Skip to main content
Log in

Common-value all-pay auctions with asymmetric information and bid caps

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study a class of two-player common-value all-pay auctions (contests) with asymmetric information under the assumption that one of the players has an information advantage over his opponent and both players are budget-constrained. We extend the results for all-pay auctions with complete information, and show that in our class of all-pay auctions with asymmetric information, sufficiently high (but still binding) bid caps do not change the players’ expected total effort compared to the benchmark auction without any bid cap. Furthermore, we show that there are bid caps that increase the players’ expected total effort compared to the benchmark. Finally, we demonstrate that there are bid caps which may have an unanticipated effect on the players’ expected payoffs—one player’s information advantage may turn into a disadvantage as far as his equilibrium payoff is concerned.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Hillman and Samet (1987), Hillman and Riley (1989), Baye et al. (1993, 1996) and Siegel (2009).

  2. See, for example, Amman and Leininger (1996), Moldovanu and Sela (2001, 2006) and Moldovanu et al. (2012).

  3. Some works considered all-pay auctions with bid caps which are player-specific and constitute players’ individual budget constraints, see e.g. Kotowski and Li (2014). In their ex-ante symmetric setting with affiliated value-signals, some bidders would overbid following the introduction of (identically and independently distributed) personal budget constraints compared to the no-constraint scenario. Pastine and Pastine (2012) also condsidered individual bid caps in a broad class of all-pay contests, though under the complete information assumption.

  4. Several researchers used the same framework as ours to analyze common-value second-price auctions and common-value first price auctions (see Einy et al. 2001, 2002; Forges and Orzach 2011; Malueg and Orzach 2012, and Abraham et al. 2014).

  5. Krishna and Morgan (1997) analyzed the equilibrium strategies of the all-pay auction with interdependent types in the Harsanyi-type formulation of Bayesian games. They assumed that the players’ types are affiliated and symmetrically distributed. Our assumptions on the information structure (to be described next) make our contribution more related to the work of Siegel (2014) in the Harsanyi-type setting; this relation will be highlighted later in the introduction.

  6. The assumption of connected information sets, although natural in some contexts, is admittedly not innocuous. Indeed, as was exhibited by Rentschler and Turocy (2014) in the common value set-up (see examples 4a and 4b) with a general information endowment, all-pay auctions may have non-monotone equilibria (with overlapping supports of best response strategy distributions corresponding to different types of the same player). In our framework only monotone equilibria seem to emerge, as shown in our Proposition 1, Claim 1 for certain ranges of bid caps.

  7. This stands in contrast to the increase in the total effort that may occur in the “bidding at the cap” equilibrium in the Che and Gale (1998) complete information framework with unequal valuations.

  8. Siegel (2014) makes a joint monotonicity assumption on the players’ conditional distributions of signals and valuations. In our model, due to the connectedness of the information partition of the informed player and it being degenerate for the uninformed player, his assumption is satisfied trivially.

  9. See Sect. 2 in the online appendix to Siegel (2014). As has been remarked, Siegel’s framework subsumes ours (without bid caps), and hence the result also holds in our set-up.

  10. See Einy et al. 2001, 2002, and Forges and Orzach 2011.

  11. Thus, the states of nature can be identified with the distinct values corresponding to the different states. Without the connectedness of information partitions, the information advantage assumption could still be reduced to (2), but the value would not need to be distinct across the states (see Example A.1 in Forges and Orzach 2011).

  12. Subsequent sections will address some complementary cases, in which bid caps are relatively low, but without providing a complete equilibrium characterization.

  13. See Sect. 2 in the online appendix to Siegel (2014).

  14. In the case of the informed player 2, by “full support” of his strategy we mean the union of the (full) supports of all distributions corresponding to the conditional strategies of player 2 given the different realizations of the uncertain common value.

  15. It can be shown that the equilibrium we have described is unique, which lends robustness to this conclusion.

  16. Note that (15) is incompatible with the left-hand inequallity in (3), i.e., it only holds for sufficiently low bid caps. This (and the other conditions that follow) is what allows player 1 to credibly commit to setting his effort at the level d in all states of nature. Under (3) this cannot occur by Proposition1.

  17. Sahuguet (2006) proves the existence of a range of bid caps that increase the total effort in an asymmetric all-pay auction where the private values have different uniform distributions. However, there seems to be no direct link between his result and our example because of the difference in set-ups.

  18. Since each interval \([y_{i-1},y_{i}]_{\_}\) is either non-degenerate or \( \{0\} \), \(0\,=y_{0}\,=\cdots =\,y_{i_{0}-1}<\,y_{i_{0}}\,<\cdots <\,y_{n}.\)

  19. In the LHS \(F_{2}\) is viewed as a probability measure, and in the RHS as a c.d.f.

  20. Distribution \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) does not have an atom at \(\beta ,\) as follows from (31), and hence formula (30) can be used for \(x=\beta \) although it is stated for \(x<y_{n}=\beta .\)

References

  • Abraham I, Athey S, Babaiof M, Grubb M (2014) Peaches, Lemons, and Cookies: designing auction markets with dispersed information. Working paper, Harvard University

  • Amman E, Leininger W (1996) Asymmetric all-pay auctions with incomplete information: the two-player case. Games Econ Behav 14:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baye MR, Kovenock D, de Vries CG (1993) Rigging the lobbying process: an application of the all-pay auction. Am Econ Rev 83:289–294

    Google Scholar 

  • Baye M, Kovenock D, de Vries C (1996) The all-pay auction with complete information. Econ Theory 8:291–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Che Y-K, Gale I (1998) Caps on political lobbying. Am Econ Rev 88(3):643–651

    Google Scholar 

  • Einy E, Haimanko O, Orzach R, Sela A (2001) Dominant strategies, superior information, and winner’s curse in second-price auctions. Int J Game Theory 30:405–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einy E, Haimanko O, Orzach R, Sela A (2002) Dominance solvability of second-price auctions with differential information. J Math Econ 37:247–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einy E, Haimanko O, Orzach R, Sela A (2014) Common-value all-pay auctions with asymmetric information. Working paper, Ben-Gurion University (2014)

  • Forges F, Orzach R (2011) Core-stable rings in second price auctions with common values. J Math Econ 47:760–767

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gavious A, Moldovanu B, Sela A (2003) Bid costs and endogenous bid caps. Rand J Econ 33(4):709–722

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillman A, Riley J (1989) Politically contestable rents and transfers. Econ Politics 1:17–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillman A, Samet D (1987) Dissipation of contestable rents by small numbers of contenders. Public Choice 54(1):63–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotowski M, Li F (2014) On the continuous equilibria of affiliated-value, all-pay auctions with private budget constraints. Games Econ Behav 85:84–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krishna V, Morgan J (1997) An analysis of the war of attrition and the all-pay auction. J Econ Theory 72(2):343–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malueg D, Orzach R (2009) Revenue comparison in common-value auctions: two examples. Econ Lett 105:177–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malueg D, Orzach R (2012) Equilibrium and revenue in a family of common-value first-price auctions with differential information. Int J Game Theory 41(2):219–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom P, Weber R (1982) A theory of auctions and competitive bidding. Econometrica 50(5):1089–1122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moldovanu B, Sela A (2001) The optimal allocation of prizes in contests. Am Econ Rev 91(3):542–558

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moldovanu B, Sela A (2006) Contest architecture. J Econ Theory 126(1):70–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moldovanu B, Sela A, Shi X (2012) Carrots and sticks: prizes and punishments in contests. Econ Inq 50(2):453–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pastine I, Pastine T (2012) All-pay contests with constraints. UCD UCD Centre for Economic Research, Working Paper WP12/04

  • Rentschler L, Turocy T (2014) All-pay auctions with interdependent valuations: The highly competitive case. http://ssrn.com/abstract=2446789

  • Sahuguet N (2006) Caps in asymmetric all-pay auctions with incomplete information. Econ Bull 9:1–8

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel R (2009) All-pay contests. Econometrica 77(1):71–92

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel R (2014) Asymmetric all-pay auctions with interdependent valuations. J Econ Theory 153:684–702

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ori Haimanko.

Additional information

E. Einy, O. Haimanko and A. Sela gratefully acknowledge the support of the Israel Science Foundation Grant 648/13.

Appendix

Appendix

Remark 1

As far as equilibrium analysis is concerned, the assumption that player 2 has an information advantage over player 1 can be reduced to (2). Indeed, in the general case of \(\Pi _{2}\) being finer than \(\Pi _{1}\) note the following. Given \(\pi _{1}\in \Pi _{1},\) the event \(\pi _{1}\) is common knowledge at any \(\omega \in \pi _{1}\). Thus, the equilibrium analysis can be carried out separately for each \(\pi _{1}\in \Pi _{1},\) as conditional on the occurrence of \(\pi _{1}\) the auction G can be viewed as a distinct common-value all-pay auction \(G^{\prime }\), where the set of states of nature is \(\Omega ^{\prime }=\pi _{1}\) and the conditional distribution \(p(\cdot \mid \pi _{1})\) serves as the common prior distribution \(p^{\prime }\). In \(G^{\prime }\), player 1 has the trivial information partition, \(\Pi _{1}^{\prime }=\left\{ \Omega ^{\prime }\right\} .\)

Thus, we may w.l.o.g. assume that \(\Pi _{1}=\left\{ \Omega \right\} \) in the original auction G. Now consider another common-value all-pay auction \( G^{\prime \prime }\) in which the set of states of nature \(\Omega ^{\prime \prime }\equiv \Pi _{2}\) consists of information sets of player 2 in G; the common value function \(v^{\prime \prime }\) is given by \(v^{\prime \prime }\left( \pi _{2}\right) =E(v\mid \pi _{2})\) for every \(\pi _{2}\in \Omega ^{\prime \prime };\) player 2 has the full information partition, consisting of all singleton subsets of \(\Omega ^{\prime \prime },\) i.e., \(\Pi _{2}^{\prime \prime }=\left\{ \left\{ \pi _{2}\right\} \mid \pi _{2}\in \Omega ^{\prime \prime }\right\} ;\) and player 1 has the trivial information partition \(\Pi _{1}^{\prime \prime }=\left\{ \Omega ^{\prime \prime }\right\} .\) It is easy to see that \(\Pi _{2}^{\prime \prime }\) is connected w.r.t. \(v^{\prime \prime }.\) Naturally, every mixed strategy \(F_{2}\left( \cdot ,\cdot \right) \) of player 2 in G corresponds to a unique mixed strategy \(F_{2}^{\prime \prime }\left( \cdot ,\cdot \right) \) of 2 in \( G^{\prime \prime }\) that is given by \(F_{2}^{\prime \prime }\left( \pi _{2},\cdot \right) =F_{2}\left( \omega ,\cdot \right) \) for every \(\pi _{2}\in \Omega ^{\prime \prime }\) and every \(\omega \in \pi _{2}\) (which is well-defined because of \(\Pi _{2}\)-measurability of \(F_{2}\) in its first coordinate), and the mixed strategies of player 1 in G and \(G^{\prime \prime }\) are identical as they are state-independent. The correspondence \( \left( F_{1},F_{2}\right) \leftrightarrow \left( F_{1},F_{2}^{\prime \prime }\right) \) between mixed strategy-profiles in G and \(G^{\prime \prime }\) obviously preserves both players’ expected payoffs. Thus, G and \(G^{\prime \prime }\) are payoff-equivalent, and hence identical in terms of equilibrium analysis. However, \(G^{\prime \prime }\) has the property that player 1 has no information on the realized state of nature while player 2 is completely informed of it. Thus, in studying equilibria in two-player common-value all-pay auctions, attention can be confined w.l.o.g. to auctions with the latter property.

Note that when a bid cap is such that a complete characterization of equilibrium in conditional “component” auctions \(G^{\prime }\) (which satisfy the first part of (2) and w.l.o.g. satisfy the second part of (2)) is available, then the equilibrium in the original general auction G can also be completely characterized. Thus, our results in Sect. 3 can be stated for general auctions in which player 2 has an information advantage over player 1, provided (3) is satisfied in the “component” auction \( G^{\prime }\) obtained by conditioning on \(\pi _{1}\in \Pi _{1}\) with the highest values. However, we do not know whether a statement similar to that of Claim 1 can be made a general auction G, as even if the claim and its premises hold for some “component” auction obtained from G,  it remains unclear what properties equilibria may possess in other “component” auctions of G.

Proof of the uniqueness of equilibrium in Proposition 1

Fix an equilibrium \((F_{1},F_{2})\) in a common-value all pay auction G satisfying (3). We will prove that \( (F_{1},F_{2})=(F_{1}^{*},F_{2}^{*}).\)

In what follows, for \(k=1,2\) and \(\omega \in \Omega ,\,F_{k}\left( \omega ,\cdot \right) \) will be treated either as a probability measure on \( \left[ 0,d\right] ,\) or as the corresponding c.d.f., sometimes in the same context. Accordingly, for \(A\subset [0,d]\), \(F_{k}\left( \omega ,A\right) \) will stand for the probability that the equilibrium effort of player k,  conditional on \(\omega ,\) belongs of the set A,  and for \(x\in {\mathbb {R}},\,F_{k}\left( \omega ,x\right) \) will stand for the probability that the equilibrium effort of player k,  conditional on \( \omega ,\) is less or equal to x. Also, as \(F_{1}\) is state-independent, \( F_{1}\left( \omega ,\cdot \right) \) will be shortened to \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) ,\) whenever convenient.

We will start the proof by listing the properties and partially characterizing the structure of the strategies in \((F_{1},F_{2})\) in a sequence of lemmas.

Lemma 1

\(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) and \(F_{2}\left( \omega ,\cdot \right) \) are non-atomic on (0, d) for every \(\omega \in \Omega .\)

Proof

If \(F_{k}\left( \omega ,\{c\}\right) >0\) for some \(c\in (0,d),\,k\) and \(\omega ,\) then \(F_{-k}\left( \omega ^{\prime },\left( c-\varepsilon ,c\right] \right) =0\) for the other player \(-k\) and every \( \omega ^{\prime }\in \Omega ,\) and some sufficiently small \(\varepsilon >0.\) But then k would be strictly better off by shifting the probability from c to \(c-\frac{\varepsilon }{2}\), a contradiction to \(F_{k}\) being an equilibrium strategy. \(\square \)

Lemma 2

There is no interval \((a,b)\subset (0,d)\) on which in some state of nature only one player places a positive probability according to his equilibrium strategy.

Proof

If such (ab) existed, there would also exist a positive \(a^{\prime }\) such that only one player (k) places a positive probability on \((a^{\prime },b)\), and it would then be profitable for k to deviate (in at least one state of nature, if this is the informed player 2) by shifting a positive probability from \((a^{\prime },b)\) to \( a^{\prime }\), a contradiction to \(F_{k}\) being an equilibrium strategy. \(\square \)

Lemma 3

There exist \(0\le \beta \le d\) such that \(F_{1}\left( [0,\beta ]_{-}\cup \{d\}\right) \,=1\) (where \([0,\beta ]_{-}\) denotes the interval \([0,\beta )\) if \(\beta >0\) and \([0,0]_{-}=\{0\}\)),  and either the restriction of \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) to \([0,\beta ]_{-}\) has full support on it, or \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) is concentrated on d (i.e., \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) =1\)).

Proof

Suppose first that there is a (non-degenerate) interval \( (a,b)\subset (0,d)\) such that \(F_{1}\left( (a,b)\right) =0\) (and thus \( F_{2}\left( \omega ,(a,b)\right) =0\) for every \(\omega \in \Omega ,\) by Lemma 2), but \(F_{1}\left( \left[ b,d\right) \right) >0\). By increasing b if necessary, it can also be assumed that b is maximal with respect to this property, i.e., that \(F_{1}\left( [b,b+\varepsilon )\right) >0\) for every small enough \(\varepsilon >0.\) However, the expected payoff of player 1 at \(\frac{a+b}{2}\) is strictly bigger than his payoff for any effort in \( [b,b+\varepsilon )\), if \(\varepsilon >0\) is small enough. This contradicts the assumption that \(F_{1}\) is an equilibrium strategy, and shows that there exists no interval (ab) as above. Non-existence of such (ab) together with Lemma 1 now imply the claim of Lemma 3. \(\square \)

Lemma 4

For every \(\omega \in \Omega ,\,F_{2}\left( \omega ,[0,\beta ]_{-}\cup \{d\}\right) \,=1\) if \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) <1\), and \(F_{2}\left( \omega ,\{0\}\cup \{d\}\right) \,=1\) if \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) =1.\)

Proof

In the contrary case there would exist an open subinterval of (0, d) where only player 2 places positive probability, which would contradict Lemma 2. \(\square \)

Lemma 5

\(F_{1}(\cdot )\) cannot be concentrated on d,  and thus (by Lemma 3) the restriction of \(F_{1}\mathrm{(} \cdot \mathrm{)} \) to \([0,\beta ]_{-}\) has full support on \([0,\beta ]_{-}\).

Proof

If, contrary to the assertion, \(F_{1}(\cdot )\) is concentrated on d,  then for each \(1\le i\le n,\,F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\{0\}\cup \{d\}\right) \,=1\) by Lemma 4. It cannot be that all \( F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) are concentrated 0,  or all \( F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) are concentrated on d [in the first case, player 1 would have a profitable deviation to a positive effort near 0,  and in the second case player 1 would have a profitable deviation to 0 since his expected payoff under \(F_{1}\) would be negative, as follow from assumption (3)]. It is easy to see that then there exists \(i^{\prime }\) such that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i^{\prime }},\{0\}\cup \{d\}\right) =1,\) whereas \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) is concentrated on 0 for \(i<i^{\prime }\) and \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) is concentrated on d for \(i>i^{\prime }.\) If \(i^{\prime }\ne n,\) however, \(F_{1}\) (which is concentrated on d) gives player 1 a negative expected payoff by assumption (3) on d,  and thus cannot be a best response. We conclude that \(i^{\prime }=n.\) But then, by lowering his effort from d to a positive effort near zero,  player 1 will save almost the entire cost of effort d, while his loss of utility from winning will not exceed \(\frac{1}{2}p_{n}v_{n}.\) By assumption (3), this will be a profitable deviation, in contradiction to \(F_{1}\) being an equilibrium strategy. \(\square \)

Lemma 6

The interval \(\left[ 0,\beta \right] _{-}\) is non-degenerate, i.e., \(0<\beta \) and hence \(\left[ 0,\beta \right] _{-}=[0,\beta ).\)

Proof

If \(\beta =0\) then both equilibrium strategies prescribe mixtures of effort 0 and effort d. It follows from Lemma 5 that \( F_{1}(\{0\}\cup \{d\})=1\) and \(F_{1}(\{0\})>0\). Then the only strategy \(F_{2} \) of 2 that may constitute a best response to \(F_{1}\) would prescribe d with probability 1 at every \(\omega \in \Omega ,\) and then \(F_{1}\) must be concentrated on 0 [since choosing d will give player 1 a negative expected payoff by assumption (3) on d]. However, no strategy of player 2 can be a best response to such \(F_{1}\), a contradiction. \(\square \)

Lemma 7

If \(1\le i<j\le n\) and \(x\in [0,d]\) (respectively, \(y\in [0,d]\)) is a pure strategy best response of player 2 given \(\left\{ \omega _{i}\right\} \) (respectively, given \(\{ \omega _{j}\} \)) against strategy \(F_{1},\) then \(x\le y.\)

Proof

Assume to the contrary that \(x>y,\) and let \(F_{1}^{-}\) be the function defined by \(F_{1}^{-}\left( z\right) \equiv \lim _{z^{\prime }\nearrow z}F_{1}\left( z^{\prime }\right) \) for every real z. Note that for every \(k=1,\ldots ,n\) and every \(z\in [0,d],\)

$$\begin{aligned} E_{2}\left( \left\{ \omega _{i}\right\} ,F_{1},z\right) =v_{i}\cdot \frac{ F_{1}^{-}(z)+F_{1}(z)}{2}-z. \end{aligned}$$

By assumption on x, y,  we thus have

$$\begin{aligned} v_{i}\cdot \frac{F_{1}^{-}(x)+F_{1}(x)}{2}-x= & {} E_{2}\left( \left\{ \omega _{i}\right\} ,F_{1},x\right) \end{aligned}$$
(22)
$$\begin{aligned}\ge & {} E_{2}\left( \left\{ \omega _{i}\right\} ,F_{1},y\right) =v_{i}\cdot \frac{F_{1}^{-}(y)+F_{1}(y)}{2}-y \end{aligned}$$
(23)

and

$$\begin{aligned} v_{j}\cdot \frac{F_{1}^{-}(x)+F_{1}(x)}{2}= & {} E_{2}\left( \left\{ \omega _{j}\right\} ,F_{1},x\right) \end{aligned}$$
(24)
$$\begin{aligned}\le & {} E_{2}\left( \left\{ \omega _{j}\right\} ,F_{1},y\right) =v_{j}\cdot \frac{F_{1}^{-}(y)+F_{1}(y)}{2}-y. \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Both \(F_{1}^{-}\) and \(F_{1}\) are non-decreasing functions, that are strictly increasing on \([0,\beta )\) by Lemmas 5 and 6; moreover, \(F_{1}(d)>F_{1}(z)\) for any \(z<\beta \) if \(F_{1}(\left\{ d\right\} )>0.\) Thus, if either \( y<\beta ,\) or \(F_{1}(\left\{ d\right\} )>0\) and \(x=d,\) since \(x>y\) and \( v_{j}>v_{i}\) we also have

$$\begin{aligned} (v_{j}-v_{i})\frac{F_{1}^{-}(x)+F_{1}(x)}{2}>(v_{j}-v_{i})\frac{ F_{1}^{-}(y)+F_{1}(y)}{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(26)

But adding (26) to the inequality in (22)–(23) contradicts the inequality obtained in (24)–(25), and so it is impossible for x to exceed y when either \(y<\beta \) or \(F_{1}(\left\{ d\right\} )>0\) and \(x=d\). In the remaining case either \(F_{1}(\left\{ d\right\} )=0\) or \(x<d,\) and (\(x>\))\(y\ge \beta .\) But then x cannot be a best response of player 2 given \(\left\{ \omega _{i}\right\} \), as lowering his bid to \(\beta \) will guarantee him \(v_{i}\) with the same probability as bidding x but at a lesser cost, contrary to the assumption on x. \(\square \)

In keeping with our earlier notation, given \(0\le a\le b\le d\) denote by \( \left[ a,b\right] _{-}\) the interval [ab) if \(b>0\) and the set \(\{0\}\) if \(a=b=0.\)

Lemma 8

For each \(i=1,\ldots ,n\) there exists a (possibly empty or degenerate) subinterval \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\) of \([0,\beta )\) such that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\cup \{d\}\right) \,=1,\) and, if \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\{d\}\right) <1,\) the restriction of \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) to \([0,\beta )\) has full support on \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\).

Proof

If \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\{0\}\cup \{d\}\right) \,=1,\) the claim obviously holds for \(0<a_{i}=b_{i}\) (an empty \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i} \right] _{-}\)), or \(a_{i}=b_{i}=0.\) Assume now that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\{0\}\cup \{d\}\right) \,<1\), but the claim does not hold. Then there are \(0<a<b<\beta \) such that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},(a,b)\right) =0\), but \( F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},[0,a]\right) >0\) and \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},[b,\beta )\right) >0.\) Since \(F_{1}\left( (a,b)\right) >0\), by Lemma 2 there must be \(j\ne i\) such that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{j},(a,b)\right) >0.\) Assume that \(i<j\) (the opposite case is treated similarly). Then there are \( x\in [b,\beta )\) and \(y\in (a,b)\) which are player 2’s pure strategy best responses to \(F_{1}\) given \(\left\{ \omega _{i}\right\} \) and \(\left\{ \omega _{j}\right\} \) respectively. But, since \(x>y,\) this contradicts Lemma 7. Consequently, the restriction of each \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) to \([0,\beta )\) has full support on some \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\). \(\square \)

Lemma 9

For each \(i=1,\ldots ,n-1,\) the set \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\) is non-empty and \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) has full support on \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\). The set \(\left[ a_{n},b_{n} \right] _{-}\) is also non-empty, and the restriction of \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) to \([0,\beta )\) has full support on \(\left[ a_{n},b_{n} \right] _{-}\).

Proof

If there is \(1\le i\le n\) such that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\{d\}\right) >0\), denote by \(i^{\prime }\) the smallest index with this property. By Lemma 7, \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) is concentrated on d for every \(i>i^{\prime },\) and hence, if \(i^{\prime }<n,\,F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) is concentrated on d. Thus

$$\begin{aligned} E_{1}(d^{\prime },F_{2})\le \sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}v_{j}+\frac{1}{2} p_{n}v_{n}-d^{\prime }<0 \end{aligned}$$

by assumption (3) for all efforts \(d^{\prime }\le d\) that are sufficiently close to d. Consequently, the support of the equilibrium strategy \(F_{1}\) of player 1 will exclude some left-hand neighborhood of d. Thus player 2 will not exert effort d at \(\omega _{n}\) with positive probability, a contradiction to \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) being concentrated on d. Thus, even if \(i^{\prime }\) is defined, it must be equal to n,  implying that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\{d\}\right) =0\) for every \(i=1,\ldots ,n-1.\) Thus, by Lemma 8 the distribution \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) has full support on \(\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\subset [0,\beta )\) for \(i=1,\ldots ,n-1\) (and in particular each \( \left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\) is non-empty). As \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) cannot be concentrated on d by the argument above\(,\, \left[ a_{n},b_{n}\right] _{-}\) is also non-empty, and the restriction of \( F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) to \([0,\beta )\) has full support on \( \left[ a_{n},b_{n}\right] _{-}\) by Lemma 8. \(\square \)

Corollary 10

The intervals \(\left\{ [a_{i},b_{i}]_{\_}\right\} _{i=1}^{n}\) are disjoint (barring the set \(\{0\}\)), and “ordered” according to the index i on the interval \([0,\beta ),\) i.e., if \(i<j,\) then \( [a_{i},b_{i}]_{\_}\) lies below \([a_{j},b_{j}]_{\_}\) (or coincides with \( [a_{j},b_{j}]_{\_},\) if \([a_{j},b_{j}]_{\_}=\{0\}\)). Moreover, \(\cup _{i=1}^{n}\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}=[0,\beta ).\)

Proof

It follows immediately from Lemmas 7 and 9 that the intervals are “ordered”. And, if \(\cup _{i=1}^{n}\left[ a_{i},b_{i}\right] _{-}\varsubsetneq [0,\beta )\) then there must be a “gap” (ab) on which only player 1 places positive probability, which contradicts Lemma 2. \(\square \)

Notation

It follows from Corollary 10 that there are points \( 0=y_{0}\le y_{1}\le \cdots <y_{n}\equiv \beta \) such that \([a_{i},b_{i}]_{ \_}=[y_{i-1},y_{i}]_{\_}\) for every \(i=1,2,\ldots ,n,\) i.e., for \(i=1,\ldots ,n-1,\, F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) has full support on \( [y_{i-1},y_{i}]_{\_},\) and the restrictions of \(F^{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) and \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) to \([0,\beta )\) have full support on \([0,y_{n})\) and \([y_{n-1},y_{n})\), respectively. We denote by \( i_{0}\) the smallest integer with \(y_{i_{0}}>0.\) Footnote 18

Since \(F^{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) has full support on \([0,y_{n})\) (when restricted to \([0,y_{n})\)) and \(F_{2}\left( \omega ,\cdot \right) \) has no atoms in \((0,y_{n}),\) player 1 is indifferent between any two efforts in \( (0,y_{n})\). Thus, after denoting

$$\begin{aligned} e_{1}\equiv \lim _{y\searrow 0}E_{1}(y,F_{2})\ge 0, \end{aligned}$$

the following equality must hold for every \(i=i_{0},\ldots ,n\) and every positive \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}):\)

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j=1}^{i-1}p_{j}v_{j}+p_{i}v_{i}F_{2}(\omega _{i},x)-x=E_{1}(x,F_{2})=e_{1}. \end{aligned}$$

In particular,

$$\begin{aligned} F_{2}(\omega _{i},x)=\frac{x-\sum _{j=1}^{i-1}p_{j}v_{j}+e_{1}}{p_{i}v_{i}} \end{aligned}$$
(27)

for every \(i=i_{0},\ldots ,n\) and every \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}).\) Since, for \(i=i_{0}+1,\ldots ,n,\,F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) has full support (after restriction to \([0,\beta )\) for \(i=n\)) on \( [y_{i-1},y_{i})\subset (0,\beta ),\) we have \(F_{2}(\omega _{i},y_{i-1})=0,\) and thus

$$\begin{aligned} y_{i}=\sum _{j=1}^{i}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1} \end{aligned}$$
(28)

for every \(i=i_{0},\ldots ,n-1.\)

Since, for \(i=i_{0},\ldots ,n,\,F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) has full support (after restriction to \([0,\beta )\) for \(i=n\)) on \( [y_{i-1},y_{i})\) and \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) has no atoms (except, possibly, at 0) on \([0,\beta ),\) player 2 is indifferent between all positive efforts in \([y_{i-1},y_{i})\). Thus, the following equality must hold for every positive \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}):\)

$$\begin{aligned} v_{i}F_{1}\left( x\right) -x= & {} E_{2}(\{\omega _{i}\},F_{1},x) \\= & {} \lim _{y\searrow y_{i-1}}E_{2}(\{\omega _{i}\},F_{1},y)=v_{i}F_{1}\left( y_{i-1}\right) -y_{i-1}, \end{aligned}$$

and in particular

$$\begin{aligned} F_{1}\left( x\right) =\frac{x}{v_{i}}+F_{1}\left( y_{i-1}\right) -\frac{ y_{i-1}}{v_{i}}. \end{aligned}$$
(29)

The rest of the proof will separately consider the following cases.

Case 1 Assume that \(e_{1}>0\) or \(i_{0}>1.\)

The assumption of Case 1 implies that either \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i_{0}-1},\cdot \right) \) is concentrated on 0 (if \(i_{0}>1\)) or \( F_{2}\left( \omega _{1},\{0\}\right) >0\) by (27) (if \( i_{0}=1\) but \(e_{1}>0\)). Thus \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) has no atom at 0 (otherwise shifting mass from 0 to a sightly higher effort would constitute a profitable deviation), and hence \(F_{1}\left( 0\right) =0.\) Using this, (28) and (29),  we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} F_{1}\left( x\right) =\frac{x+e_{1}-\sum _{j=1}^{i}p_{j}v_{j}}{v_{i}} +\sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{i}p_{j}+\frac{\sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}}{ v_{i_{0}}} \end{aligned}$$
(30)

for every \(i=i_{0},\ldots ,n,\) and every positive \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}).\)

Case 1.1 Assume that \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) >0.\)

It is a corollary of this assumption that \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\{d\}\right) >0\) (since otherwise for some small \(\varepsilon >0\) and every i we would have \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},(d-\varepsilon ,d]\right) =0,\) and then player 1 could profitably shift probability from d to a lower effort). Note further that having an atom at d by both \(F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) \) and \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\cdot \right) \) implies that these distributions place no probability on an open interval \((d-\varepsilon ,d)\) for some small \(\varepsilon >0,\) and hence

$$\begin{aligned} \beta <d, \end{aligned}$$
(31)

and \(F_{2}\left( \omega _{n},\{d\}\right) =1-F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta ).\) Footnote 19 As \(F_{2}(\omega _{n},\cdot )\) has no atom at \(\beta ,\, F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta )\) is given by (27) for \(x=\beta \) and \(i=n.\) Since \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) >0,\) the expected payoff of player 1 from choosing d must be equal to the expected payoff from choosing effort levels in \((0,\beta ),\) i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} e_{1}= & {} \lim _{y\searrow 0}E_{1}(y,F_{2})=E_{1}(d,F_{2}) \\= & {} \sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}v_{j}+p_{n}v_{n}\left[ F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta )+ \frac{1}{2}\left( 1-F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta )\right) \right] -d \\= & {} \sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}v_{j}+\frac{1}{2}p_{n}v_{n}\left[ F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta )+1\right] -d \\= & {} \sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}v_{j}+\frac{1}{2}p_{n}v_{n}\left[ \frac{\beta -\sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}v_{j}+e_{1}}{p_{n}v_{n}}+1\right] -d \\= & {} \frac{1}{2}\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}+\frac{1}{2}\beta +\frac{1}{2}e_{1}-d. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore

$$\begin{aligned} \beta =2d-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}+e_{1}. \end{aligned}$$
(32)

Since \(F_{2}(\omega _{n},\cdot )\) has full support on \([y_{n-1},\beta )\cup \{d\}\) (as we have seen, d is chosen with positive probability), the conditional expected payoff of player 2 at \(\omega _{n}\) from choosing d must be equal to his conditional expected payoff from choosing effort levels close to (but smaller than) \(\beta ,\) i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} v_{n}F_{1}\left( \beta \right) -\beta= & {} \lim _{x\nearrow \beta }E_{2}(\{\omega _{n}\},F_{1},x) \\= & {} E_{2}(\{\omega _{n}\},F_{1},d)=v_{n}\left[ F_{1}\left( \beta \right) + \frac{1}{2}\left( 1-F_{1}\left( \beta \right) \right) \right] -d \\= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1+F_{1}\left( \beta \right) \right] -d. \end{aligned}$$

It follows, by using (30) and (32) for \(x=\beta \) and \(i=n\),Footnote 20 that

$$\begin{aligned} 0= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1-F_{1}\left( \beta \right) \right] +\beta -d \\= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1-\frac{\left( 2d-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}+e_{1}\right) +e_{1}-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}}{ v_{n}}\right. \nonumber \\&\left. -\sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{n}p_{j}-\frac{\sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}}{ v_{i_{0}}}\right] +\left( 2d-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}+e_{1}\right) -d \\= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1-\sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{n}p_{j}-\frac{ \sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}}{v_{i_{0}}}\right] \\= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ \sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}\left( 1-\frac{v_{j}}{ v_{i_{0}}}\right) +\frac{e_{1}}{v_{i_{0}}}\right] . \end{aligned}$$

But the expression in brackets is positive under the assumptions of Case 1, a contradiction. Thus, the properties assumed in Case 1 and Case 1.1 cannot hold jointly in equilibrium.

Case 1.2 Assume that \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) =0.\)

This assumption implies that \(F_{2}(\omega _{n},\{d\})=0\) as well (since otherwise for some small \(\varepsilon >0\) we would have \(F_{1}\left( (d-\varepsilon ,d]\right) =0,\) and then player 2 could profitably shift mass from d to a lower effort at \(\omega _{n}\)). Thus, \(F_{1}\left( [0,\beta )\right) =\,F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},[0,\beta )\right) \,=1,\) and \( F_{1}\left( \cdot \right) ,\,F_{2}\left( \omega _{i},\cdot \right) \) are non-atomic on \((0,\beta ),\) for each \(i=i_{0},\ldots ,n.\) In particular, formulas (27) and (30) hold for \( x=y_{n}=\beta \) and \(i=n,\) and

$$\begin{aligned} F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta )=F_{1}(\beta )=1. \end{aligned}$$
(33)

It follows from (27) and (33) that

$$\begin{aligned} \beta =y_{n}=\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}. \end{aligned}$$

Thus

$$\begin{aligned} 1= & {} F_{1}(\beta )=\frac{\beta +e_{1}-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}}{v_{i}} +\sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{n}p_{j}+\frac{\sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}}{ v_{i_{0}}} \\= & {} \frac{\left( \sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}\right) +e_{1}-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}}{v_{i}}+\sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{n}p_{j}+\frac{ \sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}}{v_{i_{0}}} \\= & {} \sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{n}p_{j}+\frac{\sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}v_{j}-e_{1}}{ v_{i_{0}}} \\= & {} \sum _{j=i_{0}+1}^{n}p_{j}+\sum _{j=1}^{i_{0}}p_{j}\frac{v_{j}}{v_{i_{0}}}- \frac{e_{1}}{v_{i_{0}}}. \end{aligned}$$

The last expression is smaller than 1, however, under the assumptions of Case 1, a contradiction.

We conclude that the assumptions of Case 1 cannot hold in equilibrium, and consider next the complementary Case 2:

Case 2 Assume that \(i_{0}=1\) and \(e_{1}=0.\)

Given the assumptions, it follows that (27), (28), and (29) can be rewritten in the following way:

$$\begin{aligned} y_{i}=\sum _{j=1}^{i}p_{j}v_{j}\text { }(=x_{i}) \end{aligned}$$
(34)

for every \(i=1,\ldots ,n-1\) (where \(x_{i}\) was defined in (4)), and

$$\begin{aligned} F_{2}(\omega _{i},x)= & {} \frac{x-\sum _{j=1}^{i-1}p_{j}v_{j}}{p_{i}v_{i}}, \end{aligned}$$
(35)
$$\begin{aligned} F_{1}\left( x\right)= & {} \frac{x}{v_{i}}+F_{1}\left( y_{i-1}\right) -\frac{ y_{i-1}}{v_{i}} \end{aligned}$$
(36)

for every \(i=1,\ldots ,n\) and every \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}).\)

Denote \(e_{2}\equiv F_{1}\left( y_{0}\right) \ge 0.\) From (36) and (34) we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} F_{1}\left( x\right) =\frac{x}{v_{i}}+\sum _{j=1}^{i-1}p_{j}\left[ 1-\frac{ v_{j}}{v_{i}}\right] +e_{2} \end{aligned}$$
(37)

for every \(i=1,\ldots ,n\) and every \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}).\)

Case 2.1 Assume that \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) >0.\)

Arguing as in Case 1.1 (but substituting \(e_{1}=0\)), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} y_{n}=\beta =2d-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}\text { }(=\widetilde{x}), \end{aligned}$$
(38)

where \(\widetilde{x}\) was defined in (5), and

$$\begin{aligned} v_{n}F_{1}\left( \beta \right) -\beta =\frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1+F_{1}\left( \beta \right) \right] -d. \end{aligned}$$

Using these equalities and (37), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} 0= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1-F_{1}\left( \beta \right) \right] +\beta -d \\= & {} \frac{v_{n}}{2}\left[ 1-\frac{2d-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}}{v_{n}} -\sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}\left[ 1-\frac{v_{j}}{v_{n}}\right] -e_{2}\right] \\&+\left( 2d-\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}\right) -d=-\frac{v_{n}}{2}e_{2}, \end{aligned}$$

and we conclude that \(e_{2}=0.\) This turns (37) into

$$\begin{aligned} F_{1}\left( x\right) =\frac{x}{v_{i}}+\sum _{j=1}^{i-1}p_{j}\left[ 1-\frac{ v_{j}}{v_{i}}\right] \end{aligned}$$
(39)

for every \(i=1,\ldots ,n\) and every \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}).\)

Due to (34), (35), (38) and (39), the equilibrium strategy profile \((F_{1},F_{2})\) is identical to \((F_{1}^{*},F_{2}^{*})\) described in Sect. 3.

Case 2.2 Assume that \(F_{1}\left( \{d\}\right) =0.\)

Arguing as in Case 1.2 (but substituting \(e_{1}=0\) and \(i_{0}=1\)), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} F_{2}(\omega _{n},\beta )=F_{1}(\beta )=1 \end{aligned}$$
(40)

and

$$\begin{aligned} \beta =y_{n}=\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}. \end{aligned}$$
(41)

(Since \(\beta \le d\le \sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j},\) (41) shows that Case 2.2 can only occur when \(d=\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}.\)) It follows from (37), (40), and (41) that

$$\begin{aligned} 1=\frac{\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}}{v_{n}}+\sum _{j=1}^{n-1}p_{j}\left[ 1-\frac{ v_{j}}{v_{n}}\right] +e_{2}=1+e_{2}, \end{aligned}$$

and hence \(e_{2}=0.\) Thus, (39) also holds in Case 2.2, for every \(i=1,\ldots ,n\) and every \(x\in [y_{i-1},y_{i}).\) It follows from this, together with (34), (35), and (41), that the equilibrium strategy profile \((F_{1},F_{2})\) is identical to \((F_{1}^{*},F_{2}^{*})\) described in Sect. 3 in the case of \(d=\sum _{j=1}^{n}p_{j}v_{j}\). Q.E.D.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Einy, E., Haimanko, O., Orzach, R. et al. Common-value all-pay auctions with asymmetric information and bid caps. Int J Game Theory 45, 63–88 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-015-0492-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-015-0492-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation