Skip to main content
Log in

What Was Wrong with Eugenics? Conflicting Narratives and Disputed Interpretations

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although it is often taken for granted that eugenics is odious, exactly what makes it so is far from obvious. The existence of considerable interpretative flexibility is evident in the disparate policy lessons for contemporary reproductive genetics (or “reprogenetics”) that have been derived from essentially the same set of historical facts. In this paper, I will show how different—indeed, diametrically-opposed—morals have been drawn from the history of eugenics and link these contrasting messages both to different underlying conceptions of what constitutes the central wrong of eugenics and differing degrees of enthusiasm for reprogenetic technologies. I will then argue that, for several reasons, the history of eugenics simply cannot provide the kind of direct guidance that many participants in current debates would like. Although the history does have implications for policy, the insights to be gleaned are both subtle and indirect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Both thought that character and temperament could be read from the body, but phrenologists were concerned with conformations of the skull and physiognomists with bodily and especially facial characteristics more generally.

  2. Readers who would like an overview of Anglo-American eugenics might consult Kevles (1995) or Paul (1995). For an excellent introduction to the recent international historiography of eugenics, see Levine and Bashford (2010).

  3. Lee M. Silver, a biophysicist who teaches in the Department of Molecular Biology at Princeton University, originally coined the term “reprogenetics” to denote the convergence of genetic and reproductive technologies such as in vitro fertilization. It is typically employed broadly to include research and interventions involving both gametes and embryos (Knowles and Kaebnick 2007, p. ix).

  4. In his insightful essay on sterilization in Sweden, Torbjörn Tännsjö (1998, pp. 240) notes that there are at least three quite different and indeed inconsistent objections to sterilization policy, and that depending on which one is accepted, we will condemn different agents in the past and also favor different policy recommendations for the future.

  5. Michael Sandel (2004) also remarks on the underlying assumption that voluntary choices “are not really eugenic--at least not in the pejorative sense. To remove the coercion […] is to remove the very thing that makes eugenic policies repugnant.”

  6. They seem to have established a beachhead of sorts at the University of Oxford, where philosopher Nick Bostrom, who co-founded the World Transhumanist Association or WTA (renamed Humanity + in 2008), directs The Future of Humanity Institute. (Bostrom is also affiliated with the Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, directed by fellow reprogenetic enthusisast Julian Savulescu).

  7. The distinction between “transhumanism” and “posthumanism” is not always clear, but typically transhumans are considered to have capacities somewhere between those of unaugmented humans and greatly enhanced posthumans.

  8. Tom Shakespeare (2006, pp. 85–88), who is himself a disability-rights activist, provides an excellent critique of a tendency among activists to equate contemporary reproductive practices with Nazi programs.

  9. Typical of this genre is “Margaret Sanger, Sterilization, and the Swastika” (Richmond 1997), where the link between Sanger and Nazism is made by identifying institutions for eugenical segregation as concentration camps and Sanger’s views with those of contributors to her journal, even after she had resigned as its editor.

  10. Sanger is also featured on creationist websites, where she is identified not only with eugenics but Darwinism. For example, see Bergman 2008.

  11. Allan Brandt (2006) provides a thoughtful analysis of both the strengths and limitations of policy-relevant history.

References

  • Agar, N. (2004). Liberal eugenics: In defense of human enhancement. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, K. A. (2010). The honor code: How moral revolutions happen. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appleyard, B. (1999). Brave new worlds: Genetics and the human experience. London: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergman, J. (2008). Birth control leader Margaret Sanger: Darwinist, racist and eugenicist. Journal of Creation, 22(3), 62–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, A. (2006). From analysis to advocacy: Crossing boundaries as a historian of health policy. In F. Huisman & J. H. Warner (Eds.), Locating medical history: The stories and their meanings. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., Brock, D. W., Daniels, N., & Wikler, D. (2000). From chance to choice: genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, A. L. (2000). What is morally wrong with eugenics? In P. R. Sloan (Ed.), Controlling our destinies: Historical, philosophical, ethical, and theological perspectives on the human genome project (pp. 209–222). Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, R. S. (2008). Heredity and hope: The case for genetic screening. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, C. J. (2003). Is modern genetics the new eugenics? Presidential address delivered at the 2003 annual clinical genetics meeting of the American College of Medical Genetics, San Diego, CA. Reprinted in Genetics in Medicine, 5(6), 469–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erler, A. (2010). Eugenics or ‘reprogenetics’: Call it what you will, but let’s do it, Practical Ethics: Ethics in the News (Feb. 24). http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2010/02/eugenics-or-reprogenetics-call-it-what-you-will-but-lets-do-it/ Accessed 25 Sept. 2011.

  • Glover, J. (2006). Choosing children: Genes, disability, and design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green, R. M. (2007). Babies by design: The ethics of genetic choice. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (2007). Enhancing evolution: The ethical case for making better people. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilliard, M. T. (2010). The new eugenics: Eliminating the ‘undesirable’ by prenatal diagnosis. http://home.catholicweb.com/odccw/files/The_New_Eugenics.pdf. Accessed 9 Jan. 2012.

  • Hughes, J. (2004). Do Transhumanists Advocate Eugenics? http://www.transhumanism.org/index.php/WTA/more/66/. (27 April). Accessed on 17 Sept. 2011.

  • Hume, J. (1996). Disability, feminism and eugenics: Who has the right to decide who should or should not inhabit the world.” http://www.wwda.org.au/eugen.htm. Accessed 5 Oct. 2011.

  • ICTA [International Center for Technology Assessment]. (2011). Human biotechnology: The age of the “new eugenics.” http://www.icta.org/biotech/index.cfm. Accessed 28 Sept. 2011.

  • Kevles, D. J. (1995). In the name of eugenics: Genetics and the uses of human heredity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1997). The lives to come: The genetic revolution and human possibilities. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knowles, L. P., & Kaebnick, G. E. (2007). Reprogenetics: Law, policy, and ethical issues. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, P., & Bashford, A. (2010). Introduction: Eugenics in the modern world. In A. Bashford & P. Levine (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of the history of eugenics (pp. 3–24). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombardo, P. (2008). Three generations, no imbeciles: Eugenics, the Supreme Court, and buck v. Bell. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margaret Sanger Papers Project. (2002–2003). The Sanger-Hitler equation. (Winter). http://www.nyu.edu/projects/sanger/secure/newsletter/articles/sanger-hitler_equation.html. Accessed 4 Oct. 2011.

  • Meehan, M. (2009). Triumph of eugenics in prenatal testing. Part I. How it happened, Human Life. Review, 35(3), 28–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumayr, G. (2005). The new eugenics. The American Spectator (June), 22–25. http://www.hum.utah.edu/~bbenham/2510%20Spring%2009/Neumyer-The%20new%20eugenics.pdf. Accessed 28 Sept. 2011.

  • Paul, D. B. (1995). Controlling human heredity: 1865 to the present. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pence, G. E. (2000). Maximize parental choice. In G. Stock & J. Campbell (Eds.), Engineering the Human Germline: An Exploration of the Science and Ethics of Altering the Genes We Pass on to Our Children (pp. 111–113). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richmond, M. (1997). Margaret Sanger, sterilization, and the swastika. Address to the New History Society, New York City (Jan. 17). The Ethical Spectacle 3(9). http://www.spectacle.org/997/richmond.html. Accessed 4 Oct. 2011.

  • Rosenberg, C. E. (2007). The new enchantment: Genetics, medicine, and society, Our Present Complaint: American Medicine, Then and Now (pp. 96–112). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, on 101, 107.

  • Rothschild, J. (2005). The dream of the perfect child. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. J. (2004). The case against perfection. The Atlantic (April), 293(3), 51–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. (2005). New breeds of humans: The moral obligation to enhance”. Reproductive BioMedicine Online, 10(Supp 1), 36–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J., & Kahane, G. (2009). The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life”. Bioethics, 23(5), 274–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmalz, V. (2006). Casual eugenics: Prenatal screening has become a death sentence for the disabled, Catholic World Report (Aug/Sept), 18-22. http://www.webparish.com/prolife/documents/CasualEugenics.pdf. Accessed 28 Sept. 2011.

  • Shakespeare, T. (2006). Disability rights and wrongs. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silver, L. M. (2000). Reprogenetics: How reproductive and genetic technologies will be combined to provide new opportunities for people to reach their reproductive goals. In G. Stock & J. Campbell (Eds.), Engineering the human Germline: An exploration of the science and ethics of altering the genes we pass on to our children (pp. 57–72). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. (2008). Politically correct eugenics, Weekly Standard 13(28). Available at: http://www.weeklystandard.com/Content/Public/Articles/000/000/014/915cuzel.asp.

  • Stock, G. (2002). Redesigning Humans: Our Inevitable Genetic Future. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stock, G. & Campbell, J. (Eds.) (2000). Engineering the Human Germline: An Exploration of the Science and Ethics of Altering the Genes We Pass on to Our Children. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Sutherland, J. (2005). The ideas interview: Julian Savulescu. Eugenics need not be Nazi, and drugs in sport are good, Oxford’s leading ethicist tells John Sutherland. The Guardian (9 October). http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2005/oct/10/genetics.research. Accessed 22 Sept. 2011.

  • Tännsjö, T. (1998). Compulsory sterilisation in Sweden. Bioethics, 12(3), 236–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tough, P. (2011). The Poverty Clinic, New Yorker (21 March), 25–32.

  • Wikler, D. (1999). Can we learn from eugenics? Journal of Medical Ethics, 25, 183–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Will, G. F. (2005). Eugenics by abortion, Washington Post (14 April), A27.

  • Young, N. (2005). Autism prenatal testing. [Interview with Bonnie Ventura]. http://www.aspergianpride.com/prenatal.shtml. Accessed 28 Sept. 2011.

Download references

Acknowledgments

A small amount of material in this essay originally appeared in “On Drawing Lessons from the History of Eugenics,” in Lori P. Knowles and Gregory E. Kaebnick, eds., Reprogenetics: Law, Policy, and Ethical Issues, copyright 2007 by The Johns Hopkins University Press, reprinted by permission of the publisher. The author would also like to thank two anonymous reviewers for very helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Diane B. Paul.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Paul, D.B. What Was Wrong with Eugenics? Conflicting Narratives and Disputed Interpretations. Sci & Educ 23, 259–271 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9556-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9556-3

Keywords

Navigation