Husserl’s theory of scientific explanation emerges from his understanding of the structure of the scientific field. Simply stated, Husserl concludes that there are four hierarchically structured and interrelated tiers or strata to the scientific field. As a general sketch, the different tiers of science can be charted as follows (Fig. 1):
For the remainder of section two, we investigate the relationship between tiers one and two from our chart. In section three, we outline Husserl’s portrayal of the third tier. Accordingly, section two and section three together cover what we will call “standard” science.Footnote 4
Regarding the precise details of the contents of Sect. 2, during our discussion in Sect. 2.1 of Husserl’s understanding of the relationship between tier one and two, we introduce the topic of unity and provide an initial account of Husserl’s understanding of the explanatory function of the sciences. We also show that, locally at least, Husserl is certainly operating with a DN theory of explanation, but a DN theory that uniquely emphasizes a hierarchical interrelation between first and second-tier sciences. In Sect. 2.2, we introduce the topic of ground (Grund), which is central to Husserl’s account of scientific explanation. Finally, in Sect. 2.3, we provide an example of Husserl’s system of explanation in action. To close section two, we observe that Husserl—over 100 years ago—foresaw that the natural laws which frequently feature in DN explanations are mathematically idealized.
Explanation and Unity of Science
Two of the more important concepts of Husserl’s discussion of science in the Prolegomena are “unity” and “explanation.” Regarding unity, a foundational tenet of Husserl’s analysis is that science is not a chaotic amalgamation of random facts. Instead, sciences are organized and unified sets of propositions that possess systematic unity (Hua XVIII, pp. 30–31/1970b, 18). These propositions are expressively spoken in lectures or written in articles by scientists. One notable feature of these sets of propositions is that they must form a coherent body, such that they can be recognized as individual sciences distinguishable from each other (Hua XVIII, pp. 22–23/1970b, 13) and from pseudoscience (Hua XVIII, p. 39/1970b, 24).
We begin to clarify Husserl’s insights about unity, by noting that his philosophy of science—as it is presented in the Prolegomena—seeks to clarify how many propositions can be organized to form one unified science (Hua XVIII, pp. 230–238/1970b, 144–47). Importantly, Husserl claims that sciences are differently organized depending upon tier. The goal of those sciences found on the first tier, that is, the concrete sciences, is “the description of individual and typical individuations of earthly and heavenly existence” (Hua XXX, p. 338/2019, 356). Regarding unity, these concrete sciences are organized around specific sets of phenomena, which are taken as belonging together. Zoology studies the objects that belong together as animals, geography investigates states of affairs that concern the structure and substance of the physical earth, and so on (Hua XXX, p. 338/2019, 356; Hua XVIII, pp. 237/1970b, 148). In contrast, the second tier of the science—which Husserl refers to variously as the “abstract,” “nomological,” or “explanatory” sciences (Hua XVIII pp. 237–238/1970a, 147–148)—are sets of laws, which are organized according to the unification provided by the structure of the web of scientific explanation (this unification is discussed more in section four).
Regarding the second important concept, that is, explanation, it is evident that in the Prolegomena, Husserl thinks that the propositions of the concrete sciences require the propositions of the nomological sciences to carry out the essential scientific function of providing explanations.
Explanations, for Husserl, are a form of deductive argument,Footnote 5 which minimally has three parts: two premises and one conclusion. The prototype of a deductive argument (even an unexplanatory one) involves a major or universal premise (the example which introductory logic books used to provide is “all men are mortal”) and a minor, existential premise (“Socrates is a man”), and a conclusion which follows deductively from these two premises.
For Husserl, for the relevant kinds of explanation, the laws of the nomological sciences serve as the major premise. One then assumes certain “presupposed” or “pertinent circumstances” (Hua XVIII, p. 234/1970b, 146) as antecedent conditions that serve as the minor premise. This is, of course, a standard account of “what scientific explanation amounts to” (Hardy, 2014, 17), according at least to the DN model as it was first articulated by Hempel and Oppenheim (1948). As the latter put it, any “explanans falls into two subclasses; one of these contains certain sentences … which state specific antecedent conditions,” that is, Husserl’s presupposed or pertinent circumstances, “the other is a set of sentences … which represent general laws” (Hempel & Oppenheim, 1948, 137). Husserl’s thesis is that the contingent facts of the concrete sciences can be explained when they can be deduced as a consequence of a deductive argument, where these two subclasses of explanantia serve as premises (Hua XVIII, p. 234/1970b, 146).
A unique aspect of Husserl’s theory of explanation is his understanding of the relationship between the hierarchy of the sciences. He concludes that first-tier sciences offer the explanandum whilst second-tier sciences provide the key explanantia: laws. Otherwise stated, the nomological sciences of the second tier articulate laws, which explain the facts about the things that are the subject matter of the descriptions of the concrete sciences. Husserl writes that every natural empirical thing, or “every individual-concrete thing falls under what is universal, and the universality everywhere leads to conformity to laws” (Hua XXX, p. 337/2019, 355). This allows us, in science, to aim “ultimately to bring the particular under the law-concepts of what are called the abstract sciences precisely for purposes of explanation” (Hua XXX, p. 338/2019, 356).
Even though it is the abstract sciences that articulate the laws that feature in DN explanations, Husserl concludes that the concrete sciences carry out the type of pertinent explanations by “borrowing” those laws and applying them. He writes:
Concrete sciences like geology, mineralogy, and so on, first aim at the description of individual and typical individuations of earthly and heavenly existence. In them [the concrete sciences], however, the goal is ultimately to bring the particular under the law-concepts of what are called the abstract sciences precisely for purposes of explanation. (Hua XXX, p. 338/2019, 356, emphasis ours)
Each concrete science “corresponds” with certain nomological disciplines that provide the requisite resources to explain the facts about its field. For example, concrete biological sciences, such as zoology or botany can borrow the lawful resources from the corresponding nomological disciplines of biochemistry, cell theory, or genetics. The empirical or concrete sciences thus “set themselves the goal of not only describing concrete individuations of a field, let us say of some natural sphere, but of explaining them as necessarily being so through subsumption under the laws of a corresponding nomological discipline” (Hua XXX, p. 256/2019, 255). Tier one concrete sciences “reach up” to a corresponding discipline above them in tier two and use the nomological resources they find there to explain the facts they have described.
Grounding as Explaining
As stated, Husserl believes that sciences explain and more specifically, that the laws of the nomological sciences explain the facts of the concrete sciences. Yet, by simply stating that the former explains the latter, Husserl has by no means clarified the explanatory function of science. He must respond to the question; how exactly do those laws explain concrete facts? Husserl begins to develop his answer by asserting that the laws, which play the role of the major premise in a DN explanation, can explain by serving as ground (Grund). He writes, “To see a state of affairs as a matter of law … and to have knowledge of the ground [Grund] of the state of affairs or of its truth … are equivalent expressions” (Hua XVIII, p. 233–234/1970b, 146).Footnote 6 Husserl claims that science is made possible due to lawful grounding explanations (Hua XVIII, p. 256/1970b, 160). He even goes so far to write that “each actual advance in science is performed in an act of grounding [Begründung]” (Hua XVIII, p. 39/1970b, 24; translation modified).Footnote 7
In the Prolegomena, Husserl’s thinking around grounding is influenced by Bernard Bolzano’s use of the term Abfolge (“grounding”Footnote 8 or “consecutivity”Footnote 9) in his Wissenschaftlehre (1972).Footnote 10 As Stefan Roski elucidates, Bolzano thinks of ground
as an explanatory consequence relation. Bolzano takes grounding to be a sense of “following from”—a relation that obtains between premises and conclusions of certain proofs or arguments ... However, if some proposition follows from another one in this sense, then the latter does not only guarantee the truth of the former, it also accounts for why it is true: grounding under lies proofs that are not merely valid, but also explanatory. (Roski, 2017, 2)Footnote 11
Husserl too thinks that deductive entailment is necessary, yet insufficient to establish grounds:
every explanatory [erklärende] interconnection is a deductive one, but not every deductive interconnection is an explanatory one. All grounds [Gründe] are premises, but not all premises are grounds. Every deduction is necessary, i.e., falls under laws, but the fact that the conclusions follow according to laws (inferential laws) does not mean that they follow from those laws and are “founded” [“gründen”] in them in the precise sense. (HUA XVIII, p. 235/1970b, 147, translation modified)
Accordingly, for Husserl, an explanation is a type of deductive argument, where the conclusion follows not merely because it is valid according to one of the laws of inference, but also because the conclusion is grounded in one of the premises; that is, when at least one such premise, which features as a constituent of the actual argument itself and ergo leads deductively to the conclusion, is a law. As we shall see in Sect. 4 below, Husserl also accepts Bolzano’s thesis that the explanatory function of ground arises due to the unification provided by the global structure of the scientific field.
It is worth noting that the concept of “ground” has garnered much attention in the recent literature on explanation (see for example the collection in Correia & Schnieder, 2012; an overview in Raven, 2015). In this contemporary scholarship, it is generally thought that “ground” is a relation which obtains when one phenomenon is built out of, or one fact holds in virtue of, another. It is an asymmetric, irreflexive, transitive, and non-monotonic relation, which establishes an order amongst facts (Raven, 2015).Footnote 12 Moreover, ground is currently taken to be both a semantic relation that holds amongst facts or propositions and a “metaphysical”Footnote 13 relation that holds amongst real things in the world. Ground “is metaphysical because it concerns the phenomena in the world itself, but also explanatory because it concerns how some phenomena hold in virtue of others” (Raven, 2015, 325). Similarly, Husserl’s use of the term “ground” reflects an inseparable a priori correlation between the “interconnection of the things to which our thought-experiences (actual or possible) are intentionally directed, [and] an interconnection of truths” (Hua XVIII, p. 230/1970b, 144).
An Example and a Discussion
Readers may be uncertain as to exactly how it is, for Husserl, laws are supposed to explain the facts of descriptive science. Before proceeding, it is critical to provide one clear example—one that Husserl himself suggests. Proceeding from this example, we will observe that an unavoidable problem with DN explanations within natural science is that of forming precisely deductive arguments utilizing laws which are established inductively and thus hold only probabilistically. In closing our discussion of section two, we provide Husserl’s thinking on this problem.
Husserl provides some examples of nomological sciences, which can explain certain facts that have been gathered by concrete sciences. He states, for example, that “mathematical astronomy,” which belongs to the second tier of science, can provide the explanatory theory “for the facts of gravitation” as gathered from a tier one science, observational astronomy (Hua XVIII, p. 234/1970b, 147). What Husserl is here calling “mathematical astronomy” is a theory, that is, an organized series of nomological propositions. Examples of such propositions would be Newton’s law of universal gravitation and his laws of motion. One can apply these laws to explain certain empirical facts concerning the behavior of heavenly bodies under the effects of gravitation gathered from the field of observational astronomy, i.e., the elliptical orbit of Mercury. This means that the propositions, which express universal gravitation and the laws of motion, subsume and thus explain the proposition, which is expressed as the fact that Mercury exhibits an elliptical orbit (when arranged in a deductive argument).Footnote 14
What Husserl states is that if “the interconnection of one fact with others is one of law, then its existence … is determined as a necessary existence” (Hua XVIII, p. 234/1970b, 146, italics modified). What he means by this is that, given the laws of gravitation and motion (and other presupposed circumstances, such as Mercury’s spatial relation to the sun, etc.), Mercury could not but orbit elliptically.
Husserl emphasizes throughout this analysis that the second tier (the theoretical disciplines) borrow resources from mathematics and express their propositions in mathematical formulae (such as the formula for universal gravitation). For Husserl, this mathematization affords the essential ingredient of deduction. He writes:
Every science that is explanatory, in the strict sense, is ‘mathematical.’ Its explanations proceed deductively from principles that necessarily have deductive form; and the whole deductive system of theorization must be mathematical, and allow itself to be arranged according to its pure mathematical form. (Husserl & Stein, 2018, 460)
We gather from this quote that, for Husserl, deduction follows from the precise extension that mathematical concepts afford. However, Husserl also recognizes that stating natural laws in a mathematically precise fashion is problematic. The laws of nature are imperfect.Footnote 15 These laws, such as the “law of gravitation, as formulated in astronomy, have never really been proven,” in the sense in which a mathematical fact can be given a deductive proof. Natural laws can be rendered at best empirically adequate. They are contingent on ceteris paribus clauses, only (highly) probably true, and falsifiable (HUA XVIII, p. 83/1970b, 52–53).Footnote 16 Husserl thus identifies many of the problems with the laws of nature that will later be recognized and addressed by Hempel (1988) and Cartwright (1983).
Furthermore, Husserl here presciently highlights that, scientists idealize natural laws in order to impart the necessary (yet insufficient) explanatory quality of deductive entailment. Thus, natural laws (such as the law that gravitational force varies in proportion to an inverse square) are, according to Husserl, “no more than idealizing fictions” (Hua XVIII, p. 82/1970b, 52). We reach “the ideal of explanatory theory, of law-governed unity” when we reduce these probabilities to “exact thoughts having the genuine form of laws, and so succeed in building up formally perfect systems of explanatory theory” (Hua XVIII, pp. 82–84/1970b, 52–53; see Byrne & Kattumana, 2022).
Although we will avoid comparing this account of idealization with the one found in the Crisis (Hua VI/1970a), we conclude that the early Husserl’s “scientific fictionalism” (according to which certain scientific propositions are merely helpful fictions) applies to natural laws but not to the referents of those laws (entities that exist in the real spatiotemporal world). For the early Husserl, scientific idealization is an explanatory practice, one related to semantically evaluable entities (i.e., the propositions that express laws).
This conclusion about the early Husserl is commensurate with Hardy’s (2020) analysis of idealization in the Crisis (Hua VI/1970a). However, Hardy advances a bi-level analysis that splits laws from theories and equates the latter to a causal account that explains how laws work. Although Hardy never goes as far as to say that Husserl endorses this bi-level division, he seems to elide the fact that in Husserl (at least in the Prolegomena and Husserliana XXX) theories are just organized bodies of laws,Footnote 17 and theorization is just the process of drawing deductive conclusions from those laws. And, although Hardy is not directly discussing Husserl’s theory of explanation, the above quotes reveal Husserl is clear in the Prolegomena that it is laws that do the explaining, not the causal account of those laws, and so Husserl does not support the bi-level analysis that Hardy operates with. Thus, where we diverge from Hardy is in explicitly noting that for Husserl, explanation and causality are not coextensive. There are explanatory disciplines in tier three of the sciences that fit the model of explanation we have outlined which have no causal content whatsoever (see Sect. 3.2).
Three Kinds of Explanation
To more accurately develop our interpretation of Husserl’s theory of scientific explanation, in this section, we expound on Husserl’s conclusion that there are three different kinds of explanations to be found within the first two tiers of science.
There is the already discussed explanation of “singular facts through general laws” (Hua XIX, p. 26/1970b, 178). Husserl, however, does not believe that singular facts are the only kind of facts that can be explained. Instead, he notes that there is a distinction between singular facts and general facts: “individual and general truths” (Hua XVIII, p. 233/1970b, 146). The second kind of grounding is the explanation of a general truth. This occurs when “we are referred to certain general laws which, by way of … deductive consequence yield the [universal] proposition to be proven” (Hua XVIII, p. 233/1970b, 146). Simply stated, laws explain two types of facts: individual ones (‘this starling was aggressive because…’) and general ones (‘all starlings tend to flock because…’).
Third, Husserl concludes that not only facts may be explained. Rather, he observes that certain laws can be explained by other more general laws; as he calls them, more “basic” or “fundamental” laws (“Grundgesetze”). We can call this “inter-lawful” explanation. Husserl clearly endorses the notion of inter-lawful explanation, writing that the word “explanation”
has a twofold meaning if on one occasion one speaks of explanation with regard to what is concrete and its subsumption under the concepts of the abstract sciences, and on the other hand, says in the abstract sciences themselves within the context of the theory that through subsumption of the particular laws under the basic laws, the former receive their explanation. (Husserl, 2019, 357)
Accordingly, within nomological science, there are the explanations of “general laws through some fundamental law” (Hua XIX, p. 26/1970b, 178). One might think of how “for example, Kepler’s Laws receive their explanation from the basic law of universal gravitation and the basic laws of mechanics” (Husserl XXX, p. 311/2019, 357).Footnote 18 In other words, it is not only the facts concerning the orbit of this or that planet on this or that occasion which Newton’s theories explain. Rather, Newton’s theories also explain the less fundamental Keplerian laws concerning the orbital behavior of all celestial bodies. We are thus, Husserl writes, “led upward in the hierarchical structure of the law-governed dependencies to the basic laws upon which all full, ultimate explanation is based” (Hua XXX, p. 244/2019, 257).
However, we should point out that, even with inter-lawful explanation, wherein we have departed from the activity of explaining concrete facts (either individual or general ones), the inter-lawful explanation just discussed still occurs within “the realm of natural laws” (Hua XIX, p. 26/1970b, 178). We are talking, therefore, about the explanation of one natural law by reference to another natural law. The explanation of a general law through a basic or fundamental law occurs within the second tier of science.
One way to put the point here is that, within this second tier—that is, the realm of natural laws—even basic or fundamental laws (ones we find up towards the “top” of the explanatory hierarchy) are impure, that is, empirical. For example, gravitation is an empirical phenomenon; one which occurs in the empirical world. Thus, when we explain Kepler’s laws via the employment of the basic law of gravitation, the basic law of gravitation still has empirical content (such as the gravitational constant). Though basic natural laws may be mathematized, they are impure because they employ empirical concepts.
Explanation within A Priori Sciences
We move on now to an investigation of explanations within the third tier of regular science. The third-tier sciences are the a priori disciplines that—in Ideas 1—Husserl refers to as the pure eidetic sciences, such as pure mathematics (Hua III-1, p. 21/1986, 16). On the one hand, explanation within a priori science mirrors explanation within natural science. The a priori sciences are in fact also nomological—in that they involve laws—and their explanations have the same DN form as already discussed. On the other hand, the explanations of these two tiers are distinct, because their major premises, though both laws, are of different natures.
In second-tier nomological sciences, natural laws serve as the major premise. When stated unconditionally, these natural laws are merely convenient fictions. In contrast, within a priori sciences, axioms serve as the major premise. Husserl writes:
Theoretical explanation means… [in] the realm of the a priori… to understand the necessity of specific, lower-level relationships in terms of comprehensive general necessities, and ultimately in terms of those most primitive, universal relational laws that we call axioms. (Hua XIX, p. 25/1970b, 178).
Axioms are fundamentally distinct from natural laws in two ways. First, they are “given” and established quite differently. Axiomatic laws are not established inductively, and it is impossible to think that they could be revised. Instead, axioms “must be able to come to givenness in directly evident insights, while the opposite holds for factual laws” (Hua XXX, p. 247/2019, 261). Unlike the laws of the natural theoretical sciences, these axiomatic laws have “entire validity: they themselves in their absolute exactness are evident and proven” (Hua XVIII, p. 83/1970b, 53). For Husserl, the exact definition of a law is a proposition that holds with absolute unconditional universal necessity, such that—strictly considered—only pure laws qualify (Hua XXX, p. 221/2019, 234).
Second, while the deductive process of explanation is potentially regressive within natural science, such that more primitive laws can often be requested to explain an explanans, axioms “are the primitives or starting points in the order of justification” (Smith, 1989, 279). As we show below, it is a mistake to ask for further deductive explanation of a fundamental axiom. Explanation is not an infinitely regressive or recursive procedure for Husserl. For him, finding and referring to axioms is to hit explanatory bottom. Axioms are the ultimate grounds, that is, ungrounded explanantia.
To clarify what it means for axioms to be the initial point of justification, we discuss the example, where someone seeks an explanation for the theorem that “there is no even prime number greater than two.” We can offer a deductive and explanatory proof for this mathematical fact, which relies in part on the axiom that “even numbers are divisible by two.”
-
(1)
Prime numbers are divisible only by themselves and one (axiom).
-
(2)
Even numbers are divisible by two (axiom).
-
(3)
Any even number greater than two is divisible by two (inference from 2).
-
(4)
Any even number greater than two is divisible by a number other than itself and one (inference from 3).
Conclusion: Any even number greater than two is not prime (deduction from 1 + 4) (example adapted from Colyvan [2012, 91]).
Here, the explanandum follows deductively as conclusion, and the axiomatic premises serve as grounds that explain that conclusion.
Premise two is axiomatic because there is no similar form of deductive argument involving simpler axioms where this is the conclusion. Being divisible by two is part of the definition of an even number. There is nothing more basic that could be done to deductively prove that the concepts “even number” and “divisible by two” are equivalentFootnote 19 (the most one could do is to explicate the concepts of “even,” “number,” “two,” and so on. See Hua XVIII, pp. 241–244/1970b, 152–54). The axiom itself serves as a primitive starting point from which one can only move forward in the order of justification.
Non-Causal Explanation within A Priori Sciences
Husserl asserts in the Prolegomena that there is a strict separation between the sphere of the ideal and a priori, on the one hand, and the concrete and the empirical, on the other hand. The realm of the a priori is ideal, not reale or reelle being. In line with this, the pure and ideal explanatory axioms “exclude all factual content” (Hua XVIII, p. 83/1970b, 52). Because pure axioms are non-factual, they are non-causal, as “real” causalityFootnote 20 is only to be found amongst the actual, that is, factual empirical world. This insight is inspired by Bolzano, who writes that mathematical explanations “exclude, therefore, causal content. Thus, mathematical truths can be related as ground and consequence, although they do not deal with objects that have reality” (Bolzano, 1972, 273).Footnote 21 While the axiom that all even numbers are divisible by two certainly explains why there is no even prime greater than two, the axiom does not cause the fact. For Husserl, explanations cover non-causal relationships. In the a priori and the empirical, explanation is established when the consequence is grounded in law, causal or otherwise.
When Husserl discusses explanation within tier three science, he has in mind what has come to be referred to as intra-mathematical explanation (that is, the explanation of one mathematical fact by another). In discussing intra-mathematical explanation, Husserl is again presciently providing an account of an area that has only recently assumed great importance for the theory of explanation (Lange, 2016; Mancosu, 2008). The Bolzanian/Husserlian thesis that intra-mathematical explanations are underwritten by grounding relationships is a unique one worthy of further research.
In summary, the explanatory relation can be found a total of four times within the hierarchy of the three tiers of regular science. Each of the four explanatory relations is represented by an arrow below (Fig. 2):