Skip to main content
Log in

Without pretense: a critique of Goldman’s model of simulation

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I criticize Alvin Goldman's simulation theory of mindreading which involves the claim that the basic method of folk psychologically predicting behaviour is to form pretend beliefs and desires that reproduce the transitions between the mental states of others, in that way enabling to predict what the others are going to do. I argue that when it comes to simulating propositional attitudes it isn't clear whether pretend beliefs need to be invoked in order to explain relevant experimental results, and whether pretend desires can be distinguished from 'real' ones as forming a separate kind of mental states. Since belief-desire model underlies the conception of pretend states in higher-level mindreading, dropping pretend attitudes from the picture isn't possible and, due to that, this model may be incoherent. Nevertheless, Goldman's theory could still survive because it includes an additional model of mindreading, but simulation is given much lesser role there.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For some classic accounts, see Wellman (1990), Stich and Nichols (1993), Baron-Cohen (1995), Gopnik and Meltzoff (1997).

  2. Ignoring rather big differences between them, probably the most important accounts of simulation theory can be found from Goldman (1989), Gordon (1986), Heal (2003).

  3. This kind of defensive strategy can be found from numerous passages in his book (e.g. Goldman 2006, 34; 83; 89; 140; 164; 170; 174; 184).

  4. To do justice to Goldman, he already hints towards hybrid theory in his 1989 paper (Goldman 1989, 88) and admits a necessity of a “mixed model” in his (1992, 22).

  5. This paper entirely ignores the issue of low-level mindreading, the understanding of emotions, where Goldman’s approach is probably much more promising.

  6. What additionally characterizes that simulation model is the quarantining mechanism which is supposed to keep subject’s real attitudes from entering the simulation procedure because they may diverge from the attitudes of the target and shouldn’t obstruct the simulation process. The aim is, after all, to get other’s attitudes right and these may not correspond to subject’s own (Goldman 2006, 29).

  7. For a proposal to bring both phenomena under an unified theory of thinking, see Hesslow (2002).

  8. I’m not even sure if they are meant to demonstrate that. But since the objects of interest here are pretend beliefs and pretend desires, this is the only place in Goldman’s book which can be interpreted as an attempt to argue for the cognitive reality of pretend beliefs.

  9. The idea of similar functional effects between imagination and belief is quite popular and is also reflected in so-called “single-code hypothesis”. For a tentative defense, see Nichols (2006).

  10. I actually love broccoli. The example was chosen while keeping in mind experiments by Repacholi and Gopnik (1997) who discovered that already 18-year-old children are able to understand other’s wishes that diverge from their own. If the arguments presented here have force then one shouldn’t assume–if anyone does–that children pretend to desire broccoli.

  11. Why take the desire concerning Holmes, rather than the desire about fiction, to be a pretend desire? Well, since Holmes doesn’t exist, the desire for his success could be considered as irrational if it were conceived of as a real desire. One could claim that pretend desires, unlike the real ones, need not follow the requirements of rationality (Currie 2002: 211).

  12. It is interesting to note that Doggett and Egan themselves lean toward the neural criterion (2007: 12).

  13. I should note that Funkhouser and Spaulding see desires as inherently motivating, which I denied. Nothing hangs from that in the present context, though.

  14. Experimental results indicate that the endowment effect in one’s own valuations appears also in ascribing valuations to others, which indicates that the subject is projecting one’s own valuations to the other person (Van Boven et al. 2000).

  15. Of course, if we allow theoretical information to contribute also to the input of the mindreading process (as hybrid theorists can allow), then the quarantining mechanism may be of use initially, in keeping the theorizing accurate. But then the projection-plus-theory model–which is already a hybrid model, in any case–would rather be a theory-plus-projection-plus-theory model where the projection would turn out to be much less significant than Goldman seems to require.

  16. The work on this paper has been supported by Estonian Science Foundation Grant GFLFI9117.

References

  • Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 54(7), 462–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. (1996). Automaticity of social behavior: direct effects of trait construct and stereotype activation on action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71(2), 230–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1995). Imagination and simulation: Aesthetics meets cognitive science. In M. Davies & T. Stone (Eds.), Mental simulation (pp. 151–169). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (2002). Desire in imagination. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 201–221). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. D. (2002 [1987]). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Doggett, T., & Egan, A. (2007). Wanting things you don’t want: the case for an imaginative analogue of desire. Philosophers’ Imprint, 7(9), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funkhouser, E., & Spaulding, S. (2009). Imagination and other scripts. Philosophical Studies, 143, 291–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, S. M., Weaver, K., Moskowitz, G. B., & Darley, J. M. (2002). Crowded minds: the implicit bystander effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83(4), 843–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1989). Interpretation psychologized. Mind & Language, 4(3), 161–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1992). Empathy, mind, and morals. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 66(3), 17–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind & Language, 1(2), 158–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. (2003). Mind, reason, and imagination. Selected essays in philosophy of mind and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hesslow, G. (2002). Conscious thought as simulation of behaviour and perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(6), 242–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2001). Neural simulation of action: a unifying mechanism for motor cognition. NeuroImage, 14, S103–S109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2011). The puzzle of imaginative desire. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(3), 421–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2013). Entertaining as a propositional attitude: a non-reductive characterization. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(1), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meskin, A., & Weinberg, J. (2003). Emotions, fiction, and the cognitive architecture. British Journal of Aesthetics, 43(1), 18-34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2006). Just the imagination: why imagining doesn’t behave like believing. Mind & Language, 21(4), 459–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Craven, K. M., & Kanwisher, N. (2000). Mental imagery of faces and places activates corresponding stimulus-specific brain regions. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 12(6), 1013–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Repacholi, B. M., & Gopnik, A. (1997). Early reasoning about desires: evidence from 14- and 18-month-olds. Developmental Psychology, 33(1), 12–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, T. (2004). Three faces of desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spivey, M. J., Richardson, D. C., Tyler, M. J., Young, E. E. (2000). Eye movements during comprehension of spoken scene descriptions. Proceedings of the 22nd annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 487–492). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

  • Stich, S. P., & Nichols, S. (1993). Folk psychology: simulation or tacit theory? Mind & Language, 7(1–2), 35–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P., & Nichols, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., Dunning, D., & Loewenstein, G. (2000). Egocentric empathy gaps between owners and buyers: misperceptions of the endowment effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79(1), 66–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. (1990). The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yue, G., & Cole, K. (1992). Strength increases from the motor program: comparison of training with maximal voluntary and imagined muscle contractions. Journal of Neuropsychology, 67(5), 1114–1123.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Uku Tooming.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Tooming, U. Without pretense: a critique of Goldman’s model of simulation. Phenom Cogn Sci 14, 561–575 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9343-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9343-x

Keywords

Navigation