Skip to main content
Log in

Structural realism and the nature of structure

  • Original Paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Ontic Structural Realism is a version of realism about science according to which by positing the existence of structures, understood as basic components of reality, one can resolve central difficulties faced by standard versions of scientific realism. Structures are invoked to respond to two important challenges: one posed by the pessimist meta-induction and the other by the underdetermination of metaphysics by physics, which arises in non-relativistic quantum mechanics. We argue that difficulties in the proper understanding of what a structure is undermines the realist component of the view. Given the difficulties, either realism should be dropped or additional metaphysical components not fully endorsed by science should be incorporated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A classification of distinct versions of OSR is presented in Ainsworth (2010).

  2. For a succinct discussion of partial structures and their application in the philosophy of science, see Bueno and da Costa (2007).

  3. Landry (2007) also highlights the intimate connection between the semantic view and set theory, although her concerns are different from ours.

  4. Note that we are not invoking the indispensability argument here, as will become clear below. Our point is that by using set theory, the structural realist is thereby committed to objects—unless a proper nominalization of set theory itself is developed. (But, we will also argue, such a nominalization may conflict with the realist component of structural realism.) Note also that the point goes through independently of how much set theory is ultimately used. So it doesn’t matter whether one is dealing with a highly mathematized science or with a less mathematized one. As long as set theory is used by the structural realist (absent a full nominalization of that theory), a commitment to objects emerges.

  5. One may worry about the full success of Lewis’ construction. Since the notion of inaccessibility is fundamentally set-theoretic in nature, aren’t sets still presupposed (Bueno 2010)? Even if the proposed reconstruction is expressively equivalent to set theory, is it in fact as effective for the formulation of empirical theories as set theory is? These are fair concerns, but they are also beside the point in this context. The purpose of the Lewis example is just to make a conceptual point, namely, that the inseparability and the indispensability theses are not the same. We need not argue that the indispensability thesis is in fact false; only that it can be.

  6. More generally, one of the crucial features of Anjan Chakravartty’s semirealism (Chakravartty 2007) is to argue that realists need the commitment to both objects and some properties and relations—and, thus, some structures—in order to get off the ground. Clearly, given the commitment to objects, this is not a move open to ontic structural realists.

  7. This line of response has been suggested by Steven French and James Ladyman in conversation.

  8. Building from an argument advanced by Bueno 2011, this section examines additional considerations regarding the philosophical significance of elementarily equivalent but non-isomorphic models to the OSR debate.

  9. Demopoulos (2003) also discusses this worry, and he links it to Putnam’s model-theoretic argument and to the semantic view of theories, but it is independent from the concerns we raise here.

  10. For an excellent discussion of second-order logic, see Shapiro (1991).

  11. To ask questions about the metaphysical nature of structures is not forbidden, since ontic structural realists admit that philosophy of science is also in the business of dealing with metaphysical issues arising from science.

  12. We consider the mathematical framework for clarity purposes only. If a metaphysical characterization of structure is advanced independently of any such framework, problems analogous to those raised here will also emerge. After all, the issue of whether the structures in question are individuals or not can always be raised, and the problems discussed in this paragraph will return.

  13. We focus on the particular category of individuality (or non-individuality) of the relevant structures, rather on some other category in metaphysics, since this is the one invoked by ontic structural realists in their case for metaphysical underdetermination. So this is the relevant category to consider in this context.

  14. In this respect, there is a concern for ontic structural realists that their view may collapse into standard scientific realism. Psillos (1999) raises this point for the epistemic version of the view.

  15. Our thanks go to Newton da Costa, Steven French, Décio Krause, and James Ladyman for extremely helpful discussions about the issues examined in this work. An earlier version of the paper was presented at the Epistemology and Philosophy of Science Workshop at the University of Miami. Many thanks for all the feedback we received, in particular, from Ed Erwin, Fredrik Haraldsen, Peter Lewis, Yuki Onishi, and Harvey Siegel. Peter Lewis also gave us detailed and perceptive comments on the entire manuscript, which led to significant improvements. We are very grateful for his help. Thanks are also due to two anonymous reviewers for this journal who also provided extensive and extremely helpful comments. Needless to say, we are responsible for any mistakes and infelicities that remain.

References

  • Ainsworth, P.M. (2010). What is Ontic Structural Realism Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41, 50–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Awodey, S. (2010). Category theory, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Azzouni, J. (2004). Deflating existential consequence. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Azzouni, J. (2011). Nominalistic content. In: Cellucci, C., Grosholtz, E., Ippoliti, E. (Eds.) , Logic and knowledge. Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Newcastle, (pp. 33–51).

  • Bain, J. (2013). Category theoretic structure and radical ontic structural realism. Synthese, 190(9), 1621–1635.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brading, K. (2011). Structuralist approaches to physics: objects, models and modality. In: Bokulich, P., & Bokulich, A. (Eds.) , Scientific structuralism. Springer, Dordrecht, (pp. 43–65).

  • Brading, K., & Landry, E. (2006). Scientific structuralism: presentation and representation. Philosophy of Science, 73, 571–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O. (2010). Can set theory be nominalized? A fictionalist response. In: Woods, J. (Ed.) , Fictions and models: new essays. Munich, Philosophia Verlag, (pp. 191–224).

  • Bueno, O. (2011). Structural empiricism, again. In: Bokulich, P., & Bokulich, A. (Eds.) , Scientific structuralism. Springer, Dordrecht, (pp. 81–103).

  • Bueno, O. (2013). Nominalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.) , Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2013 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/nominalism-mathematics/.

  • Bueno, O., & da Costa, N.C.A. (2007). Quasi-truth, paraconsistency and the foundations of science. Synthese, 154, 383–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A Metaphysics for scientific realism: knowing the unobservabl. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • da Costa, N.C.A., & French, S. (2003). Science and partial truth. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • da Costa, N.C.A., & Rodrigues, A.A.M. (2007). Definability and invariance. Studia Logica, 82, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demopoulos, W. (2003). On the rational reconstruction of our theoretical knowledge. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 371–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Domenech, G., Holik, F., Krause, D. (2008). Quasi-spaces and the foundations of quantum mechanics. Foundations of Physics, 38, 969–994.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • French, S. (2010). The interdependence of structure, objects and dependence. Synthese, 175, 89–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2012). The presentation of objects and the representation of structure. In: Landry, E. M., & Rickles, D.P. (Eds.) , Structural realism. Springer, Dordrecht, (pp. 3–28).

  • French, S., & Krause, D. (2006). Identity in physics: a historical, philosophical and formal analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2003). Remodelling structural realism: quantum physics and the metaphysics of structure. Synthese, 136, 31–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2011). In defence of ontic structural realism. In: Bokulich, P., & Bokulich, A. (Eds.) , Scientific structuralism. Springer, Dordrecht, (pp. 25–42).

  • Krause, D. (2010). Logical aspects of quantum (non-)individuality. Foundations of Science, 15(1), 79–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29(3), 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2013). Structural realism. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.) , Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/structural-realism/.

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Everything must go: metaphysics naturalized (with Spurrett, D. and Collier J.) Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Landry, E. (2007). Shared structure need not be set-structure. Synthese, 158, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Lewis, D. (1993). Mathematics is megethology. Philosophia Mathematica, 3, 3–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E.J. (2006). The four-category ontology: a metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Quine, W.V. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: how science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

  • Redhead, M., & Teller, P. (1991). Particles, particle labels, and quanta: the toll of unacknowledged metaphysics. Foundations of Physics, 21(1), 43–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. (2003). Structural realism, again. Synthese, 136, 127–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1991). Foundations without foundationalism: a case for second-order logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Suppe, F. (2000). Understanding scientific theories: an assessment of developments, 1969-1998. Philosophy of Science, 67, S102–S115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. (1980). The scientific image, (p. 1980). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Votsis, I. (2011). Structural realism: continuity and its limits. In: Bokulich, P., & Bokulich, A. (Eds.) , Scientific structuralism. Springer, Dordrecht, (pp. 105–117).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Otávio Bueno.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Arenhart, J.R.B., Bueno, O. Structural realism and the nature of structure. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 5, 111–139 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0100-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0100-y

Keywords

Navigation