Skip to main content
Log in

Environmental Ethics and Science: Resilience as a Moral Boundary

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Science has always been tightly associated with environmental ethics in a way traditional ethics has not. However, despite this proximity, science has had a merely informational role, where it must inform ethics but not intervene in ethical judgment. Science is seen as an amoral enterprise, requiring an ethics rather than recommending one. In this paper I try to go against this common view. First, I give a critique of the naturalistic fallacy following the lines of Frankena. Then I go on to describe the two possible roles science can have in ethical though, and in environmental ethics in particular. As it turns out, science does not only inform ethics, but can actually have moral import and intervene in moral judgment. Finally, from an ecocentric point of view, I try to illustrate this last point by construing the ecological notion of resilience as a moral boundary—a scientifically determined boundary between right and wrong.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Leopold (1949).

  2. Leopold (1949, pp. 224–225).

  3. Taylor (1981, p. 198).

  4. Leopold (1949, p. 221).

  5. Callicott (1980, p. 321).

  6. See Frankena (1939).

  7. Here I am adopting a position according to which a source of the normative force of our moral concepts comes from our conception of the good. One reason why we ought to do things is because they are good. I don´t claim this is the only source of normativity, but it seems to me to be definitely a source. This means in the present context that in order to conclude that we ought to do something, one could say that such a thing is good.

  8. Roslton (1997, p. 137).

  9. Of course, I am assuming that Doug is not a philosopher either—at least not a good one. Some biocentric philosophers would claim that the killing of the deer is wrong, even if it is done for the good of the ecosystem—Tom Regan for instance would probably claim this (see Regan 1983).

  10. IPCC (2014, p. vii).

  11. IPCC (2014, p. ix).

  12. Risser et al. (1991), as cited in Roslton (1997).

  13. I submit that this increase in normative power is not only due to the fact that George appears as some kind of public figure of authority. This is surely a component in his normative authority, but it is not the only one. We could imagine for instance that no one knows that George is the great scientists he is. Still, his judgment will have more power that Doug´s. And, the fact that George appears as having authority is certainly due partly to the fact that he has the knowledge that he has.

  14. “A biologist who does not respect life is just as much a contradiction in terms as is an ethicist who does not” (Roslton 1997, p. 151).

  15. Roslton (1997, p. 142).

  16. See for instance Folke et al. (2016).

  17. See also Röckstrom et al. (2009), and Gibbs (2009).

References

  • Callicott, J. B. (1980). Animal liberation: A triangular affair. Environmental Ethics, 2(1980), 311–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Folke, C., Biggs, R., Norström, A. V., Reyers, B., & Rockström, J. (2016). Social-ecological resilience and biosphere-based sustainability science. Ecology and Society, 21(3), 41.

  • Frankena, W. (1939). The naturalistic fallacy. Mind, 48(192), 464–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, M. T. (2009). Resilience: What is it and what does it mean for marine policymakers? Marine Policy, 33(2), 322–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • IPCC. (2014). Climate change 2014: Mitigation of climate change. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, A. (Ed.). (1949). The Land Ethic. In A Sand County Almanach. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Regan, T. (1983). The case for animal rights. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risser, P. G., Lubchenco, J., & Levin, S. A. (1991). Biological research priorities—A sustainable biosphere. BioScience, 47, 625–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Röckstrom, J., Steffen, W., Noone, K., Persson, Å., Chapin III, F.S., Lambin, E., et al. (2009). Planetary boundaries: Exploring the safe operating space for humanity. Ecology and Society, 14(2), 32.

  • Roslton, H. (1997). Environmental science and environmental advocacy: From ‘Is’ in science to ‘Ought’ in ethics. In A. Nordgren (Ed.), Science, ethics and sustainability: The responsibility of science in attaining sustainable development (pp. 137–153). Uppsala: Uppsala University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1975). Animal liberation. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, P. (1981). The ethics of respect for nature. Environmental Ethics, 3, 197–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Felipe Bravo Osorio.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bravo Osorio, F. Environmental Ethics and Science: Resilience as a Moral Boundary. J Agric Environ Ethics 30, 121–134 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-017-9657-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-017-9657-8

Keywords

Navigation