Skip to main content
Log in

The many conditions under which monopolistic advertising can differ from the social optimum

  • Published:
Journal of Economics and Finance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper takes a new approach to a classical question about the relationship of monopolistic behavior to the social optimum when advertising is admitted. By characterizing conditions in terms of consumer preferences and using an uncommon approach to comparative static analysis, we derive a general result that produces a dozen special cases of interest. We also show that a plausible preference specification is general enough to generate each of these cases. The specification is amenable to estimation and inference with common data, although empirical application is beyond the scope of this paper. Results are derived assuming that advertising follows the complementary rather than persuasive advertising paradigm where consumers have stable quasilinear preferences and the amount of advertising is seller-determined rather than offered at a unit price to consumers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See the Handbook survey by Bagwell (2007) for a complete exposition and comparison of the persuasive, informative, and complementary paradigms by which the advertising literature is typically segmented.

  2. Additivity of advertising effects, u qa  = 0, implies that advertising does not affect optimal consumption and thus precludes both complementarity and substitution of advertising with consumption of the advertised good.

  3. The notation u qa q(q *,0) denotes evaluation of both u qa and q at q = q * and a = 0.

  4. The notation u a (q *,0) denotes evaluation of u a at q = q * and a = 0.

  5. For example, suppose dq/ = δ i X i at points θ = θ i  = i/n, i = 1,…,n. Then E(X) = Σ n i = 1 δ i X i /Σ n j = 1 δ j may be regarded as a weighted average of the X i ’s with normalized weights δ i /Σ n j = 1 δ j at corresponding θ i ’s. Letting n → ∞, the numerator of E(X) in (12) becomes an exact measure of the change in q if X = dq/ in (10), or the change in a if X = da/ in (11). The qualitative results of Proposition 2 follow because the denominator is positive by second-order conditions.

  6. In this case, the advertising incentive is adequate given the output level, but output is restricted below the social optimum because the product is over-priced by a monopoly.

  7. Note that u qq is weak and ω qq is strong in (11) when demand is highly elastic and marginal cost is steeply increasing.

  8. For simplicity, we do not formally treat the case where a consumer finds out after consumption purchases that a good was misrepresented so that the utility derived from consumption is less than expected.

  9. In this case, the monopolistic case of profit-maximization complements holds according to Definition 6 at θ = 1. For convenience, we assume in this section that θu qqa q + u qa holds for all θ ∈ [0,1] if u qqa q + u qa  > 0, i.e., that u qa  > −θu qqa q for θ < 1 if this inequality holds at θ = 1. We regard this as a fairly weak assumption because this only depends on variation of q between q m and q w . A similar qualification applies to profit-maximization substitutes.

  10. The possibility that a seller can endogenously exercise control over the rotation of a demand curve by choice of the form of advertising has been considered in very different contexts by Johnson and Myatt (2006) and Aislabie and Tisdell (1988), but to our knowledge these conditions have not been examined to delineate comparative static implications. Aislabie and Tisdell (1988) consider the potential private gains when a seller can choose to rotate a linear industry demand curve costlessly at the existing price. Johnson and Myatt (2006) consider a very different but better motivated framework where each consumer either buys or does not buy one unit of the product and producer alteration of the distribution of heterogeneous product characteristics can change the rotation of the demand curve by altering the distribution of purchase likelihoods among consumers. In contrast, the primary focus of this paper is on (e.g., agricultural) markets for divisible homogeneous goods so our model is essentially unrelated.

  11. Assuming c qq  > 0, u q  > 0 requires μ > μ 1 ≡ −(φa β q 1–αλγq γα a)/α, and u qq  < 0 requires μ > μ 2 ≡ −λγ(γ – 1)q γ–α a/[α(α – 1)], and u qqq q + 2u qq c qq  < 0 requires μ > μ 3 ≡ −λγ 2(γ – 1)q γ–α a/[α 2(α – 1)]. Jointly, these conditions require μ > max{μ 1, μ 2, μ 3}, which can alternatively define a joint upper bound on q and a for the feasible choice set such that u aa  < 0 and u qaa  < 0 if (β – 1)τq/a < 0. Additionally, a likely nonbinding constraint is μ > − c qq  < 0.

  12. Because u aa  = φβ(β – 1)a β−2 q < 0 and u qaa q = φβ(β – 1)a β–2 q < 0, both conditions impose the same parameter constraint, φβ(β – 1) < 0. Note, however, that the additional cross second-order conditions in Assumptions 2 and 3 [(u qq – c qq )u aa – u 2 qa > 0 and π qq π aa – π 2 qa > 0] may further restrict the joint parameter-variable space.

  13. For more general cases, the factor ½ can be changed to some other constant in the unit interval to prove a similar result by analogy.

  14. Another set of possibilities for Corollary 6 is the case where −1 < γ < 0 and τq > γ(γ + 1)/[γ(γ + 1) – 2] > 0, and max{0, (1 – τq)q –γ} < λ < −2τq 1– γ/γ(γ + 1), which requires φ and β to be of the same sign.

  15. Another set of possibilities for Corollary 12 is the case where 0 < γ < 1, 0 < (1 – τq)q –γ/γ < λ < −2τq 1– γ/γ(γ + 1), and τq < (γ + 1)/(γ – 1) < 0, which requires φ and β to be of opposite signs.

References

  • Aislabie CJ, Tisdell CA (1988) Profit maximization and marketing strategies: demand rotation and social influences. Manag Decis Econ 9:77–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagwell K (2007) The economic analysis of advertising. In: Armstrong M, Porter RH (eds) Handbook of industrial organization, vol 3. North Holland, Amsterdam, pp 1701–1844

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS, Murphy KM (1993) A simple theory of advertising as a good or bad. Q J Econ 108:941–964

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD, Rangel A (2009) Beyond revealed preference: choice theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Q J Econ 124:51–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bockstael NE, McConnell KE (1983) Welfare measurement in the household production framework. Am Econ Rev 73:806–814

    Google Scholar 

  • Bresnahan TF (1989) Empirical studies of industries with market power in Handbook of Industrial Organization, Volumn 2. eds: R. Schmalensee and R. Willig, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1011–1057

  • Dixit A, Norman V (1978) Advertising and welfare. Bell J Econ 9:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorfman R, Steiner PO (1954) Optimal advertising and optimal quality. Am Econ Rev 44:826–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson JP, Myatt DP (2006) On the simple economics of advertising, marketing, and product design. Am Econ Rev 96:756–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Just RE (2011) Behavior, robustness and sufficient statistics in welfare measurement. Ann Rev Resour Econ 3:37–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Just RE, Chern WS (1980) Tomatoes, technology, and oligopsony. Bell J Econ 11:584–602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor NV (1950) The economic aspects of advertising. Rev Econ Studies 18:1–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kőszegi B, Rabin M (2008) Revealed mistakes and revealed preferences. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) In the foundations of positive and normative economics. Oxford Univ. Press, New York, pp 193–209

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom P, Shannon C (1994) Monotone comparative statics. Econometrica 62:157–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols LM (1985) Advertising and economic welfare. Am Econ Rev 75:213–218

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler GJ, Becker GS (1977) De gustibus non est disputandum. Am Econ Rev 67:76–90

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rulon D. Pope.

Appendix

Appendix

This appendix demonstrates the possibility of each of the conditions in this paper using the specific utility specification u(q,a) = q α + φa β q + λq γ a assuming μ is sufficiently large and φβ(β – 1) < 0 as required for Assumptions 1–3. Our intent is merely to show that the results of each corollary can be generated by some set of feasible conditions, rather than to determine all possible conditions that generate each corollary. We first note that monopoly advertising occurs (or not) as u qa q = τq + λγq γ > (≤) 1 which requires λγ > (≤) (1 – τq)q –γ. Advertising occurs (or not) at the social optimum as u a = τq + λq γ > (≤) 1, which requires λ > (≤) (1 – τq)q –γ. For Corollaries 1–12, advertising by both a monopoly and the social optimum requires min{λ, λγ} > (1 – τq)q –γ. For Proposition 3, advertising by a monopoly but not at the social optimum requires λ ≤ (1 – τq)q –γ < λγ. For Proposition 4, advertising at the social optimum without advertising by a monopoly requires λγ ≤ (1 – τq)q –γ < λ. For brevity of presentation, we define τ = φβa β-1 where sign(τ) = sign(φβ).

Except where explicitly indicated otherwise, the possibilities we demonstrate for Corollaries 1–12 assume the standard conditions 0 < α < 1, 0 < β < 1, 0 ≤ γ ≤ 1, φ ≥ 0, and that μ is sufficiently positive so that second-order conditions hold. For Corollary 1, u qa qu a  < 0 if (γ – 1)λ < 0 and u qqa q + u qa  > 0 if λγ 2 > −τq 1– γ. These conditions and those for advertising by both regimes are satisfied if λ > min{0, (1 – τq)q –γ/γ}, among other possibilities. Corollary 2 holds if u qa qu a  = 0, which requires (γ – 1)λ = 0, and u qqa q + u qa  > 0, which requires λγ 2 > −τq 1– γ, which together with conditions for advertising by both regimes are satisfied by γ = 1 and λ > min{0, q −1τ}, among other possibilities. Corollary 3 holds if u qa qu a  > 0, which requires (γ – 1)λ > 0, and u qq q = α(α – 1)q α–1 + λγ(γ – 1)q γ–1 a ≈ 0, which together with conditions for advertising by both regimes hold if γ > 1, α,γ → 1, and λ > min{0, (1 – τ)q –γ}. Compared to Corollary 3, Corollary 4 only requires confining γ to the unit interval to satisfy u qa qu a  < 0, which changes the dominating constraint required for both regimes to advertise, and is satisfied by 0 < γ < 1, α,γ → 1, and λ > min{0, (1 – τ)γ −1 q –γ}. Corollary 5 requires u qa qu a  > 0, i.e., (γ – 1)λ > 0, and that ω qq  = θ(u qqq q + u qq ) + u qq – c qq  = α 2(α – 1)μq α–2 + λγ 2(γ – 1)q γ–2 ac qq is large negatively relative to u qq  = α(α – 1)μq α–2 + λγ(γ – 1)q γ–2 a, which together with conditions for advertising by both regimes hold if γ > 1, α,γ → 1 so that u qq /c qq  0 assuming c qq is bounded away from zero, and λ > (1 – τ)/q γ.

Corollary 6 includes the condition that u qqa q + u qa  ≪ 0 meaning that u qqa is sufficiently negative that negative cases of θu qqa q + u qa (where θ is large) dominate the positive cases (where θ is small) so that E[u qq q(θu qqa q + u qa )] > 0. To verify the possibility of this case, we assume that u qq q and δ are approximately constant on θ ∈ [0,1] so that E(θu qqa q + u qa ) < 0 holds if ½u qqa q + u qa  < 0.Footnote 13 Then Corollary 6 holds if u qa qu a  > 0, i.e., (γ – 1)λ > 0, and ½u qqa q + u qa  < 0 if λγ(γ + 1) < −2τq 1– γ. If the first condition is satisfied by γ > 1 and λ > 0, then the latter condition together with advertising by both regimes requires (1 – τq)q –γ < λ < −2τq 1– γ/γ(γ + 1), which is possible if τq = φβa β-1 q > γ(γ + 1)/[γ(γ + 1) – 2] > 0. Thus, Corollary 6 holds if γ > 1, max{0, (1 – τq)q –γ} < λ < −2τq 1– γ/γ(γ + 1), and φβa β-1 q > γ(γ + 1)/[γ(γ + 1) – 2], which implies that β and φ are either both positive or both negative.Footnote 14 This is a stringent set of conditions and may not be possible for every set of parameter choices, but these results demonstrate that the possibility can arise.

Turning to the corollaries regarding quantity effects, the conditions of Corollaries 7 and 9 are identical to Corollaries 1 and 3, respectively, so no further demonstration is required. Further, Corollary 8 simply drops one of the requirements of Corollary 2 so trivially it applies under the conditions of Corollary 2. For Corollary 10, ω aa  = θu qaa q + (1 – θ)u aa  = θφβ(β – 1)a β–2 q + (1 – θ)φβ(β – 1)a β−2 q → 0 if β → 1, u qqa q + u qa  > 0 if γ > 1 and λ > 0, and u qqa q + u qa  > 0 if λγ 2 > − τq 1– γ. These conditions and conditions for advertising under both regimes hold if γ > 1, β → 1, and λ > min{0,(1 – τ)/q γ}. For Corollary 11, γ > 1, α,γ → 1, and λ > min{0,(1 – τ)/q γ} imply u qqa q + u qa  > 0, λγ 2 > − τq 1– γ, and u qa qu a  > 0, which satisfy the conditions for advertising by both regimes. For Corollary 12, u qa qu a  < 0 can be satisfied by γ > 1 and λ < 0, which implies that conditions for both regimes to advertise require 0 > λγ > (1 – τq)q –γ. Then under the same illustrative approach as used for Corollary 6, ½u qqa q + u qa  < 0 follows from λγ(γ + 1) < −2τq 1– γ, which is equivalent to λ > −2τq 1– γ/γ(γ + 1). These constraints leave a non-empty set of possibilities for λ if (1 – τq) < −2τq/(γ + 1), which holds if τq > (γ + 1)/(γ – 1) > 0. Jointly, these conditions are satisfied by γ > 1, 0 > λ > (1 – τq)q –γ/γ, and φβa β-1 q = τq > (γ + 1)/(γ – 1) > 0, which implies that β and φ are either both positive or both negative.Footnote 15

For Corollary 14, u qqa  = λγ(λ – 1)q γ–2 = 0 if λ = 1, u qq q → 0 if α,γ → 1, and advertising by a monopoly without advertising at the social optimum holds if (1 – τq)q –γ/γ < λ ≤ (1 – τq)q –γ, which includes λ = 1 if γ > 1 and 0 < τq < 1 (e.g., under small positive values of φ and β), which also satisfies u qa = τ + λγq γ–1 u qqa = λγ(γ – 1)q γ–2 > 0. Corollary 15 is verified similarly by relaxing the λ = 1 requirement because u qqa q + u qa = τ + λγ 2 q γ–1 > 0 if λγ 2 > − τq 1– γ, which is a redundant requirement if λ > 0. The possibility of conditions for Corollary 16 is verified as for Corollary 12 except that advertising by a monopoly without advertising at the social optimum with profit-maximization substitutes requires (1 – τq)q –γ/γ < λ < min{(1 – τq)q –γ, −2τq 1– γ/[γ(γ + 1)]}, which requires 0 < γ < 1 rather than γ > 1, which in turn means that (1 – τq)q –γ/γ < −2τq 1– γ/[γ(γ + 1)] requires τq < (γ + 1)/(γ – 1), i.e., either φ < 0 or β < 0.

For Corollary 17, u qqa  = 0 if λ = 1 and u qa > 0 if λγ(γ – 1)q γ–2 > 0. Combining these conditions with the condition that advertising occurs at the social optimum but not by a monopoly requires λ > (1 – τq)q –γ ≥ (1 – τq)q –γ/γ, which applies when −1 < γ < 0. All conditions are satisfied if 0 < τq < 1 (e.g., under small positive values of φ and β) and (1 – τq)q –γ < 1. Corollary 18 is verified similarly by relaxing the λ = 1 requirement because u qqa q + u qa = τ + λγ 2 q γ–1 > 0 if λγ 2 > − τq 1– γ, which is a redundant requirement if λ > 0. The possibility of conditions for Corollary 19 is verified as for Corollary 6 except that advertising at the social optimum but not by a monopoly with profit-maximization substitutes requires (1 – τq)q –γ < λ < min{(1 – τq)q –γ/γ, −2τq 1– γ/[γ(γ + 1)]}, which requires 0 < γ < 1 rather than γ > 1, which in turn means that (1 – τq)q –γ < −2τq 1– γ/[γ(γ + 1)] is satisfied by 0 > τq > (γ + 1)/(γ – 1), i.e., where φ and β are small and have opposite signs.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Just, R.E., Pope, R.D. The many conditions under which monopolistic advertising can differ from the social optimum. J Econ Finan 41, 421–440 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12197-016-9360-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12197-016-9360-z

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation