Skip to main content
Log in

Analog of Formula of Total Probability for Quantum Observables Represented by Positive Operator Valued Measures

  • Published:
International Journal of Theoretical Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We represent Born’s rule as an analog of the formula of total probability (FTP): the classical formula is perturbed by an additive interference term. In this note we consider practically the most general case: generalized quantum observables given by positive operator valued measures and measurement feedback on states described by atomic instruments. This representation of Born’s rule clarifies the probabilistic structure of quantum mechanics (QM). The probabilistic counterpart of QM can be treated as the probability update machinery based on the special generalization of classical FTP. This is the essence of the Växjö interpretation of QM: statistical realist contextual and local interpretation. We analyze the origin of the additional interference term in quantum FTP by considering the contextual structure of the two slit experiment which was emphasized by R. Feynman.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1 Nowadays realism is not fashionable in QM, especially local realism. Besides the Växjö interpretation, we can mention the interpretation due to Garola [1416] (completed in cooperation with Sozzo [17, 18]) and known as the extended semantic realism (ESR). We stress that the latter is non-contextual.

  2. 2 See Bohr [4, 5]: “This crucial point, which was to become a main theme of the discussions reported in the following, implies the impossibility of any sharp separation between the behaviour of atomic objects and the interaction with the measuring instruments which serve to define the conditions under which the phenomena appear. In fact, the individuality of the typical quantum effects finds its proper expression in the circumstance that any attempt of subdividing the phenomena will demand a change in the experimental arrangement introducing new possibilities of interaction between objects and measuring instruments which in principle cannot be controlled. Consequently, evidence obtained under different experimental conditions cannot be comprehended within a single picture, but must be regarded as complementary in the sense that only the totality of the phenomena exhausts the possible information about the objects.”

  3. 3 They are also both local and it seems that a consistent subjectivist has to handle probability in the contextual framework.

  4. 4 However, the problem “quantum versus classical probability” is even more complicated, cf. Nanasiova [35, 36] and Nanasiova and Valaskova [37]. If additional randomness, namely, of selection of experimental contexts, is taken into account then it is possible to construct the Kolmogorov representation for data collected for incompatible contexts, e.g., contexts C i ,i=0,1,C 01 in the two slit experiment [32], and even for incompatible contexts involved in Bell’s test - corresponding to selection of different pairs of orientations of polarization beam splitters [33]. Thus the terminology “non-Kolmogorovian probability has to be used with caution, cf., e.g., with its wide exploring in [1, 2, 28, 29].

References

  1. Asano, M., Khrennikov, A., Ohya, M., Tanaka, Y., Yamato, I.: Quantum Adaptivity in Biology: From Genetics to Cognition. Springer, Berlin (2015)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Asano, M., Basieva, I., Khrennikov, A., Ohya, M., Tanaka, Y., Yamato, I.: Quantum information biology: From information interpretation of quantum mechanics to applications in molecular biology and cognitive psychology. Found. Phys. 45(10), 1362–1378 (2015)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Atmanspacher, H.: Determinism is ontic, determinability is epistemic. In: Atmanspacher, H., Bishop, R.C. (eds.) Between Chance and Choice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Determinism, pp 49–74. Imprint Academic, Thorverton (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bohr, N.: The causality problem in atomic physics. In: Faye, J., Folse, H.J. (eds.) The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr: Causality and Complementarity, Supplementary Papers, 1987, vol. 4, pp 94–121. Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge (1938)

  5. Bohr, N.: The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, vol. 3. Woodbridge, Ox Bow Press (1987)

  6. Busch, P., Grabowski, M., Lahti, P.: Operational Quantum Physics. Springer, Berlin (1995)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Buscemi, F., D’ Ariano, G.M., Perinotti, P.: There exist nonorthogonal quantum measurements that are perfectly repeatable. Phys. Rev. Lett. 92, 070403–1–070403-4 (2004)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  8. Caves, C.M., Fuchs, C.A., Schack, R.: Quantum probabilities as Bayesian probabilities. Phys. Rev. A 65, 022305 (2002)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. de Laplace, P.-S.: A Philosphical Essay on Probabilities (Dover), translated from 6th french edn (1819, 1952)

  10. Davies, E., Lewis, J.: An operational approach to quantum probability. Comm. Math. Phys. 17, 239–260 (1970)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Feynman, R., Hibbs, A.: Quantum mechanics and path integrals. McGraw-Hill, New York (1965)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Fuchs, C.A.: Quantum mechanics as quantum information (and only a little more). In: Khrennikov, A. (ed.) Quantum Theory: Reconsideration of Foundations, Ser. Math. Modeling 2 (Växjö University Press, Växjö), pp 463–543 (2002)

  13. Fuchs, C.A., Mermin, N.D., Schack, R.: An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics. Am. J. Phys. 82, 749 (2014)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. Garola, C.: Criticizing Bell: Local realism and quantum physics reconciled. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 34(2), 253–263 (1995)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Garola, C.: Semantic realism: A new philosophy for quantum physics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 38(12), 3241–3252 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Garola, C.: MGP vs. KochenSpecker condition in hidden variables theories. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 44(7), 807–814 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Garola, C., Sozzo, S.: Embedding quantum mechanics into a broader noncontextual theory: A conciliatory result. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 49(12), 3101–3117 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Garola, C., Sozzo, S.: The modified Bell inequality and its physical implications in the ESR model. 50, N 12, 3787–3799 (2010)

  19. Jaeger, G.: Quantum Objects: Non-Local Correlation Causality and Objective Indefiniteness in the Quantum World. Springer, Berlin (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Interpretations of Probability (VSP Int. Sc. Publishers, Utrecht/Tokyo). Second edition: Khrennikov, A. (2009). Interpretations of Probability, 2nd edn. (De Gruyter, Berlin) (1999)

  21. Khrennikov, A.: Linear representations of probabilistic transformations induced by context transitions. J. Phys. A:. Math. Gen. 34, 9965–9981 (2001)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Khrennikov, A.Y.: Origin of quantum probabilities. In: Khrennikov, A. (ed.) Foundations of Probability and Physics (Växjö-2000, Sweden; WSP, Singapore), pp 180–200 (2001)

  23. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum statistics via perturbation effects of preparation procedures. Il Nuovo Cimento B 117(3), 267–281 (2002)

  24. Khrennikov, A.: Ensemble fluctuations and the origin of quantum probabilistic rule. J. Math. Phys. 43(2), 789–802 (2002)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Khrennikov, A.: Växjö interpretation of quantum mechanics. In: Quantum Theory: Reconsideration of Foundations, Ser. Math. Modelling (Växjö Univ. Press). Preprint arXiv:quant-ph/0202107, vol. 2, pp 163–170 (2002)

  26. Khrennikov, A.: Contextual viewpoint to quantum stochastics. J. Math. Phys. 44(6), 2471–2478 (2003)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Khrennikov, A.: Representation of the Kolmogorov model having all distinguishing features of quantum probabilistic model. Phys. Lett. A 316, 279–296 (2003)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Khrennikov, A.: Contextual Approach to Quantum Formalism. Springer, Berlin (2009)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Khrennikov, A.: Ubiquitous Quantum Structure: From Psychology to Finances. Springer, Berlin (2010)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Khrennikov, A., Basieva, I., Dzhafarov, E.N., Busemeyer, J.R.: Quantum models for psychological measurements: An unsolved problem. PLoS. ONE 9, e110909 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Khrennikov, A.: Beyond Quantum. Pan Stanford Publishing, Singapore (2014)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Khrennikov: Two-slit experiment: Quantum and classical probabilities. Phys. Scr. 90, 074017

  33. Khrennikov, A.: CHSH inequality: Quantum probabilities as classical conditional probabilities. Found. Phys. 45(7), 711–725 (2015)

  34. Kolmolgoroff, A.N.: Grundbegriffe Der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung (Springer-Verlag, Berlin). English translation: Kolmolgorov, A. N. (1956). Foundations of the Probability Theory (Chelsea Publ. Comp. New York) (1933)

  35. Nanasiova, O.: Map for simultaneous measurements for a quantum logic. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 42(9), 1889–1903 (2003)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. Nanasiova, O.: Principle conditioning. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 43(7), 1757–1767 (2004)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  37. Nanasiova, O., Valaskova, L.: Marginality and triangle inequality. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 49(12), 3199–3208 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. Nyman, P., Basieva, I.: Quantum-like representation algorithm for trichotomous observables. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 50, 3864–3881 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  39. Ozawa, M.: An operational approach to quantum state reduction. Ann. Phys. (N.Y.) 259, 121–137 (1997)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  40. Plotnitsky, A.: Epistemology and Probability: Bohr, Heisenberg Schrdinger and the Nature of Quantum-Theoretical Thinking. Springer, Berlin (2009)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  41. Plotnitsky, A., Khrennikov, A.: Reality without realism: On the ontological and epistemological architecture of quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 45(10), 269–1300 (2015)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. von Neuman, J.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princenton (1955)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrei Khrennikov.

Appendix: Växjö Viewpoint on Quantum Realism

Appendix: Växjö Viewpoint on Quantum Realism

Now we plan to discuss in more detail the Växjö viewpoint on quantum realism. We recall that the Växjö interpretation of QM, claiming that it is statistical, realist, contextual and local. At the same time this interpretation does not assume the existence of individual objects possessing individual properties, but only deals with statistical ensembles. One can ask: What kind of realism is the Växjö interpretation of QM the about?

As was pointed out in Section 5, Växjö realism is represented in the claim that it is in principle possible to construct a mathematical model describing causally subquantum processes and generating (via some correspondence rules) the observational quantum model described by the mathematical formalism of QM. This approach matches well with philosophy of the ontic-epistemic description of physical reality (Atmanspacher and Primas, see, e.g., [3]). The ontic description is about “reality as it is”, i.e., when nobody performs measurements. The epistemic description is about outputs of measurements, i.e., this is the observational description. The epistemic quantities cannot be treated as the objective properties. In this approach QM is considered as the epistemic (observational) model. In particular, this model is contextual, because its quantities are determined not only by features of physical systems, but also by the corresponding experimental contexts. Thus by the Växjö interpretation the QM-formalism is epistemic, but understanding of its observational and contextual nature does not exclude the possibility to create a causal ontic model. As was emphasized, this possibility is Växjö’s quantum realism.

Finally, as one of possible candidates for aforementioned ontic model, we can present the subquantum model of the random field type, so-called prequantum classical statistical field theory (PCSFT). Another candidate is the Bohmian model. However, in contrast to PCSFT, the Bohmian mechanics is nonlocal. We have already mentioned the Garola-Sozzo interpretation [1418] of QM based on the extended semantic realism (ERS) model. This model is not only local, but even non-contextual.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Khrennikov, A. Analog of Formula of Total Probability for Quantum Observables Represented by Positive Operator Valued Measures. Int J Theor Phys 55, 3859–3874 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10773-016-3015-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10773-016-3015-x

Keywords

Navigation