In his notes on the formation of concepts and on the possibility of nonconceptuality written during the 1970s, Hans Blumenberg (1920–1996), one of the best-known German philosophers of the 20th century, states that “the desire for linguistic definiteness [unambiguity] […] will, as a utopia, no more disappear than Esperanto has.” This longing is “bound to the ideal of mathematics to cover, with the use of a constructive set of instruments, all noncontradictory possibilities.”Footnote 1 (2020, p. 282) Isolated from its context and without any connection to Blumenberg’s writings on metaphors on the one hand, and on nonconceptuality on the other hand, this statement– that mathematical language ideally does not contain (or tolerate) any ambiguity– may be considered to represent a rather simplistic view within the philosophy of mathematics. But can one extract from Blumenberg’s view of nonconceptuality another position toward both mathematical concepts and their emergence?

Considering ‘nonconceptuality’ as a designation for a field of study which deals with encounters with not yet conceptualized events or objects, or even with objects which do not have a place in a given conceptual system, two questions arise: first, how mathematicians deal and have dealt with these kinds of encounters; second, whether such encounters are also a part of the concept itself. To answer these questions, however, one should note that there are two ways of viewing these encounters: the first concerns how nonconceptuality arises in mathematics itself, even though the ‘ideal’ of mathematics is to consider this discipline as being based on nonambiguous definitions, laws of deduction, and theorems, while the second relates to how mathematicians, philosophers, and historians (of mathematics) have discussed unsolved problems, unclear mathematical concepts or configurations, or possibly ambiguous definitions. These two views certainly overlap and relate to each other, but they are not the same: the first deals with (un)ambiguity within mathematics, while the second deals with how such encounters (with what is considered ambiguous or undefined) are discussed. Hence, to follow Corry (1989, 2004), the first view deals with the body of mathematics (or of a mathematical configuration),Footnote 2 whereas the second is concerned with its image.Footnote 3 While this paper will deal mostly with the second view, Corry stresses that the two views cannot be treated separately– that is, encounters with ‘inexistent,’ impossible, or not well-defined mathematical concepts are accompanied by a certain image of the corresponding mathematical configuration, which specifies how those concepts are considered; moreover, discussions of such images usually point toward the emergence of nonconceptuality in the body of the mathematical configuration itself. In this sense, the paper joins and is motivated by the recent studies in the philosophy of mathematics respectively of mathematical practices, which deviate from this ideal of mathematics and stress, as will be elaborated in Sect. 1.3, the semantic indeterminacy, vagueness and ‘open texture’ of mathematical concepts, following later Wittgenstein, Lakatos, and Waismann.

How do metaphors enter the picture? One of the most famous examples of a reaction to such an encounter with a not yet conceptualized object is the story told concerning the alleged rejection by the Pythagoreans of irrational numbers,Footnote 4 metaphorized by drowning in a sea (see Sect. 2.2). Another example would be the slow acceptance of imaginary numbers– first by treating them as ‘mental torture,’ as Gerolamo Cardano called them (Corry, 2015, p. 144), but finally by accepting them as legitimate, and assigning them a symbol of their own: i = √-1. These episodes are well known and well researched. Blumenberg’s theory of metaphors and his view of nonconceptuality allow to examine these and similar events not from a (conceptual) historical point of view but from the point of view of the metaphorical frameworks accompanying these concepts and the histories of the acceptance of these concepts. This approach, as will be shown in Sect. 1.3, is opposed to the one developed by George Lakoff and Rafael E. Núñez, since it does not aim to uncover “where mathematics”– or any other science– “comes from,” to cite the title of Lakoff’s and Núñez’s book.

This paper will therefore deal with how encounters with and discoveries of mathematically impossible or still undefinable objects as well as their conceptualization may be viewed from the perspective of the metaphors, parables, and fables that frame such encounters and concepts, whereby these issues will be considered in relation to metaphorology, Blumenberg’s theory of metaphors. After reviewing Blumenberg’s work on metaphors and his complicated relation to mathematics in Sect. 1.1, I focus in Sect. 1.2 on how his approach to nonconceptuality deals with mathematics and mathematical concepts. Section 1.3 examines other approaches in philosophy of mathematics, which may be related to Blumenberg’s approach: its differences from Lakoff’s and Núñez’s appraoch, and its possible affinities with Friedrich Waismann’s views on the ‘open texture’ of concepts and with later Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics. Section 2 discusses one specific set of metaphors: the complex of nautical and oceanic metaphors and images, such as the shipwreck, the sea, and the coast, as well as certain ‘demonic’ events, such as plagues, floods, and tides, which are sometimes associated with such metaphors. The question that stands at the center of this section concerns the philosophical insights that Blumenberg’s approach to nautical and oceanic metaphors may uncover. The last section, Sect. 3, goes on to examine a specific case study: it looks at Alexandre Grothendieck’s philosophy of mathematical practices and discovery through the lens of Blumenberg’s understanding of nautical-oceanic metaphors. Grothendieck suggests considering these practices as a never-ending series of waves crashing on the shore. An examination of this metaphor hence offers a unique way to reflect on and frame– both philosophically and metaphorically– acts of practicing mathematics, which is further reflected in the concluding Sect. 4.

1 Mathematics between Blumenberg’s metaphorology and nonconceptuality: how to account for mathematical concept formation?

Hans Blumenberg is known for his work in the field of the history and philosophy of ideas, which focuses on the role played by metaphors in the formation of concepts and of images of knowledge.Footnote 5 One of his early starting points is his 1960 text Paradigms for a Metaphorology [Paradigmen zu einer Metaphorologie], which starts with a critique of René Descartes, in which Blumenberg rejects the Cartesian project of developing a language which consists only of clear and distinct concepts,Footnote 6 and in which all figurative elements are eliminated. This rejection leads Blumenberg to an inquiry into the various metaphors to be found in the history of European thought.Footnote 7 This section will briefly review Blumenberg’s metaphorology, mainly examining in Sect. 1.1 his relationship to mathematics and mathematical concepts. Section 1.2 goes on to examine Blumenberg’s later views on nonconceptuality, which point toward a revised understanding of the formation of mathematical concepts. Section 1.3 examines Blumenberg’s reflections on mathematics in the wider context of philosophy of mathematics in the 20th and the 21st centuries.

1.1 Blumenberg’s metaphorology and mathematical concepts

One of Blumenberg’s main claims in Paradigms for a Metaphorology is not only that not every element of language can be reduced to a concept, but that there are also linguistic elements which are necessary for human thought and irreducible to concepts. These elements are later termed ‘absolute metaphors,’ on which I will elaborate below. The investigation of these fundamental metaphors is therefore a part of the investigation of the history of ideas. Blumenberg’s project, called metaphorology, represents an alternative to the history of concepts not so much because it deals primarily with metaphors, whereas the history of concepts deals primarily with concepts, but because it suggests that concepts themselves operate on a metaphorical foundation.Footnote 8 This mode of operation is not to be understood as implying that concepts are a crystallization of metaphors,Footnote 9 but rather that there are fundamental metaphors which guide the emergence and production of concepts.Footnote 10 It is therefore essential to remember that Blumenberg stresses that the (historical) research of concepts and the (historical) research of metaphors, along with their respective philosophical frameworks, are interwoven. The necessity of this interwovenness for our thinking is termed by Blumenberg as a “sad necessity” [“traurige Notwendigkeit”] (Blumenberg, 2020, p. 294), when he cites the opening passages of a letter Georg Jonathan von Holland sent to Johann Heinrich Lambert in 1765: “I think that we owe a large part of our knowledge [Erkenntnis], and an even larger part of our errors, to the development of metaphors.”Footnote 11 (Ibid.) Blumenberg then adds: “Here, everything is said with the fewest possible words: the sad necessity of a makeshift solution leads to the ambiguous excess of a guidance for knowledge on the one hand,”– that is, the guideline of the formation of concepts, “and to a relegation of deception on the other”Footnote 12– implying that perhaps other metaphors will be needed to overcome such future misapprehensions (ibid.). I will return to the 1765 letter below, as it also shows Blumenberg’s complicated relation to mathematics.

To be more explicit, in Paradigms for a Metaphorology, Blumenberg does not formulate a complete theory of metaphor,Footnote 13 but rather discusses numerous examples of metaphors (of light, the machine, the organism, or the circle), and from this discussion emerges a multifaceted definition of the absolute metaphor, whereby, with each example, Blumenberg illuminates only certain aspects.Footnote 14 For Blumenberg, what needs to be addressed is “the fundamental question of the conditions under which metaphors can claim legitimacy in philosophical language. Metaphors can first of all be leftover elements, rudiments on the path from mythos to logos […].” (2010, p. 3) But in opposition to the Cartesian understanding of the metaphor, which ultimately dismisses metaphor as a dispensable tool, Blumenberg presents absolute metaphors, which “can also […] be foundational elements of philosophical language, ‘translations’ [‘Übertragungen’] that resist being converted back into authenticity and logicality.” (Ibid.) These metaphors “prove resistant to terminological claims and cannot be dissolved into conceptuality.” (Ibid., p. 5) Absolute metaphors are not to be taken as a substrate which can be transformed into concepts, but function “as a catalytic sphere from which the universe of concepts continually renews itself, without thereby converting and exhausting this founding reserve.” (Ibid., p. 4) Moreover, these metaphors do not have to be expressed explicitly as metaphors (though they can be), but can remain latent, in the background, when other expressions and modes of articulation draw on the semantic field of these (absolute) metaphors without the metaphors themselves being explicitly stated as such.

Absolute metaphors are therefore metaphors which, by definition, cannot be reduced to concepts or to dead metaphors (such as in the expression ‘footnote’). They rather unfold a dynamic conceptual space which allows the emergence of specific concepts.Footnote 15 Moreover, these concepts themselves, as is already clear from Blumenberg’s reference to Holland’s letter to Lambert, do not necessarily have to follow the Cartesian “ideal of clarity”, but rather have a certain relation to the dynamicity, to “the elasticity of the latitude” of the absolute metaphor (Blumenberg, 2020, p. 262). In this sense, as will be explicated later, also the concept itself, and not just the dynamic space enabling its emergence, “must possess enough indeterminacy [Unbestimmtheit]” (ibid.).Footnote 16

As noted, Blumenberg’s rejection of the Cartesian project consists in a rejection of a conception of a language which is cleansed and devoid of any residue of metaphorical language, and this rejection may also be considered as implicitly articulating a suspicion against mathematics’ claim to be the (only) adequate language for all domains of the natural sciences, that is, the only language which allows one to ‘read the book of nature.’Footnote 17 If mathematical concepts are (or should be) understood as well defined and unambiguous, then this understanding of mathematical language follows the Cartesian project. Mathematics can be thought of as providing this security to language, since by means of mathematics– at least according to the analytical conception of mathematics– everything can be reduced in theory to logical terms and relations, following what Blumenberg calls the “Cartesian teleology of logicization” (2010, p. 3);Footnote 18 such a reduction does not allow an ‘elastic space’ of interpretation of concepts. That this conception of security in mathematics is already expressed by Descartes himself can be seen in his Discours de la méthode, published in 1637: “I was especially delighted with the mathematics, on account of the certitude and evidence of their reasonings; but I had not as yet a precise knowledge of their true use; and thinking that they but contributed to the advancement of the mechanical arts, I was astonished that foundations, so strong and solid, should have had no loftier superstructure reared on them. On the other hand, I compared the disquisitions of the ancient moralists to very towering and magnificent palaces with no better foundation than sand and mud.” (1951, p. 6)

In this passage Descartes not only stresses the security mathematics provides, but he also employs architecture as an image of knowledge. That is, Descartes interlaces claims about the body of mathematics and the image of mathematics. He sees himself as an architect whose role is to rebuild secure and safe foundations for science.Footnote 19 How geometry is constructed is an important issue for Descartes. After being asked to set out his arguments in a geometrical fashion, he presents in an appendix to the sixth meditation of his Meditations on First Philosophy a ‘geometrical’ exposition of some of his central lines of argument, organized as definitions, postulates, axioms or common notions, and propositions (Descartes, 1904, pp. 160–170).

However, that Descartes uses architectural images and metaphors to present his ideas,Footnote 20 is not noted by Blumenberg. When, in his book The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, Blumenberg notes that Descartes sees logic and mathematics as that which guarantees certainty,Footnote 21 he considers Descartes’ theory without the accompanying metaphorical images, and sees the Cartesian project only through the lens of the explicit aim of eliminating metaphors or of reducing them to logic and mathematics. Geometry plays a double role for Descartes– as a guiding architectural image and as a domain of unshakable knowledge, though one which may be expanded and revised (as seen in Descartes’ La Géométrie).Footnote 22 This double role of geometry enables Descartes to employ this metaphor both as rhetoric and as that which prompts the emergence of new knowledge; but this double role is not mentioned in the short reference to Descartes in the introduction to Blumenberg’s 1960 text Paradigms for a Metaphorology.

Here, it is already instructive to approach the question of how Blumenberg considers mathematics and its history. Blumenberg’s relation to these subjects is rather difficult to reconstruct, since a detailed discussion on the history or philosophy of mathematics is not to be found in his (published) writings.Footnote 23 A possible reason for this may be that for Blumenberg, as noted above, mathematics might be considered as fulfilling (or at least attempting to fulfill) the Cartesian project. Nevertheless, one may still extract from Blumenberg’s writings a rather convoluted approach regarding mathematics: Blumenberg is aware of its role for the development of modern science, but he ignores its many metaphorical frameworks, except for specific cases. This focus on specific cases can be seen in several of Blumenberg’s writings in which he discusses the ways in which metaphors are tolerated within mathematics; this can be seen, for example, in Paradigms for a Metaphorology. Two chapters of this book deal directly with mathematical concepts or with metaphors coming from mathematics: Chapter VIII (“Terminologization of a Metaphor: From ‘Verisimilitude’ to ‘Probability’”Footnote 24) discusses the “transitions from metaphors to concepts” (2010, p. 81), explicitly analyzing how the mathematical concept of probability emerged. Chapter X (“Geometric Symbolism and Metaphorics”) considers the transition from geometrical symbols to metaphors through a discussion of the circle and the sphere.

Blumenberg’s emphasis on the role of mathematics in the early modern period is noted when he underlines that the mathematization of nature was a criterion for this period’s efforts to find “a set of instruments for man that would be usable in any possible world” (Blumenberg, 1983, p. 164).Footnote 25 But as he notes, while this set of instruments was thought in this period to reach the “naked truth,”Footnote 26 it was exactly this nakedness that was later criticized by Husserl as deceptive, being only a “well-fitting garb of ideas.”Footnote 27 This transformation of the metaphor of clothes and clothing, of covering, uncovering, and revealing shows that the metaphors used to illustrate the role and importance of mathematics change over time. This again might be one of the few examples of Blumenberg which discusses the changing metaphors within the history of mathematics.Footnote 28

Yet, as already noted in relation to his discussion on Descartes, the ways in which mathematical concepts function and operate, and especially how this mode of operation and emergence is framed metaphorically, is rarely discussed explicitly by Blumenberg; the episodes from the history of mathematics which he does discuss (as examined above) are brought up less to explicate the formation of mathematical concepts than to elucidate other domains, such as Blumenberg’s claims about the history of metaphors. The choice to ignore the role of metaphors in the formation of mathematical concepts can be noted in two examples from Blumenberg’s own writings.

The first can be found in the abovementioned letter from Holland to Lambert, where, according to Blumenberg, “everything is said with the fewest possible words […] [concerning the] sad necessity” of metaphors (Blumenberg, 2020, p. 294). But if one continues reading the letter, Holland discusses misapprehensions and errors which mainly arise in mathematics. In fact, the first topic Holland presents in this letter is a discussion on possible differences between the “symbolic Nothing [symbolische[ ] Nichts]” and the “conceivable Nothing [gedenkbare[ ] Nichts]” (Lambert, 1782, p. 40), a subject which one would have thought might be relevant to Blumenberg’s views of the concept. The first example Holland provides is the square root of (-1)– that is, √-1– as a case in which the two types of Nothing coincide (ibid., p. 41). Other examples, such as the differential or limits of fractions (when both denominator and numerator converge to zero) are also discussed.Footnote 29 These examples of concepts whose mathematical status was at that time ambiguous and unclear, though they are presented immediately after Holland’s statement on the necessity of metaphors, are, however, not mentioned by Blumenberg.

The second example of Blumenberg’s failure to consider this issue is the absence in his writings of any discussion of the crises of mathematics at the end of the 19th century and the beginning of the 20th century (for example, the Grundlagenkrise or the crisis of Anschauung), even though he does underline that the “tendency of formalization” starting in the early modern period, prompted by the usage of “mathematical means of representation,” leads first to an “arithmetization of geometry,” then to its “algebraization,” and eventually to a “purely empty set theory [‘Mannigfaltigkeitkslehre’]” (Blumenberg, 1981, pp. 30–31). While Blumenberg is aware of the Grundlagenkrise, implicitly referring to it when citing Hilbert’s phrase that “from the paradise [of set theory], that Cantor created for us, no one shall be able to expel us” (Hilbert, 1926, p. 170; see: Blumenberg, 1989, p. 789),Footnote 30 the absence of a more detailed discussion is somewhat surprising, since in several of his writings Blumenberg sets out to delineate a number of encounters with nonconceptuality, encounters which are also present in mathematics and may be detected clearly in the abovementioned crises of mathematics. At the same time, Blumenberg does explicate the relation between nonconceptuality and mathematics, which makes it somewhat surprising that he hardly deals with how mathematics and its concepts operate. Here, I would like to return to Blumenberg’s philosophical conception of mathematical encounters with the nonconceptualized, as presented at the beginning of the paper, in order to show how, despite the above, it is still possible to account for the formation of mathematical concepts using Blumenberg’s metaphorology.

1.2 Blumenberg’s nonconceptuality and mathematical concepts

A discussion on nonconceptuality [Unbegrifflichkeit] is already found in Blumenberg’s writings in 1960, when he describes the relationship between absolute metaphor and nonconceptuality in the following way: “the function of ‘absolute metaphor’ [is that it] springs into a nonconceptualizable, conceptually unfillable gap and lacuna […].” (2010, p. 122) In 1979, in “Prospect for a Theory of Nonconceptuality,” in which Blumenberg reframes his conception of metaphorology, he notes that “metaphorology’s function has not changed, but its referent has, primarily in that metaphorics is now understood as merely a limited special case of nonconceptuality.” (1997, p. 81) That is, as Paul Fleming stresses, nonconceptuality also includes “myth, gloss, example, anecdote, etc.” as other forms which may “spring” into this “unfillable gap.” (Fleming, 2012, p. 25) Moreover, in 2007, the notes Blumenberg had made on the concept of nonconceptuality during the 1970s were published,Footnote 31 notes in which he stresses the operativeness of nonconceptuality. These notes begin by remarking that “concepts developed from the actio per distans, from action across spatial and temporal distance.”Footnote 32 (Blumenberg, 2020, p. 261), and that the concept is “an action in […] absence” (ibid., p. 263). This is because the object, which we should touch, see, or sense, is missing– and the concept comes as a replacement and a representation of the lack of tangibility caused due to the distance from the object. Hence, Blumenberg designates the concept as “a trap” (ibid., p. 260). And, yet again, Blumenberg expresses his critique of the Cartesian conception of the concept, according to which concepts should be clear and distinct (ibid., p. 261). The interest here, to emphasize, does not lie in concepts; as with metaphorology, the goal is not necessarily to inquire into how concepts are formed. Nevertheless, as we will see later, Blumenberg does delineate a possibility to think on an essentially indeterminate conceptual system. Returning to nonconceptuality, it “is less concerned with the ‘what’ or even the ‘how’ of thinking (i.e., its relation to concept formation, though this is certainly also the case).” (Fleming, 2012, p. 25) Here, Fleming notes that “what a theory of nonconceptuality attempts to outline” is a “horizon of thinking, where knowledge is tied to disappointment”Footnote 33 (ibid.), that is, where thinking encounters boundaries. This gives rise to the question of where one may hope that such a disappointment would not be encountered; and a possible answer given by Blumenberg refers to two domains: a legal one and a mathematical one.

By also explicating the relations between metaphor and concept, Blumenberg clarifies to some extent his position toward mathematics. A metaphor appears when “the determination of the context is weak enough. In a legal text […] the metaphor becomes impossible.”Footnote 34 (Blumenberg, 2007, p. 61) According to Blumenberg, if a system (such as a system of laws) is understood as a system of unambiguous, precisely determined concepts, then mathematics would also have to be imagined as a field in which metaphors are impossible.Footnote 35 Blumenberg explicitly addresses this idea with the statement quoted in the introduction to this paper, according to which the longing for linguistic definiteness is “bound to the ideal of mathematics.” (2020, p. 282) It seems, moreover, that Blumenberg here is following Kant, since, a few passages before the above statement, he quotes a footnote from Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: “In mathematics definitions belong ad esse, in philosophy ad melius esse. Attaining them is fine, but often very difficult. Jurists are still searching for a definition of their concept of right.”Footnote 36 (Ibid., p. 281) What Blumenberg does not cite, but he may very well have agreed with it, is the statement by Kant which comes almost immediately after the statement which is cited by Blumenberg: “Mathematical definitions can never err. For since [in mathematics] the concept is first given through the definition, it contains just that which the definition would think through it.” (Kant, 1998, A731/B759)Footnote 37

The possibility of never being mistaken corresponds to the longing for linguistic unambiguity, which is in turn bound to the “ideal of mathematics.” Accordingly, one may interpret Blumenberg’s position as claiming that the semantic clarity of mathematical definitions vouches for the reliability of the mathematical procedure.Footnote 38 It is essential to note here that he underlines that this is an “ideal,” which may imply that even mathematics and mathematical concepts never reach this state, and hence this never-ending process may emphasize the historicity of mathematics. I will elaborate on this position in Sect. 2.1, since Blumenberg himself stresses that even in mathematics, there might be essential incompleteness, in the sense that it can (or should) be again and again reconstructed. This ideal but unreachable state may be seen in the following statement by Blumenberg on the relation between concept and nonconceptuality: “for the benefit of concepts, there has to be a preliminary field [forefield; Vorfeld] of nonconceivability [incomprehensibility; Unbegreiflichkeit], even if, under the criteria of the possible perfected concept, one were inclined to cross this field disparagingly and let it be altogether forgotten in the state of perfection.”Footnote 39 (Blumenberg, 2020, p. 281) This statement may open a way of thinking about mathematical nonconceptuality, or at least about the ‘forefield’ of incomprehensibility and nonconceivability, before but also during the emergence and formation of mathematical concepts. First, Blumenberg’s sarcastic tone concerning the disparaging crossing of the field implies that such a state of completion is not really possible. Second, immediately after the passage cited above, Blumenberg warns us not to consider “nonconceptuality in the service of concepts” [“Die Unbegrifflichkeit im Dienst des Begriffs”] as a “mere philosophical auxiliary discipline [Hilfswissenschaft],” (ibid.) but rather to note that the work in this forefield “of concepts does not arrive at its goal.”Footnote 40 (Ibid., p. 282) It thus becomes clear that between the ‘solid’ concept and its forefield of incomprehensibility there is a tension (and certainly not a smooth transition), since it is impossible to know when one has ‘successfully’ defined the concept (being the “goal” mentioned above) without any exceptions or ‘holes’. This is since not only are both entities (the forefield and the full-fledged concept) are interwoven, but also a transition from one to the other is practically impossible; nonconceptuality should not be seen in the service of the production of well-defined concepts.Footnote 41 It is hence no wonder that Blumenberg compares the concept to a “fishing net,” as it represents the tolerance between the accuracy and imprecision, between “exactness and inexactness of its reference object that can only be created by way of concepts.”Footnote 42 (Ibid., p. 263) That is, “[i]n principle, a concept must be definable” (ibid., p. 271), but in practice it also lets the absence on which it is founded be present as such. Or, to formulate it more concretely, the holes in the ‘fishing net’ are also present when the concept is defined. This is how nonconceptuality is present, a presence which– to return to the beginning of this subsection– can be accounted for, among other things, by metaphors.

If we return to Blumenberg’s statement about the forefield of incomprehensibility, and how one would like to leave it in order to define, at least in theory, clear and distinct concepts,Footnote 43 one may claim that the history of mathematics can show almost the opposite of this ‘ideal’ state: that some mathematical concepts were or will be ambiguous and unclear, and that their emergence, conception, and coining were (or will be) accompanied by metaphors and fables. Before showing how discussions on mathematical concepts and their emergence have been and are accompanied and framed by such metaphors, I would like to take a step back and examine Blumenberg’s reflections on metaphorology in the wider context of the 20th and 21st century philosophy of mathematics.

1.3 Metaphors, nonconceptuality and indeterminacy of mathematics in context

First, it is important to note that the immediate context of Blumenberg’s 1960 paper on metaphorology is to be found on the backdrop of the emerging field of Begriffsgeschichte (back then developed by Erich Rothacker, Otto Brunner and Reinhart Koselleck) during these years in Germany. Invited to write to the journal Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte, with the intention that he would contribute to the field of Begriffsgeschichte, Blumenberg explicitly goes against any possibility of writing such a history of concepts, at least if one does not consider the essential role of metaphors. Moreover, as can be noted above, Blumenberg’s critique on the 20th century analytic philosophy is clear, if one considers it as a logical analysis of concepts and their usages. Indeed, in the wider context of philosophy of mathematics and of the sciences of the first half of the 20th century, Blumenberg’s metaphorology criticizes analytic philosophy and logical positivism; he underlines the limits of the philosophy of Karl Popper (and also of Alfred Ayer), stressing that metaphors “do not admit of verification, and that the alternative already decided in them […] theoretically undecidable. Metaphors are unable to satisfy the requirement that truth, by definition, be the result of a methodologically secure procedure of verification.” (2010, pp. 13–14)Footnote 44

Moving forward to the late 20th century and the first decades of the 21st century, Blumenberg’s research on metaphors and their historical frameworks can be considered as opposed to the metaphor theory developed by George Lakoff and Mark Johnson in the 1980s, and developed further in the context of mathematics by Lakoff and Rafael E. Núñez (2000) in their book Where Mathematics Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being. According to Lakoff and Núñez’s approach (which is informed mainly by cognitive science), human conceptual thinking, and hence also mathematics, are framed by metaphors drawn from our embodied experience, whereas metaphors are defined as a universal cognitive mechanism and as an “inference-preserving cross-domain mapping” (Lakoff & Núñez, 2000, p. 6). While this approach has considerable explanatory power, its very strength can also be a weakness, namely the temptation to reduce all metaphors to the body or to ‘embodiment.’ This is clearly expressed in the preface of the book: “Abstract human ideas make use of precisely formulatable cognitive mechanisms such as conceptual metaphors that import modes of reasoning from sensory-motor experience. It is always an empirical question just what human ideas are like, mathematical or not.” (ibid., p. xii) While Lakoff and Núñez stress here that they are discussing “conceptual metaphors,” by emphasizing that the question concerning the nature of “human ideas” (and hence mathematical concepts) is “always an empirical” one, they note that the sensory-motor framework is the only framework they take into consideration. Admittedly, the reference of numerous metaphors to corporal, physical, or embodied (in the world) experience is an aspect which is not taken into account by Blumenberg.Footnote 45 However, despite Johnson and Lakoff’s metaphor theory and despite Lakoff and Núñez’s contribution to the understanding of mathematical metaphors and concepts, one of the main critiques regarding Lakoff and Núñez’s work concerns their ignorance not only of the history of mathematics in particular and the history of ideas in general, but also of the particular way metaphors emerge in mathematics– that is, the way metaphors only acquire their meaning in the specific historical and social context within which and for which they were employed as a metaphor.Footnote 46 The critique of Lassègue (2003, pp. 228-9) is essential to recall: by stressing the universal character of cognitive mechanisms, Lakoff and Núñez carry out a flattening of the various meanings of mathematical statements by always presupposing the univocity of such meaning. In addition, viewing the metaphor as a correspondence (a “mapping”) between two domains, this conception only considers the metaphor as a connection between two already existing domains, domains which moreover must be assumed to exist innately– but such correspondence of domains does not account for the appearance of new concepts.

While Lakoff and Núñez’s approach to mathematical metaphors is highly influential, they do not claim that mathematical concepts may have a dynamic or indeterminate character, a claim which may be deduced from Blumenberg’s position. However, such a claim, it should be emphasized, is not a revolutionary one. To give one example, as already noted, the debates on the status of imaginary numbers– that is, whether they should only be considered as a fictitious auxiliary machinery, mere symbols, or whether they should be accepted as numbers, and not understood as ‘torture’– are well researched. Moreover, that mathematical concepts are dynamic and subject to change, and hence already have a kernel of indeterminacy, has been noted not only by Lakatos (1976) but also by the later Wittgenstein and by Waismann. As Pérez-Escobar (2022, p. 171) shows, “Wittgenstein’s late philosophy of mathematics moves the emphasis away from the foundations of mathematics […] and closer to mathematical practices and ways of living”, when Wittgenstein discusses ‘bending’ of mathematical rules, which may very well point to their indeterminacy (cf. also: Scheppers, 2023). Interestingly enough, Blumenberg knew Wittgenstein’s works on such subjects, as he discusses in (Blumenberg, 1989 p. 757ff) Wittgenstein’s reflections on ‘mathematical’ flies and the discovery of surprising solutions to mathematical problems.Footnote 47 Moreover, recent works, such as those by Tanswell (2018) or Zayton (2022), on whether mathematical concepts can be ‘open textured,’ a notion taken from Waismann (1968),Footnote 48 or whether they can display semantic indeterminacy or be essentially vague,Footnote 49 indicate that this debate certainly should not be philosophically limited to specific case studies such as imaginary numbers or the foundations of set theory, but should encapsulate the entirety of mathematics. In this sense, one may argue that when committing to the thesis that a mathematical concept can be open textured,Footnote 50 one vouches also for the possible existence of a forefield of that concept or, in Waismann’s words, for an “essential incompleteness” of the concept (Waismann, 1968, p. 121).

With these philosophical discussions on the one hand, and with Blumenberg’s own remarks on mathematics on the other hand, the possibility of bringing mathematics and nonconceptuality together may be detected. Hence, following this conception, one can consider mathematics as an elastic, dynamic space that is transformed again and again with every encounter with ‘inexistent’ objects,Footnote 51 which is to say with objects for which a concept is yet to be coined– and this encounter can be unfolded with glosses, anecdotes, and fables, or metaphorically, as underlined above, and for example, with nautical and oceanic metaphors.

2 Nautical metaphors, oceanic metaphors, and histories of mathematics

Before examining these encounters and their accompanying metaphors in more detail, one question should be answered in advance concerning the focus of this paper: why concentrate on nautical and oceanic metaphors, appearing, for example, in the form of the sea and shipwreck when examining the formation of mathematical concepts and theories?

It is clear that other metaphors have been used to describe how mathematics develops– the organic metaphor and the architectural metaphor are well-known examples; see: (Schlimm, 2016; Friedman, 2020, 2022).Footnote 52 Blumenberg himself notes the metaphor of clothing, covering, and uncovering with respect to mathematics, as was mentioned above. But the nautical and oceanic metaphors play a special role in Blumenberg’s examination of the history of metaphors, as can be seen especially in his 1979 book Shipwreck with Spectator; reflections on the components of these metaphors are also to be found in his posthumous publication Quellen, Ströme, Eisberge (2012), which contains essays written in 1980 on the various metaphors of fluidity and of water.Footnote 53 To emphasize: while nautical metaphors point more to the relation of man to the sea, having to do with navigation, boats and their construction, navies, and steering in the sea, oceanic (or marine) metaphors deal with the sea itself, having to do with water and currents, and not necessarily with attempts at controlling them. Thus, Shipwreck with Spectator can be regarded as unfolding mainly an array of nautical metaphors, while Quellen, Ströme, Eisberge unfolds mainly an array of oceanic or marine metaphors.Footnote 54 But this separation is not a strict one, as components of one array can certainly appear in another. In Shipwreck with Spectator, the metaphor of the sea and the shipwreck functions for Blumenberg, as the subtitle of this book suggests, as a “paradigm of a metaphor for existence.” Blumenberg notes: “Humans live their lives and build their institutions on dry land. Nevertheless, they seek to grasp the movement of their existence above all through a metaphorics of the perilous sea voyage.” (1997, p. 7) In this sense, one can consider that Blumenberg viewed transgressions and crises not pejoratively or as something to be appeased, but as an essential part of human existence; this becomes apparent via the nautical metaphors used also in mathematical discourse.

To explicate: Several components of the shipwreck metaphor– the meeting of sea and shore, the stormy sea, the unpredictability of the waves, or the ever-shifting shoreline– refer to an encounter with a frontier or crisis, and in this they may correspond to the way the transformation of mathematics has been perceived, either by the mathematicians contributing to it or by the philosophers and historians describing it. This is not to suggest that the changes undergone by mathematics could not have been approached with other metaphors, as we saw above with Descartes’ architectural metaphor. During the 20th century, mathematics and the changes mathematics underwent were also metaphorized, for example, with the story of the Tower of Babel (see: Friedman, 2021).Footnote 55 As will be shown, however, the numerous nautical and oceanic metaphors that frame the history of mathematics suggest that these are background metaphors to account for such frontier experiences. Moreover, with the sea, a physical place is indicated which has always set limits to the human capacity for sovereignty and action– and it is precisely to the transgression of these limits which some mathematicians refer. That is, the usage of this metaphor to account for and unfold a certain image of mathematics implies an encounter with not yet well-defined mathematical concepts. The following two subsection will elaborate on those metaphors: Sect. 2.1 deals with Blumenberg’s reflections on mathematics in Shipwreck with Spectator, whereas Sect. 2.2 examines other nautical metaphors which account for mathematical crises or concepts.

2.1 Blumenberg on geometrical salvation and mathematical shipwrecks

Blumenberg’s approach to geometry and to mathematical concepts, as presented in Shipwreck with Spectator, consists of two somewhat opposed positions. To begin with the first position, the second chapter of this book deals with geometry and, more precisely, with geometrical figures, through a discussion of the philosopher Aristippus (Blumenberg, 1997, p. 12). Blumenberg cites the following passage in Book VI of Vitruvius’s De architectura: “It is related of the Socratic philosopher Aristippus that, being shipwrecked and cast ashore on the coast of the Rhodians, he observed geometrical figures drawn thereon, and cried out to his companions: ‘Let us be of good cheer, for I see the traces of man.’” (Vitruvius, 1914, p. 167) Blumenberg notes that, “even in the hopeless situation of being shipwrecked on a foreign shore, a philosophically trained person still knows what to do, when he recognizes civilized reason in geometrical diagrams.” (1997, p. 12) These geometrical drawings are associated by Aristippus with a sign of human habitation, civilization, and safety. Geometry itself becomes a safe land. This story is recounted again and again over the centuries as a metaphor of safety, as can be seen in Blumenberg’s own discussion on the 16th century astronomer Joachim Rheticus and the 18th century mathematician Abraham Gotthelf Kästner: both turn the shore in Vitruvius’s historical description into an image of knowledge (ibid., pp. 13–14). As Blumenberg is aware, however, it would be wrong to automatically associate the shore with an image of safety, as this would imply that the shore metaphor does not change and does not have a history.

What arises from Blumenberg’s reading of certain chapters of the history of this metaphor is an image of the human as seeking guidance and protection, whereas the sea is depicted as a place of constant change, or even, in certain epochs, as “the place where evil appears” (ibid., p. 8). But Blumenberg also points out that this metaphor is a story of a search for safe foundations. While one of the characteristics of this metaphor is the demonization of the sea as a lawless place without order, another is its designation of a limit to human activity. This leads me to Blumenberg’s second approach regarding mathematics and especially mathematical concepts, which is also presented in Shipwreck with Spectator, and which underlines how even ‘well-defined’ mathematical concepts themselves may have a kernel of indeterminacy, and in this sense such a stable conceptual system may not be so stable after all. The last chapter of Shipwreck with Spectator deals with various critiques expressed towards logical positivism and whether “the foundation of scientific language is possible” (ibid., p. 76). Blumenberg notes that the critiques of Otto Neurath, and afterwards of Paul Lorenzen, explicitly use ship metaphors: Neurath (1932, p. 206) affirms that “[w]e are like sailors who have to rebuild their ship on the high seas” with no place to dock, hence, so Blumenberg, if conceptual “imprecision is diminished in one place, it may reappear in a stronger form elsewhere.” (Blumenberg, 1997, p. 77) Already this remark underlines the indeterminacy of any conceptual (and hence mathematical) system. Blumenberg then notes that Lorenzen in 1965 takes an “extreme variant of the [ship] metaphor”, by supplementing it with a prehistory– that our ancestors had an initial point of beginning.Footnote 56 Blumenberg suggests at the end of the book that even a scientific language that presents itself as the “philosophical zero point”– and an example for that would be the mathematical set theory, which was considered as the foundation of mathematics– cannot be the promised initial point: it “contains material other than what has already been used. Where can it come from […] Perhaps from earlier shipwrecks?” (ibid., p. 79) Hence, not only Blumenberg doubts the safety that such “philosophical zero point” would gaurantee, but he also doubts the safety that any conceptual construction may ever provide. Following this double approach, I aim in the following to show that several other episodes in the history of mathematics display as well ambivalent and ambiguous positions toward the sea and shipwreck metaphor.

2.2 Nautical metaphors of geometrical disasters?

To begin with a first example, and to see how the metaphor of the sea framed encounters with ‘impossible’ mathematical objects, one can recall the following story. In a legend told by Pappus of Alexandria, Hippasus, who published his discovery of irrationality (or incommensurability), was drowned in the sea precisely because of this discovery:

[in] the sect […] of Pythagoras […] a saying became current in it, namely, that he who first disclosed the knowledge of surds or irrationals and spread it abroad among the common herd, perished by drowning: […] it is better to conceal (or veil) every surd, or irrational, or inconceivable in the universe, […] [since] the soul, which by error or heedlessness discovers or reveals anything of this nature which is in it or in this world, wanders [thereafter] hither and thither on the sea of non-identity […] immersed in the stream of the coming-to-be and the passing away where there is no standard of measurement. (Pappus, 1930, p. 64).

This legend should not be read as a historical account and it should certainly not imply that the Pythagoreans rejected irrational numbers or incommensurable quantities.Footnote 57 Following this legend, Pappus employs several nautical and oceanic expressions and metaphors: the drowning of man, the “sea of non-identity,” the “stream of the coming-to-be.” If one considers these expressions not as mere decorative elements, then Hippasus drowned because he made a controversial claim regarding the body of the mathematical configuration during this epoch: he showed that what exists in geometry cannot exist in the alleged Pythagorean arithmetic– for example, the irrational diagonal of a square. It is essential to emphasize that while one may interpret the above quotation as referring to the philosophical tradition of Heraclitus,Footnote 58 and thus as advocating an ever-present change, this story appears also in more recent accounts.Footnote 59 That is, the fable of drowning in the sea is employed again and again– without even attempting to offer another metaphorical framework– in order to frame a meeting with an object which allegedly had no place in the Pythagorean system.

Another example of how mathematical problems are accounted for with nautical metaphors is the problem of the doubling of the cube. In contrast to Pappus’s description, the following parable, told by Plutarch, presents a different type of description, one in which the problem is posed by an oracle to plague-stricken Delians. In Plutarch’s account, Simmias of Thebes, who was traveling with Plato, recounts a meeting with the inhabitants of the island of Delos on the coast of Caria, when Simmias and Plato were returning home from Egypt:

[…] as we were sailing from Egypt, about [the shores of]Footnote 60 Caria some Delians met us, who desired Plato […] to solve [a problem which] an odd oracle lately delivered […] [namely, the doubling of the cube]. […] They, not comprehending the meaning of the words, after many ridiculous endeavors […] made application to Plato to clear the difficulty. He […] said that the God was merry upon the Greeks, who despised learning; […] it required skill to find the true proportion by which alone a body of a cubic figure can be doubled, all its dimensions being equally increased. (Plutarch, 1878, vol. 2, p. 385)

It is easy to see that the problem of the doubling of the cube is equivalent to constructing two segments whose ratio is 3√2, or just constructing a segment of length 3√2 (given a segment whose length is 1). It is also well known that, if one constructs segments only with straightedge and compass, then constructing a segment whose length is 3√2 is impossible. The impossibility of such a construction was nevertheless only proven during the first half of the 19th century (Wantzel, 1837).Footnote 61

If we return to Plutarch’s account, then one can find there almost all the ingredients of the shipwreck metaphor (voyage across the sea, island, danger in the form of a plague, coast), but they serve a different function than in Pappus’s parable. While one may argue that the elements of the parable do not seem to directly relate to the mathematical problem itself, the problem is nevertheless framed via a metaphorical framework of danger and with nautical metaphors. In this sense, and following Blumenberg, who notes that metaphors do not have to be explicitly expressed as such, I claim that the result of not solving the mathematical problem is metaphorized by a plague which can be only stopped by a passenger of a nautical voyage. In this case, no one drowns in the sea, but it is clear that the story encapsulates a meeting with an object (a doubled cube) whose constructability– at least with straightedge and compass– is not yet known. Moreover, the metaphors employed also unfold a certain image of mathematics as a threatening, ever-changing realm; this image, in its turn, points to the abovementioned meeting. Here, however, one should stress that the construction of a segment of length 3√2 was a problem which was solved numerous times in antiquity, though not with a straightedge and a compass.Footnote 62 Hence, while the problem was not really unsolvable, despite what Plutarch states above,Footnote 63 the encounter with a certain impossibility is nevertheless framed via nautical metaphors.

The above mathematical episodes are not the only ones in which the metaphor of the sea and the shore plays an essential role; there are other episodes in the history of mathematics where the metaphor of nautical voyages and their possible hazardous consequences come into expression. In his book Geometrical Landscapes, Amir Alexander notes that “some early modern mathematicians adopted the imagery of geographical discovery and made it their own.” (2002, p. 2) Alexander deals with several mathematicians, mainly from the 16th and 17th centuries, showing that “the imagery of a mathematics of adventure and exploration went hand in hand with the emergence of infinitesimal methods.” (Ibid., p. 200) While some of the examples discussed by Alexander deal mainly with the exploration of land, other examples underline the nautical imagery used by a number of mathematicians. These include Bonaventura Cavalieri, who at the end of the 1630s described Galileo Galilei as the one who dared to “steer the immensity of the sea, and plunge into the ocean […], [and who] managed easily to navigate the immense ocean of indivisibles […] and a thousand other hard and distant things which could shipwreck anyone” (ibid., p. 184); Evangelista Torricelli, who calls Cavalieri’s method of indivisibles an “immense ocean,” noting that he himself prefers to stay near to the safe shore (ibid., p. 179); Thomas Harriot, for whom the mathematical continuum resembles “the coasts of undiscovered land” (ibid., p. 168); or John Davies, who in 1614 praises the mathematician Edward Wright, noting that as a geometer he resembles a navigator on the high seas, and hence equating the practices of the one with the practices of the other (ibid., p. 199).

As is clear from the above list of examples from Alexander’s book, the nautical voyage in the sea of mathematics is much more than an imagery of adventure and exploration; rather, it points toward the conception of the nonconceptualized as potentially a “place where evil appears,” to quote Blumenberg; the encounter with the nonconceptualized within mathematics itself– which occurs in opposition to the ‘ideal’ of mathematics– cannot be fully integrated or transferred into a concept. But as we saw with Blumenberg’s own position, also ‘well-defined’ concepts may contain ‘holes’ and their system may need to be reconstructed. This encounter with indeterminacy is hence at times considered dangerous, and at times metaphorized.

3 On Grothendieck’s mathematical and oceanic practices

In the examples discussed so far, one may note that each such encounter with the sea is unique, and thus each of the components of the metaphor illustrating it functions differently. To the dangerous, perplexing, or diverting images that serve to convey the mathematical encounter with what is not yet conceptualized, another metaphorical horizon can be added. Above, it was noted that Plutarch’s nautical metaphor implicitly frames the discussion on the ‘correct’ or ‘right’ practices to be employed when solving geometrical problems (i.e. with straightedge and compass). Hence the meeting on the shore framed the geometer’s uncertainty with respect to the instruments to be used. Nevertheless, the metaphors framing the discussion on the practices were more implicit, and thus remained in the background. How such oceanic-nautical metaphors may account explicitly for how one should practice mathematics is presented in the work of Alexandre Grothendieck (1928–2014), one of the pioneers of modern algebraic geometry.Footnote 64 To stress: these metaphors are not just attempts to present a claim about mathematical practices (i.e. as being basically meta-mathematical descriptions) but also– at least according to Grothendieck– a description of those practices, that is, how one can practice mathematics and how vagueness and ambiguity may arise in mathematics itself.

In his autobiographical manuscript Récoltes et semailles, Grothendieck describes two methodological approaches to mathematical problems. The first is to approach a problem as if it were a goal, using all tools to solve it, calling this method the one “of the chisel and the hammer” (1985–1987, p. 552). The second approach takes us to the image of the sea– or, more precisely, to what Grothendieck describes as the “rising sea” [“la mer qui monte”]. In Grothendieck’s words, “the sea advances imperceptibly and without noise, nothing seems to break, nothing moves, the water is so far away that it can hardly be heard […]. However, it ends up surrounding the reluctant substance, which gradually becomes a peninsula, then an island, then an islet, which ends up being submerged in its turn, as if it had finally dissolved in the ocean stretching as far as the eye can see […].”Footnote 65 (Ibid.) For Grothendieck, one has to let a problem– which he metaphorizes as a nut– be submerged and dissolved by a vast theory, one that goes well beyond the results originally to be established (ibid., p. 555). In this way, not only does the nut become so soft that it opens by itself, but this approach also reshapes the entire mathematical landscape– one discovers “‘new’ worlds” (ibid., p. 554). This is not to suggest that Grothendieck considers that every mathematician employs (or should employ) this method. Indeed, he stresses that the mathematician Jean-Pierre Serre mainly uses the first method: “Serre’s mathematical work, his approach to mathematics, […] to a difficulty would rather be that of the chisel and the hammer, very rarely that of the sea which rises and submerges, or that of the water which soaks and dissolves.”Footnote 66 (Ibid., p. 558) Moreover, Grothendieck explicitly notes that he uses this method to solve several mathematical problems, emphasizing that this description is not merely metaphorical but also very much practical. Among these problems he lists the Hirzebruch–Riemann–Roch theorem for any characteristic or the structure of the algebraic fundamental group of an algebraic curve over an algebraic closed field of any characteristic (ibid., p. 554, footnote ***).Footnote 67

What is unique in the use of this metaphor is that the sea, and not the shore, lets a solution arise, a solution which emerges almost unexpectedly, as if by itself. The method of submersion, absorption, and dissolution– in fact, of letting the problem drown in the sea of mathematics– is presented as a legitimate way to practice mathematics. One may very well claim that the metaphors presented here are oceanic, but they are also implicitly nautical, as they deal with how the mathematician should steer his way in the sea of mathematics. While Grothendieck’s metaphor of the rising sea deals with the encounter between unsolved problems and a possibly already existing sea of theory, in Grothendieck’s work there is yet another way in which the sea metaphor is discussed: in relation to the wave. In a subchapter titled “The arrow and the wave” [“La flèche et la vague”], Grothendieck again describes the two methods of mathematical research he favors. The first, once again, is characterized by solving a specific problem, reaching a goal, described as “this impatience to have reached the end of a task, this impulse toward such and such a ‘point’ […], this attraction of the ‘goal’ on me which throws me forward, like an arrow rushing toward its target.”Footnote 68 (Ibid, p. 594) But the mathematical work itself, of practically dealing with mathematical problems, can also be described otherwise:

There is no longer an arrow, rushing toward a target, but a wave that stretches out far and wide, moving who knows where, wherever the moving force that animates it takes it– a wave followed by another wave, followed by yet another […]. In each moment there is a progression, one cannot say toward what, there is a ‘work’ accomplished in a movement which ignores the effort– and there is no goal. The very idea of a ‘goal’ here seems strangely absurd […].Footnote 69 (Ibid.)

Here, the image of the waves complements and expands the metaphor of the rising sea. What is unique in the wave metaphor, however, is the explicit emphasis on the countless meetings between the sea and shore, that is, the changes undergone by mathematical practice itself. For Grothendieck, just as the sea always meets the shore in new and unique ways, the changes occurring within mathematics and affecting its boundaries also takes place in a unique way. If one takes into account both metaphors as comprising one image of mathematical practice, then on the shore of the sinking island of mathematical problems, which borders in a non-predetermined way with the sea of mathematics, the waves of the rising sea are crashing one after the other. According to Grothendieck’s philosophy of mathematical practice, not only is there no goal, as an attempt to construct a stable mathematical theory, which may be metaphorized, for example, with a ‘solid’ nautical metaphor (e.g. constructing a ship or controlling the sea) or with an architectonical metaphor (e.g. with a stable building), but also the result of practicing mathematics– described as the repeated crashing of the waves– is never known in advance, implying an unusual interlacement of nautical and oceanic metaphors. This, if we take notice of Blumenberg’s views, encapsulates his statement, that the goal of reaching a well-defined concept while working in its forefield is doomed to fail. This is reflected in both Blumenberg’s and Grothendieck’s conception of conceptual or mathematical practice; both note that the “goal” of concept formation is not what one should strive for: while Blumenberg explicitly stresses that a ‘successful’ definition of a concept cannot be obtained, in Grothendieck’s work, in which concepts are dynamic and may change, concept formation can be viewed as a byproduct. In this sense, even a ‘successful’ concept formation may result in concepts which are open-textured or essentially incomplete. Hence, with Grothendieck, one observes another use of the nautical-oceanic metaphor in relation to mathematics: there is no longer a possibly demonic sea, nor is there an island which guarantees certainty; there is rather an immense sea into which the islands of the problems should– or must– sink.

4 Conclusion: towards metaphorology of mathematics

If one views Grothendieck’s philosophy of mathematical practices through the lens of Blumenberg’s metaphorology and nonconceptuality, then one may conclude that the nautical-oceanic metaphors and their components are mostly suitable to account for the change and unpredictability of mathematical practices and of mathematics itself. This is seen not only with Grothendieck’s own examples, but also with the changing practices and concepts employed in the other examples presented above: the “emergence of infinitesimal methods,” (Alexander, 2002, p. 200) the uncertainty with respect to the use of geometrical instruments (besides compass and straightedge), the encounter with incommensurability, or the changing conceptual framework itself. Hence, nautical and oceanic metaphors– as well as other metaphors– are not a decoration, a byproduct, or a redundant appendix to the (historical) account, and the arguments presented here give reason to believe that metaphors play a fundamental role also in other examples and domains. This set of metaphors in its turn points toward an encounter with a mathematical nonconceptuality, and calls for a consideration of Blumenberg’s metaphorology with the latest discussions on open texture and the philosophy of mathematical practices.

To summarize: As seen in this paper, Blumenberg considered metaphors and metaphorology as a way to account for the emergence of concepts, later expanding his reflections to the field of nonconceptuality, hence reflecting also how mathematical concepts themselves may be elastic or indeterminable. While he did not explicitly deal with an extensive historical research of mathematical objects, concepts, or practices, I would like to suggest that his methodology can assist in understanding how these are conceptualized and used. Concepts in general, and hence also mathematical concepts, always have a forefield of what has not yet been or cannot be conceptualized, and this forefield is still a part of the concept, even when the latter is considered as well-defined. The (always occurring) encounter with this forefield is accounted for with metaphors. Hence, nautical and oceanic metaphors (and obviously not only these metaphors) should be taken into consideration within the philosophical and historical investigation, as they point toward an encounter with indeterminacy, and with nonconceptuality; this encounter, as both Grothendieck and Blumenberg stress, does not and cannot end or reach a definite conclusion. These metaphors therefore expand Blumenberg’s discussion toward a consideration also of scientific and mathematical practices– as elaborated in the case of Grothendieck.

These considerations also point to two open questions, with which I would like to conclude this paper. First, how are the various metaphors interwoven with one another? The most explicit example examined here is the interlacement of nautical and oceanic metaphors. As we have seen, in order to account for certain images of mathematics, other images besides nautical ones are employed, including the clothing metaphors and the architectonic or organic images mentioned above. Taking into account the history of these metaphors, how are these histories interlaced with the history of the nautical metaphor, when discussing mathematical concepts, practices, and their history? And how is this interlacement reflected in the philosophy of mathematical practices?

While the first question aims at a broader inspection of other metaphors, the second returns to the sea and to the nautical and oceanic metaphors. How is the history of these metaphors and their components to be seen in relation to the history of the ocean and its exploration on the one hand, and to possible attempts at its mathematizationFootnote 70 on the other hand? Against this background, Mentz (2015, 2020) proposes a retelling of human history and culture from an oceanic point of view. The task of examining nautical metaphors historically does not consist only in bringing Blumenberg into the fold, but also in more historical approaches stemming from the Blue Humanities. As Mentz and Blumenberg remind us, shipwreck, crashing waves, and unknown shores are not just metaphors but have their own materiality, with their own past, present, and future. Accordingly, this paper aims to point not only toward a possible future historical-metaphorical research on the nautical and oceanic metaphors found in mathematics, but also toward the philosophical implications of this research concerning how mathematics develops and is practiced.