Skip to main content
Log in

Tractable consumer choice

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We present a rational model of consumer choice, which can also serve as a behavioral model. The central construct is \(\lambda \), the marginal utility of money, derived from the consumer’s rest-of-life problem. It provides a simple criterion for choosing a consumption bundle in a separable consumption problem. We derive a robust approximation of \(\lambda \) and show how to incorporate liquidity constraints, indivisibilities, and adaptation to a changing environment. We find connections with numerous historical and recent constructs, both behavioral and neoclassical, and draw contrasts with standard partial equilibrium analysis. The result is a better grounded, more flexible, and more intuitive description of consumer choice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Indeed, \(N\) could even be infinite and not affect our analysis.

  2. Prices that apply to future goods are discounted appropriately. For simplicity, we treat \(L\) as a constant, but later note how it can be endogenized.

  3. In the special case that the same separable subproblem recurs every period, (6) closely resembles the Bellman equation familiar to macroeconomists (where time discounting is built into \(V(.)\)). Note, however, that in general, \( \widetilde{V}\) differs from \(V\) not only in the value of the state variable (remaining wealth) but also in the set of (dated) goods available to purchase.

  4. Of course, expenditure \(L-\mathbf {p}\cdot \mathbf {x}\) available for the continuation problem falls as we move out along the IEP so, by concavity, \( V^{\prime }\) increases. Thus, a more complete informal description is that the falling proportionality factor meets the rising \(V^{\prime }\) at a unique point, \(\mathbf {x}^{*}\), on the IEP; more formally, under present assumptions, the intermediate value theorem and implicit function theorem guarantee a unique smooth interior solution described by (7).

  5. The maximand in (9) slightly generalizes quasi-linear utility. Textbook treatments (e.g., Varian 1992, p. 154, 164–167) often assume that \(n=1\) so the variable of interest \(x\) is scalar, and that \(\widehat{\lambda }=1\). In our notation, the textbook quasi-linear utility function would be written as \(u(x)+m\) with budget constraint \(m=L-px.\) Our approach shows that textbook quasi-linear preferences can be justified for single separable goods, and can be generalized directly for separable bundles of related goods. Given a constant exogenous \(\lambda \), there is no loss of generality in using a VNM utility function for \(u\) (and implicitly, \( U\)) that normalizes its value to 1, but our analysis sheds light on the conditions for which the constancy assumption is justified.

  6. For given constant \(\lambda ,\) the Frisch demand function is formally equivalent to \(\mathbf {x}^{\lambda }\), notwithstanding important differences in interpretation (see the second segment of Appendix ).

  7. This is intuitive, as a constant \(\lambda \) means that there are no income effects. As an empirical matter, it is not clear that Giffen goods exist at all (c.f. Dwyer and Lindsay 1984; Nachbar 1998), with the possible exception of extreme poverty (c.f. Jensen and Miller 2008) when indeed we would not expect consumers to take the future into account and to exhaust whatever purchasing power they have.

  8. Only approximately linear because \(\beta \) is a second derivative evaluated at a point that can depend on \(y\).

  9. The logic is reminiscent of quasi-hyperbolic discounting: there is a big difference between today and tomorrow, but tomorrow and the day after look similar from the vantage point of today.

  10. Here we assume, for simplicity, that the consumer does not try to extrapolate from individual observed prices to changes in the price level. See Deaton (1977) for an exploration of that idea.

  11. Textbooks often refer to \(\mathbf {x}^{B}\) as the Marshallian demand function, in distinction to the Hicksian demand function which holds constant the utility level rather than \(B\) or \(\lambda \). The literature survey in Appendix will note that \(\mathbf {x}^{B}\) actually owes more to Hicks than to Marshall, whose preferred demand function was a special case of \(\mathbf {x}^{\lambda }.\)

  12. For the single good case, we have the following simplified expressions

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial x^{*}}{\partial p}(\widehat{p})&= \frac{ \lambda - BV^{\prime \prime }(L-B)}{u^{\prime \prime }(x^{*})-p^2V^{\prime \prime }(L-B)}, \\ \frac{\partial x^{\lambda }}{\partial p}(\widehat{p})&= \frac{\lambda }{ u^{\prime \prime }(x^{*})}, \text{ and } \\ \frac{\partial x^{B}}{\partial p}(\widehat{p})&= \frac{ B}{p^2}. \end{aligned}$$
  13. If such a consumer is faced with several purchasing decisions (subproblems) subject to a unified liquidity constraint, then Eq. (27) and Fig. 1, with \(q=0\) and \(r=\infty \), apply only to the final decision. For the prior decisions, she should still use the unconstrained \( \lambda \) rule, where the constraint will be built into her continuation (indirect) utility. When the borrowing constraint binds, the consumer’s time horizon effectively shrinks to a single pay period. This would decrease the precision of the estimate of \(\lambda ,\) leading to a normative and a positive prediction. First, the final decision should incorporate more goods than usual to decrease the bias in \(\lambda .\) Second, as the estimate is an underestimate—as \(V^{\prime }(L-px)>V^{\prime }(L)\)—paycheck-to-paycheck consumers using the moneysworth demand should be bad at consumption smoothing and get to the end of the month short of money.

  14. Hauser and Urban (1986) pose as alternative hypotheses that consumers use “value for money,” \(u/p,\) or “net value,” \(u-\lambda p,\) to prioritize purchases of indivisibles. Our analysis shows that the two rankings are equivalent for yes/no decisions, but we shall now show that “net value” is the appropriate criterion for mutually exclusive alternatives.

  15. Note that this crucial detail is overlooked in the melioration theory of Herrnstein and Prelec (1991), which posits that the option with higher utility per $ is the one that is chosen (in a distributed choice problem).

  16. Note that for yes/no decisions the quality-price ratio is also incremental but the benchmark is normalized to zero.

  17. We suspect that it is also quite descriptive of actual consumer behavior, but we are not aware of any empirical studies so far that compare the predictive power of \(\mathbf {x}^{\lambda }\) and \(\mathbf {x}^{B}\).

  18. In public finance, for example, it is well known that a uniform income tax is more efficient for raising a given amount of revenue than a collection of specific taxes on individual items.

  19. Arguably, revealed preference theory is the real contribution of ordinality. A companion paper (Sákovics 2013) shows that revealed preference theory has a cardinal counterpart, with the Generalized Axiom of Revealed Preference replaced by the stronger Axiom of Revealed Valuation (ARV). Formally, assume that we have \(T\) observations of a consumer’s chosen bundles, \(x^{t}\in \mathfrak {R}_{+}^{n},\) at price vectors, \( p^{t}\in \mathfrak {R}_{++}^{n}\). Let \(a_{tj}=p^{t}\cdot (x^{j}-x^{t})\) denote the pecuniary advantage of the chosen bundle, \(x^{t}\), relative to an arbitrary bundle, \(x^{j}.\) Then ARV states For every ordered subset \( \{i,j,k,...,s\}\subseteq \{1,2,...,T\}, \ \ a_{ij}+a_{jk}+...+a_{si}\ge 0.\) The main theorem states If and only if the observed choices satisfy ARV, they are rationalizable by a cardinal utility function of the form \( u(x)-\lambda p\cdot x\).

  20. Allen (1933) interpreted Frisch’s constant \(\lambda \) as an unjustified imposition of additional restrictions on the utility function. Eventually, Brown and Calsamiglia (2003) noted that Frisch demand functions are better understood as related to Marshall’s theory of consumer demand.

  21. Heckman (1974) was apparently the first to use \(\lambda \)-constant comparative statics in such models. Bewley (1977) proposed a consumer theory for the lifetime problem using the constancy of marginal utility of money. See Bewley (2007, Chapt. 8.3) for a recent synthesis.

  22. See also Bordalo et al. 2013, for a related model based on the salience of past observations.

  23. We have chosen the \(i\)th coordinates as we will be checking sensitivity to the \(i\)th price.

References

  • Allen, R. G. D. (1933). On the marginal utility of money and its application. Economica, 40, 186–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1802). Theory of legislation. Edited by E. Dumont, translated from the original French by C.M. Atkinson in 1914. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bernoulli, D. (1738). Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis. English translation, “Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk”. Econometrica, 22, 23–26.

  • Bewley, T. (1977). The permanent income hypothesis: A theoretical formulation. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 252–292.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bewley, T. (2007). General equilibrium, overlapping generations models, and optimal growth theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Biswas, T. (1977). The Marshallian consumer. Economica, 44(173), 47–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bordalo, P., Gennaioli, N., & Shleifer, A. (2013). Salience and consumer choice. Journal of Political Economy, 121(5), 803–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. J., & Calsamiglia, C. (2003). The Strong Law of Demand. Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 1399.

  • Browning, M. (2005/1985). A working paper from April 1985: Which demand elasticities do we know and which do we need to know for policy analysis? Research in Economics, 59, 293–320.

  • Browning, M., Deaton, A., & Irish, M. (1985). A profitable approach to labor supply and commodity demands over the life-cycle. Econometrica, 53(3), 503–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cramer, G. (1728). Letter to Nicolas Bernoulli. Reprinted in Bernoulli (1738).

  • Deaton, A. (1977). Involuntary saving through unanticipated inflation. American Economic Review, 67(5), 899–910.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deaton, A. (1992). Understanding consumption. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, G. P, Jr, & Lindsay, C. M. (1984). Robert Giffen and the Irish potato. American Economic Review, 44(1), 188–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T., & Frankish, K. (Eds.). (2009). In two minds: Dual processes and beyond. New York: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. J. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. The Journal of Political Economy, 56(4), 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, R. (1932). New methods of measuring marginal utility. Tubingen: J.C.B Mohr (Paul Siebeck).

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, R. (1959). A complete scheme for computing all direct and cross demand elasticities in a model with many sectors. Econometrica, 27, 177–196.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Genesove, D., & Mayer, C. (2001). Loss aversion and seller behavior: Evidence from the housing market. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(4), 1233–1260.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gennaioli, N., & Shleifer, A. (2010). What comes to mind. Quarterly Journal of Economics, CXXV(4), 1399–1433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, J. R., & Urban, G. L. (1986). The value priority hypotheses for consumer budget plans. Journal of Consumer Research, 12(4), 446–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heckman, J. (1974). Life cycle consumption and labor supply: An explanation of the relationship between income and consumption over the life cycle. American Economic Review, 64(1), 88–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrnstein, R. J., & Prelec, D. (1991). Melioration: A theory of distributed choice. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(3), 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heymann, D., & Leijonhufvud, A. (1995). High Inflation. The Arne Ryde Memorial Lectures. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

  • Hicks, J. R., & Allen, R. G. D. (1934). A reconsideration of the theory of value. Economica, Part I: 1(1), 52–76. Part II, 1(2), 196–219.

  • Jensen, R. T., & Miller, N. H. (2008). Giffen behavior and subsistence consumption. American Economic Review, 98(4), 1553–1577.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking. Farrar, Straus and Giroux: Fast and Slow.

  • Knutson, B., Rick, S., Wimmer, G. E., Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, G. (2007). Neural predictors of purchases. Neuron, 53, 147–156.

    Article  PubMed Central  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Love, D. A. (2013). Optimal rules of thumb for consumption and portfolio choice. The Economic Journal, 123(September), 932–961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, A. (1890/1920). Principles of economics. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nachbar, J. H. (1998). The last word on Giffen goods? Economic Theory, 11(2), 403–412.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, G. (1998). The red and the black: Mental accounting of savings and debt. Marketing Science, 17(1), 4–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: A calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68(5), 1281–1292.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Read, D., Lowenstein, G., & Rabin, M. (1999). Choice bracketing. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 19(1–3), 171–197.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Sákovics, J. (2013). Revealed cardinal preference. Economic Theory Bulletin, 1(1), 39–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2000). Individual differenves in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 645–665.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. J. (1950). The development of utility theory. I. Journal of Political Economy, 58, 307–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H. (1999). Mental accounting matters. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12(3), 183–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian, H. R. (1992). Microeconomic analysis (3rd ed.). New York: W.W. Norton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper supersedes the previously circulated “The marginal utility of money: a new Marshallian approach to consumer choice.” We thank Olga Rud Rabanal for research assistance. For helpful suggestions, we thank two anonymous referees of this Journal, as well as Luciano Andreozzi, Buz Brock, Roberto Burguet, Andrew Clausen, Joan-Maria Esteban, Steffen Huck, Axel Leijonhufvud, Youn Kim, Michael Mandler, Albert Marcet, Carmen Matutes, David de Meza, Ryan Oprea, Martin Shubik, Peter Simmons, Nirvikar Singh, Hal Varian, Donald Wittman, and seminar audiences at Barcelona GSE, Cambridge, CEU (Budapest), Edinburgh, Glasgow, Roy Seminar (Paris), UBC-UHK Summer Micro Seminars (Hong Kong), UCIII (Madrid), UC at Santa Cruz, and York (England).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to József Sákovics.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Friedman, D., Sákovics, J. Tractable consumer choice. Theory Decis 79, 333–358 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-014-9461-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-014-9461-0

Keywords

Navigation