous guides to the achievements of the Scientific Revolution is Gribbin (2002, Book 2).

  8. 8.

    See contributions to special issues of Science & Education (vol. 6 no. 4 1997, vol. 7 no. 6 1998), McComas (1998), Flick and Lederman (2004). See also the literature reviews in Abd-El-Khalick and Lederman (2000) and Lederman (2007).

  9. 9.

    For a critical account of instruments used for NOS assessment from the 1950s to the present, see Lederman, Wade and Bell (1998).

  10. 10.

    Norman Lederman, now professor of science education at the Chicago Institute of Technology, was formerly at Oregon State University. Among his many publications see especially Lederman (1992, 2004). His original Oregon State students included Fouad Abd-El-Khalick, Renee Schwartz, Valarie Akerson and Randy Bell – all of whom have published widely in this field.

  11. 11.

    The list is articulated and defended in, among other places, Lederman et al. (2002, 499–502), Lederman (2004, 303–308), Schwartz and Lederman (2008, 745–762).

  12. 12.

    Laudan first made the claim in his ‘Demise of the Demarcation Problem’ (Laudan, 1983). A recent survey of the ensuing debate, and refutation of the claim, is provided by Robert Pennock (2011).

  13. 13.

    The classic treatment of the ancient and medieval debates about ‘saving appearances’ as the goal of natural philosophy is Duhem (1908/1969).

  14. 14.

    For Berkeley’s positivist critique of Newtonian theory, see Popper (1953/1963).

  15. 15.

    For the outlines of this debate, and a guide to some of the literature, see Matthews (1994, Chap. 8).

  16. 16.

    A classic discussion of the difference between hypothetical constructs (that in principle have existence) and intervening variables (that in principle do not have existence) is Meehl and MacCorquodale (1948). Clarity on this issue is of absolute importance in social science: Is ‘intelligence’ to be understood as a hypothetical construct or an intervening variable? Rivers of ink have been spilt because researchers have not clarified the kind of thing they are looking for.

  17. 17.

    See Matthews (2000, pp. 88–89).

  18. 18.

    The classic statement of this position, but with the causal twist, is Boris Hessen’s 1931 The Social and Economic Roots of Newton’s ‘Principia’. For Hessen’s text and commentary see Freudenthal and McLaughlin (2009). One well-known elaboration of the thesis, in the causal direction, is Freudenthal (1986).

  19. 19.

    For a philosophically sophisticated discussion of some of the issues, see Nola and Irzik (2006).

  20. 20.

    I have argued this claim at some length in Matthews (2000, pp. 245–48).

References

  • Abd-El-Khalick, F. (2004). Over and over again: College students’ views of nature of science. In L. B. Flick & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Scientific inquiry and nature of science: Implications for teaching, learning, and teacher education (pp. 389–425). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abd-El-Khalick, F., & Lederman, N. G. (2000). Improving science teachers’ conceptions of the nature of science: A critical review of the literature, International Journal of Science Education, 22(7), 665–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS). (1989). Project 2061: Science for all Americans. Washington, DC: AAAS. Also published by Oxford University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS). (1990). The liberal art of science: Agenda for action. Washington, DC: AAAS.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS). (1993). Benchmarks for science literacy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1721/1901). De Motu. In A. C. Fraser (Ed.), The works of George Berkeley. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Extracts in D. M. Armstrong (Ed.), Berkeley’s philosophical writings, New York, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  • Beyerchen, A. D. (1977). Scientists under Hitler: Politics and the physics community in the third Reich. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birstein, V. J. (2001). The perversion of knowledge: The true story of Soviet science. Cambridge, MA: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003). Twenty-five centuries of quantum physics: From pythagoras to us, and from subjectivism to realism, Science & Education, 12(5–6), 445–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2010). How historical experiments can improve scientific knowledge and science education: The cases of boiling water and electrochemistry. Science & Education. Online first DOI 10.1007/s11191-010-9301-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, S. (2006). Development of an instrument to assess views on nature of science and attitudes towards teaching science. Science Education, 90(5), 803–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, R. S. (1975). Physical science. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1910). Science as subject-matter and as method, Science, 31, 121–127. Reproduced in Science & Education, 4(4), 391–398, 1995.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1916). Democracy and education. New York: Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1908/1969). To save the phenomena: An essay on the idea of physical theory from Plato to Galileo. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, L. (2004). The enlightenment and the intellectual foundations of modern culture. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. A. (1985). Science education and philosophy of science twenty-five, years of mutually exclusive development. School Science and Mathematics, 87(7), 541–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. A. (1990). Restructuring science education: The importance of theories and their development. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. A. (1994). Research in history and philosophy of science. In D. L. Gabel (Ed.), Handbook of research in science teaching and learning (pp. 443–465). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkana, Y. (Ed.). (1984). William Whewell: Selected writings on the history of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fermi, L., & Bernadini, G. (1961). Galileo and the scientific revolution. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flick, L. B., & Lederman, N. G. (Eds.). (2004). Scientific inquiry and nature of science: Implications for teaching, learning and teacher education. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman, P. (1971). Weimar culture, causality and quantum theory, 1918–1927: Adaptation by German physicists and mathematicians to a hostile intellectual environment. In R. McCormmach (Ed.), Historical studies in the physical sciences, No. 3 (pp. 1–116). University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freudenthal, G. (1986). Atom and individual in the age of Newton: On the genesis of the mechanistic world view. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freudenthal, G., & McLaughlin, P. (Eds.). (2009). The social and economic roots of the scientific revolution. Texts by Boris Hessen and Henryk Grossmann. Springer, Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, G. (1638/1954). Dialogues concerning two new sciences (trans. H. Crew & A. de Salvio). New York: Dovers (orig. 1914).

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, L. R. (1973). Science and philosophy in the Soviet Union. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gribbin, J. (2002). Science: A history 1543–2001. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankins, T. L. (1985). Science and the enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1960). Metaphor, model and mechanism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 60, 101–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1953). Models in physics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 4, 198–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1961). Forces and fields: The concept of action at a distance in the history of physics. London: Thomas Nelson & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1966). Models and analogies in science. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Himmelfarb, G. (2004). The roads to modernity. The British, French, and American enlightenments. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1986). Philosophy of science and the science curriculum. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 20, 241–251. Reprinted in M. R. Matthews, ed. (1991). History, philosophy and science teaching: Selected readings (pp. 19–32). Toronto: OISE Press.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1988). Toward a philosophically more valid science curriculum. Science Education, 72, 19–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1993). Re-thinking old ways: Towards a more critical approach to practical work in science. Studies in Science Education, 22, 85–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1996). Laboratory work as scientific method: Three decades of confusion and distortion. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 28, 115–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (2008). Towards scientific literacy: A teachers’ guide to the history, philosophy and sociology of science. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (2009). Teaching and learning about science: Language, theories, methods, history, traditions and values. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton, G. (1975). Science, science teaching and rationality. In S. Hook, P. Kurtz, & M. Todorovich (Eds.), The philosophy of the curriculum (pp. 101–118). Buffalo: Promethus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton, G. (1978). On the educational philosophy of the project physics course. In his The scientific imagination: Case studies (pp. 284–298). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoodbhoy, P. (1991). Islam and science: Religious orthodoxy and the battle for rationality. London: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1885/1964). Science and education. New York: The Citadel Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G., & Nola, R. (2011). A family resemblance approach to the nature of science for science education. Science & Education, 20(7–8), 591–607.

    Google Scholar 

  • Israel, J. (2001). Radical enlightenment: Philosophy and the making of modernity 1650–1750. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1787/1933). Critique of pure reason (2nd ed.) (N. K. Smith, Trans.). London: Macmillan. (First edition, 1781).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kipnis, N. (1996). The “historical-investigative” approach to teaching science. Science & Education, 5(3), 277–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kipnis, N. (1998). A history of science approach to the nature of science: Learning science by rediscovering it. In W. F. McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies (pp. 177–196). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klopfer, L. E. (1969). Case histories and science education. San Francisco: Wadsworth Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). History of science and its rational reconstructions. In J. Worrall & G. Currie (Eds.), The methodology of scientific research programmes: Volume I, pp. 102–138. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Originally 1971)

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). William Whewell on the consilience of inductions. In his Science and hypothesis (pp. 163–180). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1983). The demise of the demarcation problem. In R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan (Eds.), Physics, philosophy and psychoanalysis (pp. 111–127). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1996). Beyond positivism and relativism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (1986). Students’ and teachers’ understanding of the nature of science: A reassessment. School Science and Mathematics, 86(2), 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (1992). Students’ and teachers’ conceptions of the nature of science: A review of the research. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29(4), 331–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (2004). Syntax of nature of science within inquiry and science instruction. In L. B. Flick & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Scientific inquiry and nature of science (pp. 301–317). Dordrecht; Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (2007). Nature of science: Past, present, and future. In S. K. Abell & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 831–880). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N., Abd-el-Khalick, F., Bell, R. L., & Schwartz, R. S. (2002). Views of nature of science questionnaire: Towards valid and meaningful assessment of learners’ conceptions of the nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 39, 497–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G., Wade, P. D., & Bell, R. L. (1998). Assessing the nature of science: A historical perspective. Science & Education, 7(6), 595–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg, D. C., & Numbers, R. L. (Eds.). (1986). God and nature: Historical essays on the encounter between Christianity and science. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1689/1924). An essay concerning human understanding (A. S. Pringle-Pattison, abridged and ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1689/1983). A letter concerning toleration. In J. Tully (Ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690/1960). Two treatises of government. Introduction and Notes by Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1693/1996). Some thoughts concerning education & of the conduct of the understanding. In R. W. Grant & N. Tarcov (Eds.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1695/1999). The reasonableness of Christianity as delivered in the scriptures (J. C. Higgins-Biddle, ed. and introduction). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1872/1911). The history and root of the principle of the conservation of energy. Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1886/1986). On instruction in the classics and the sciences. In Popular scientific lectures (pp. 338–374). La Salle: Open Court Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1972). Concepts of science education: A philosophical analysis. New York: Scott, Foresman & Co. (Reprint, University Press of America, 1985)

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1974). The relevance of philosophy of science for science education. Boston Studies in Philosophy of Science, 32, 293–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1992). History, philosophy and science teaching: The present rapprochement. Science & Education, 1(1), 11–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1994). Science teaching: The role of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1998). In defense of modest goals for teaching about the nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 35(2), 161–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2000). Time for science education: How teaching the history and philosophy of pendulum motion can contribute to science literacy. New York: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (Ed.). (2009). Science, worldviews and education. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F. (Ed.). (1998). The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F., & Olson, J. K. (1998). The nature of science in international science education standards documents. In W. F. McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies (pp. 41–52). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meehl, P., & MacCorquodale, K. (1948). On a distinction between hypothetical constructs and intervening variables. Psychological Review, 55, 95–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic, rationcinative and inductive, being a connected view of the methods of scientific investigation. London: Longmans, Green & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanda, M. (2003). Prophets facing backward. Postmodern critiques of science and Hindu nationalism in India. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council (NRC). (1996). National science education standards. Washington: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham, J., & Ling, W. (1954–65). Science and civilisation in China (Vols. 1–4). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1713/1934). Principia mathematica (2nd ed.) (F. Cajori, Trans.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. (First Edition, 1687.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1730/1979). Opticks or a treatise of the reflections, refractions, inflections & colours of light. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R., & Irzik, G. (2006). Philosophy, science, education and culture. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, L. (1980). The structure of idealization. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennock, R. T. (2011). Can’t philosophers tell the difference between science and religion? Demarcation revisited. Synthese, 178(2), 177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1953/1963). A note on Berkeley as a Precursor of Mach and Einstein. In K. R. Popper (Ed.), Conjectures and refutations (pp. 166–174). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, R. (2000). The enlightenment: Britain and the creation of the modern world. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. T. (1968). The nature of science and science teaching. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudge, D. W., & Howe, E. M. (2010). Wither the VNOS?. Paper presented at the First IHPST Latin America Regional Conference, Maresias Beach.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford, F. J. (1972). A humanistic approach to science teaching. National Association of Secondary School Principals Bulletin, 56(361), 53–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwab, J. J. (1949). The nature of scientific knowledge as related to liberal education. Journal of General Education, 3, 245–266. Reproduced in I. Westbury & N. J. Wilkof. (Eds.). (1978). Joseph J. Schwab: Science, curriculum, and liberal education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwab, J. J. (1958). The teaching of science as inquiry. Bulletin of Atomic Scientists, 14, 374–379. Reprinted in J. J. Schwab & P.F. Brandwein. (Eds.). (1960). The teaching of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, R., & Lederman, N. (2008). What scientists say: Scientists’ views of nature of science and relation to science context. International Journal of Science Education, 30(6), 727–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinbank, E., & Taylor, J. (Eds.). (2007). Perspectives on science: The history, philosophy and ethics of science. Harlow, Essex: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, S. H. (2003). Molecules: New philosophical perspectives on chemistry. Philosophy of Science, 70, 383–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westaway, F. W. (1919/1937). Scientific method: Its philosophical basis and its modes of application (5th ed.). New York; Hillman-Curl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westaway, F. W. (1929). Science teaching. London: Blackie and Son.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1837). History of the inductive sciences, from the earliest to the present time (3 vols). London: J. W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1840). Philosophy of the inductive sciences, founded upon their history. London: J. W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1849). On induction, with especial reference to Mr. J. Mill’s system of logic. London: J. W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1854). On the influence of the history of science upon intellectual education. Lectures on education delivered at the royal institution on Great Britain. London: J. W. Parker and Son.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeo, R. R. (1993). Defining science: William Whewell, natural knowledge and public debate in early Victorian Britain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael R. Matthews .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Matthews, M.R. (2012). Changing the Focus: From Nature of Science (NOS) to Features of Science (FOS). In: Khine, M. (eds) Advances in Nature of Science Research. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2457-0_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics