Skip to main content

Hempel, Carnap, and the Covering Law Model

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 273))

Abstract

Carl Gustav Hempel was one of the most influential figures in the development of scientific philosophy in the twentieth century, particularly in the English-speaking world. While he made a variety of contributions to the philosophy of science, he is perhaps most remembered for his careful formulation and detailed elaboration of the “Covering Law model” for scientific explanation. In this essay I consider why the CL model was, and still is, so influential, in spite of the fact that it has been subjected to many criticisms and is usually seen as superseded by alternative models. Answering this question involves a reexamination of Hempel’s relationship to other influential scientific philosophers, especially Rudolf Carnap. It also sheds new light on issues concerning the notions of analysis, explication, and modeling that remain relevant today.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For biographical information, cf. Fetzer (2000b, 2010), Rescher (2005), also Friedman (2000).

  2. 2.

    For overviews of Hempel’s main works, cf. Salmon (2000), Kitcher (2001), Fetzer (2010), and Curd (2012).

  3. 3.

    In Wesley Salmon’s words: “The 1948 Hempel–Oppenheim article marks the division between the pre-history and the history of modern discussions of scientific explanation.” (Salmon 1990, 10)

  4. 4.

    As Salmon later put it: “[T]he Hempel-Oppenheim 1948 article forced scientific explanation onto the attention of a wide class of logicians and philosophers of science. There was an explicit proposal regarding the nature of scientific explanation on the table, and it challenged philosophers to respond either positively or negatively. It elicited alternative analyses. The temptation to say that there is no such a thing as scientific explanation seems to have vanished.” (Salmon 2000, 315)

  5. 5.

    I take the logically based account of scientific laws in the later parts of Hempel and Oppenheim (1948) to be due mostly to Hempel. I will come back to Oppenheim’s role briefly later in this essay.

  6. 6.

    Cf. the discussion of archeology in Salmon (1990), 25–26. Hempel had applications to history in mind from early on; cf. Hempel (1942). Some of its earliest and longest lasting criticisms concern that intended application.

  7. 7.

    Cf. the discussion of the early, internal criticisms of the CL model (by R. Eberle, D. Kaplan, R. Montague, and others) in Salmon (1990), chapter 2.

  8. 8.

    The corresponding counterexamples focused attention on, among others, the necessity of laws, the deductive structure of explanations, and certain explanatorily relevant causal asymmetries not captured by the CL schema. For overviews, cf. Salmon (1990), chapter 23, and Fetzer (2000a).

  9. 9.

    Many of the “second-wave” challenges to the CL model concerned the inductive-statistical case. One attempt to improve on Hempel’s position was Salmon’s “statistical-relevance” model, which was subsequently also found wanting. Cf. Salmon (1990), chapter 3 and Fetzer (2000a).

  10. 10.

    Pitt (1988) contains representative texts; cf. also Kitcher and Salmon (1989) and, again, Salmon (1990). For the basic difference between Scriven’s and the other approaches, cf. Reck (2012).

  11. 11.

    An authoritative recent discussion of the topic, as presented by the proponent of a causal account, can be found in Woodward (2003). For a more general overview, see also, e.g., Psillos (2007).

  12. 12.

    The first reaction, or the first kind of alternative, is much more common in the literature on scientific explanation. Even van Fraassen’s pragmatic model can be seen as falling into this first camp. I take Michael Scriven’s approach to be an example of the second kind of response, in the sense that he provided what Peter Strawson would later call a “connective analysis” of the notion of explanation. For further discussion of the latter point, cf. Reck (2012); for another, more recent representative of Scriven’s camp, cf. Wright (2011).

  13. 13.

    Note, moreover, that outside of philosophy something close to the CL model is still often taken for granted when people talk about scientific explanation, especially in the natural sciences.

  14. 14.

    It is worth adding here that Oppenheim didn’t just collaborate with Hempel but with other philosophers as well (including Kurt Grelling, Olaf Helmer, Nicholas Rescher, and Hilary Putnam). And often these collaborations involved working out Oppenheim’s ideas (cf. Rescher 2005).

  15. 15.

    For further forays in that direction, compare the two essays by Nikolay Milkov (Chaps. 1 and 14) in this volume.

  16. 16.

    Hempel started interacting with Kuhn in 1963–1964, when both spent time at the Center for Advanced Studies in the Behavioral Sciences in Palo Alto. Subsequently, they became colleagues at Princeton. Quine’s views were very prominent in the US during the 1960s and later, of course.

  17. 17.

    As Michael Friedman reports, Hempel himself later talked about “his conversion from the point of view of Carnapian ‘explication’ or ‘rational reconstruction’ to the point of view of Kuhnian historical and sociological naturalism as a return to Neurath’s original conception” (Friedman 2000, 45).

  18. 18.

    For a survey of ways in which scientific models are representative, cf. Bailer-Jones (2009), chapter 8.

  19. 19.

    For a few more comments on the meta-theoretic and the normative role of the CL model, cf. Reck (2012). For comparisons of different kinds of models within science (physical, mechanical, set-theoretic, etc.), see again Morgan and Morrison (1999), Bailer-Jones (2009), and the literature referred to in them.

References

  • Bailer-Jones, Daniela. 2009. Scientific models in philosophy of science. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1947. Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curd, Martin. 2012. Carl G. Hempel: Logical empiricist. In Key thinkers in the philosophy of science, ed. James R. Brown, 83–111. London: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, James. 2000a. The paradoxes of Hempelian explanation. In Fetzer 2000b, 111–137. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, James H. (ed.). 2000b. Science, explanation, and rationality: The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, James H. 2010. Carl Hempel. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/hempel/.

  • Friedman, Michael. 2000. Hempel and the Vienna Circle. In Fetzer 2000b, 39–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1942. The function of general law in history. The Journal of Philosophy 39: 35–48; repr. in Hempel 1965b. 231–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1965a. Aspects of Scientific Explanation. In Hempel 1965b, 331–496. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1965b. Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1966. Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1973. Rudolf Carnap: Logical empiricist. Synthese 25: 256–268; repr. in Hempel 2000b. 253–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1988. On the cognitive status and the rationale of scientific methodology. Poetics Today 9: 5–27; repr. in Hempel 2000b. 199–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 2000a. An intellectual autobiography. In Hempel 2000b, 3–35. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 2000b. Carl G. Hempel: Selected philosophical essays, ed. Richard Jeffrey. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 2001. The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel: Studies in science, explanation, and rationality, ed. James H. Fetzer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G., and Paul Oppenheim. 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15: 135–175; repr. In Hempel 1965b. 245–290; also in Pitt 1988. 9–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 2001. Carl G. Hempel (1905–1997). In A companion to analytic philosophy, ed. Aloysius P. Martinich and David Sosa, 148–159. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip, and Wesley C. Salmon (eds.). 1989. Scientific explanation. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science XIII. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Mary S., and Margaret Morrison (eds.). 1999. Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, Joseph (ed.). 1988. Theories of explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, Stathis. 2007. Past and contemporary perspectives on explanation. In General philosophy of science: Focal issues, ed. T. Kuipers. 97–174. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reck, Erich. 2012. Carnapian explication: A case study and critique. In Carnap’s ideal of explication and naturalism, ed. P. Wagner, 96–116. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 1997. H2O: Hempel-Helmer-Oppenheim. An episode in the history of scientific philosophy in the 20th century. Philosophy of Science 64: 334–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 2005. The Berlin school of logical empiricism and its legacy. In Studies in 20 th century philosophy. Collected papers, N. Rescher, 119–147. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, Wesley. 1990. Four decades of scientific explanation. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, Wesley. 2000. The spirit of logical empiricism: Carl G. Hempel’s role in twentieth-century philosophy of science. In Fetzer 2000b, 309–324. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolters, Gereon. 2003. Carl Gustav Hempel: Pragmatic empiricist. In Logical empiricism. Historical and contemporary perspectives, ed. P. Parrini, W. Salmon, and M. Salmon, 109–122. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, James. 2003. Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Larry. 2011. Explanation, contrast, and the primacy of practice. European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00472.x.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erich H. Reck .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Reck, E.H. (2013). Hempel, Carnap, and the Covering Law Model. In: Milkov, N., Peckhaus, V. (eds) The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 273. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5485-0_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics