Skip to main content
Log in

The metaphysics of natural kinds

  • S.I. : Causation in Metaphysics
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper maps the landscape for a range of views concerning the metaphysics of natural kinds. I consider a range of increasingly ontologically committed views concerning natural kinds and the possible arguments for them. I then ask how these relate to natural kind essentialism, arguing that essentialism requires commitment to kinds as entities. I conclude by examining the homeostatic property cluster view of kinds in the light of the general understanding of kinds developed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Hacking (1991) for a historical survey.

  2. ‘Naturalism’ can mean a fair variety of things in philosophy (Papineau 2009). One quite general understanding is that a (methodologically) naturalistic approach to Xs means that the truth about Xs can and can only be discovered by using the methods of science. Regarding natural kinds that means that science can discover which natural kinds there are and what they are like (for many kinds if not for all), and that we cannot do this a priori (which we could if kinds were entirely conventional).

  3. In this paper I do not address questions concerning the structure of natural kind classifications. Do natural kinds always come in hierarchies? If so, does any given natural entity belong at most to one hierarchy (monism)? Or could an entity belong to more than one system of natural classification?

  4. I say ‘typically’, because I do not wish to assert that kind membership is an intrinsic property of an entity. Often it is, but membership of a biological kind may well depend on origin, which will be a relational rather than intrinsic property of an object.

  5. Quine (1969, pp. 137–138) does remark that, “In general we can take it as a very special mark of the maturity of a branch of science that it no longer needs an irreducible notion of similarity and kind.” But Quine is not referring to the elimination of kinds specifically but rather to the elimination of qualitative properties, such as colour, in favour of quantitative ones, such as mass.

  6. Much of the blame for the tendency to ignore the kindhood question in favour of the naturalness question can be placed on the habit, found in Quine’s article for example, to take the discussion of Goodman’s new riddle of induction to be central to understanding natural kinds. But, as Mill would have pointed out, even if green things are naturally similar and grue things are not, it remains the case that green things do not form a natural kind.

  7. For an extended discussion of this point, see Bird (2009); Needham 2012); Bird 2012).

  8. I do not ask whether there is an difference between characterization of essence in terms of identity or nature: no such difference will affect my argument.

  9. Not in the Cartesian sense that the content of the essence of God implies that God exists. Rather, the fact that some x has an essence implies that x exists.

  10. Isn’t the round square essentially square? I see no reason to agree. I have argued that the nature of non-existent entities is obscure, and the nature of impossible entities is even more obscure.

  11. Of course, this leaves it open that it is essential to the concept unicorn that it is the concept of a mythical creature. But that is consistent with the essence implies existence thesis, since that thesis would imply on the existence of the concept unicorn, which is not in doubt.

  12. Abbott (1997, p. 312) points out that to “get Putnam’s results one does not need to use terms like ‘reference ’ or ‘extension’ ...All one need to ask is whether ...such-and-such a substance would be water”.

  13. Devitt notes in response to criticism by Schwartz (2002, p. 275) that he does not claim that it is the function of rigid designation to distinguish natural from non-natural kinds. However, this criticism is different, since Devitt does regard it as a secondary function of an account of rigid designation that it explain, even if only superficially, the modal features of kind and general terms. Thus while his view does not need to account for the distinction between natural and non-natural kinds, it ought to identify the distinction between those general terms which are associated with essences and those which are not.

  14. It is important to note that species membership is not a matter of genotype (cf. Ridley (2003); but see also Devitt (2008), who denies this). It is true that members of a species will be genetically similar, but there will often be no unique genetic character that they all share but is not shared by anything outside the species—particularly if we consider members of the same species that come from different points in the species’ evolutionary history. In particular, a certain mutation may in due course lead to a speciation event, but the arrival of that mutation cannot itself be regarded as the arrival of a new species, at least not for sexually reproducing species. The organism with the new mutation will need to breed with organisms without it. If the mutated organism is the first member of the new species, then its offspring from mating with a non-mutated member of the old species will be members of which species? Furthermore, since mutations are frequent, the arrival of not just any mutation will create a new species; it will have to spread throughout a significant subpopulation, leading to splitting of the original population. If the mutation is the speciation event, then whether or not it counts as a speciation event will depend on subsequent events—the spreading of the mutation and the splitting of the populations. In which case whether or not an organism belongs to species S at t will depend on events occurring later than t, which seems at least undesirable.

  15. The cross-temporal counterparts are not the four-dimensional objects; rather they are time-slices. Note that David Lewis’s motivation for transworld counterparts, the problem of accidental intrinsics is the analogue of his reason for adopting time-slices, the problem of temporary intrinsics (Lewis 1986b, pp. 202–204, 210–220).

  16. Another example of items that change their kind might be stem cells, which are able to become cells of a specific kind that they did not previously belong to (I owe this example to Peter Farleigh). In particular, induced pluripotent stem cells start out as adult stem cells and are reprogrammed to become pluripotent stem cells and thereafter become specific specialised cells of widely varying kinds, depending on their environment (here I owe thanks to an anonymous referee). Devitt himself accepts that not all natural kind terms apply rigidly, citing Schwartz’s example of ‘frog’: an individual that is a tadpole may become a frog, but might not have done. I don’t mention this example, because it is not obvious that frogs (in this sense) form a natural kind, since ‘frog’ is a phase sortal. If some phase sortals can be natural kinds, then there are many counterexamples, including not only biological phases (pupa, embryo, etc.) but also stellar phases.

  17. Or if one does want to allow existence to the kind of which wedding rings are mostly made, as an abundant property perhaps, then the argument allows us to distinguish those from the natural kinds, since the essences of the latter are of a different sort.

  18. See Bird (2011) for a more detailed discussion of this point.

  19. Indeed, the proposal considered make kinds look like the senses or intensions of kind terms, whereas the kinds themselves should be the referents of such terms.

  20. An on-off property can be accommodated by their characteristic function: 0 for lacking the property, 1 for possessing it.

  21. Note that while such a view sees kinds as complex universals rather than particulars, the analogue with concrete particulars means that it can accommodate many of the insights that the view of species as individuals (Hull 1976).

  22. This conclusion does not exclude the possibility that alternatives to the HPC view may also cohere with the metaphysical conclusions reached here.

  23. Although I presented the answers to subsequent questions as building on positive answers to earlier questions, leading to the a maximally committed metaphysics of kinds, there may be positions that allow for a combination of negative responses to earlier questions with positive answers to later ones [e.g. a social constructivist about ontology might answer ‘no’ to (Q1) and ‘yes’ to (Q3)], and so a full account of all the possibilities for a metaphysics of natural kinds may see these questions as providing a matrix rather than a decision tree, as Huw Price has suggested to me.

References

  • Abbott, B. (1997). A note on the nature of “water”. Mind, 106, 311–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1978). A theory of universals. Universals and scientific realism (Vol. II). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1989). Universals: An opinionated introduction. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J. (1986). Towards structural universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 94–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1989). A theory of structural universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 67, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. J. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. J. (2009). Are natural kinds reducible? In A. Hieke & H. Leitgeb (Eds.), Reduction-abstraction-analysis (pp. 127–136). Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. J. (2011). Are any kinds ontologically fundamental? In T. Tahko (Ed.), Contemporary Aristotelian metaphysics (pp. 94–104). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. J. (2012). Referring to natural kind thingamajigs, and what they are: A reply to Needham. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26, 103–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, R. (2000). Against quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 87–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1990). Realism, conventionality, and ‘realism about’. In G. Boolos (Ed.), Meaning and method: Essays in honor of Hilary Putnam (pp. 171–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism, and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999a). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999b). Kinds, complexity, and multiple realization. Philosophical Studies, 95, 67–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2005). Rigid application. Philosophical Studies, 125, 139–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M., & Sterelny, K. (1999). Language and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1993). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1994). Dispositional essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers: A defence of nominalism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 8: Logic and language (pp. 1–16). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1986). The foundations of arithmetic, trans. J. L. Austin (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical essences. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 208–228). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1991). A tradition of natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 109–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1993). Working in a new world: The taxonomic solution. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (1987). Abstract objects. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2010). Mereology, modality and magic. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88, 117–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K., & Bird, A. J. (2011). What are natural kinds? Philosophical Perspectives, 25, 205–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Zoology, 25, 174–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1979). Metaphor in science. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (pp. 409–419). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (2000). Social construction and the philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986a). Against structural universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 25–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986b). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690). An essay concerning human understanding, 1964th edn. London: Fontana.

  • Lowe, E. J. (1989). Kinds of being. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martí, G. (2004). Rigidity and general terms. Proceeding of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2009). Chicken, eggs, and speciation. Noûs, 43, 94–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J. (1958). The theory of evolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1942). Systematics and the origin of species from the viewpoint of a zoologist. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1976). On the necessity of origin. The Journal of Philosophy, 73, 127–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive. References to the 1974 edition. In J. M. Robson (ed.). Toronto: University of Toronto Press

  • Millikan, R. (1999). Historical kinds and the “special sciences”. Philosophical Studies, 95, 45–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Needham, P. (2012). Natural kind thingamajigs. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26, 97–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131, 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2009). Naturalism. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, spring 2009 edition edn.

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers (pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1969). Natural kinds. In W. V. Quine (Ed.), Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 114–138). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (2003). Evolution (3rd ed.). Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Quiddistic knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 123, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (Ed.). (1977). Naming, necessity, and natural kinds. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (2002). Kinds, general terms, and rigidity. Philosophical Studies, 109, 265–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause (pp. 109–135). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Venn, J. (1866). The logic of chance. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1983). Frege’s conception of numbers as objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to audiences at the Inland Northwestern Philosophy Conference 2008, at the University of Idaho, the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society’s annual conference 2008 in Kichberg am Wechsel, the University of Sheffield, the Cambridge Serious Metaphysics group, Saint Louis University, the University of Melbourne, the University of Sydney, the Australian National University, IHPST in Paris, the Metaphysics of Science conference in Nottingham 2009, and the Metaphysics of Science conference at Kyung Hee University, South Korea in 2010, as well as to anonymous referees for Synthese.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Bird.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bird, A. The metaphysics of natural kinds. Synthese 195, 1397–1426 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0833-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0833-y

Keywords

Navigation