Skip to main content
Log in

Binary tense and modality

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present paper adopts as its point of departure the claim by Te Winkel (1866) and Verkuyl (2008) that mental temporal representations are built on the basis of three binary oppositions: Present/Past, Synchronous/Posterior and Imperfect/Perfect. Te Winkel took the second opposition in terms of the absence or presence of a temporal auxiliary zullen ‘will’. However, in a binary system Future loses the status it has in a ternary analysis as being at the same level as Past and Present. The present paper shows that Present and Past already may express posterior information, there being no temporal role for zullen ‘will’. Grice’s Maxim of Quantity determines which sort of interpretation (current or posterior) is to be associated with Present or Past. The infinitival form of zullen ‘will’ should be seen as an epistemic modal operator with a specific role in the interaction between speaker and hearer. This operator will be argued to be positioned between the first and the third opposition. The binary approach is not restricted to Dutch and so it points to a fundamental flaw in Kissine (2008) which proposed that the English auxiliary will is (only) temporal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This has been proposed for English will and shall (e.g., Palmer 1974; Hornby 1975; Comrie 1985; Hornstein 1990); for German werden (e.g., Saltveit 1962; Dieling 1982; Ballweg 1988) and for Dutch zullen (e.g., Den Hertog 1903; Haeseryn et al. 1997).

  2. Dutch: Paardekooper (1957), Droste (1958), Kirsner (1969), Janssen (1988); German: Vater (1975), Erb (2001); English: Quirk and Greenbaum (1973), Huddleston and Pullum (1975), Palmer (2001), Stowell (2012), among others. The literature on German werden suggests that this verb comes close to Dutch zullen (cf. Janssen 1989).

  3. Verkuyl (2008) discusses in detail the tense systems of languages such as French, Chinese, Bulgarian, Georgian and English, arguing that the three binary oppositions occur in each of them albeit in different choices made by the languages in question.

  4. The italicized labels in the cells of Table 1 are the ones that we will use in this study for the eight tense forms occurring in Dutch even though the terms used for the four posterior forms will turn out to be less felicitous due to our claim that zullen ‘will’ does not belong to the temporal system.

  5. Jespersen (1924:258f.) discusses the notion of present time along the same line but there is a crucial difference. Jespersen considers the present in sentences like (4) and (5) as an extension of the present ‘now’, which it is not in the binary system under discussion: n partitions the present domain i.

  6. The binary analysis solves the problem for Lekakou and Nilsen (2008) raised by the principle proposed in Giorgi and Pianesi (1997) which says that a closed event may not be simultaneous with a punctual event. Lekakou and Nilsen take n as the present and so the Giorgi/Pianesi-principle excludes the Present Perfect from pertaining to n. By separating the notion of present from the notion of shifting point, the binary approach does not have any problem in (14) with locating k in i a up to and including n.

  7. One of the few to discuss a present tensed form of a modal auxiliary in terms of tense morphology is Sarkar (1998:92f). See also Kirsner (1969:119f); Janssen (1988:119).

  8. It is not possible to render the present tensed sentence Vrijdag is ze klaar in (3d) into the past sentence Vrijdag was ze klaar in (18d′) without losing its posterior sense. It is a factual statement about the past with no posteriority expressed. However, it suffices to add dan ‘then’ to obtain the posterior: Vrijdag was ze dan klaar (lit: Friday she was then ready) may pertain to an expectation expressed at n′.

  9. The type-logical conventions are borrowed from Verkuyl (2008). For example, the post-operator introduced in the fourth line of (32) is of type 〈〈i,t〉,〈i,t〉〉, taking the formula of type 〈i,t〉 in the third line in order to yield an expression of type 〈i,t〉 in the fifth line, where i is the type of indices. This representation is close to event-semantics but the indices i, j and k are all taken as numbers standing for temporal units, much in the way in which 23 in March 23 stands for a natural day. Thus, k corresponds closely to the e of event semantics, but the representation in (32) abstracts from ontological (naive physical) considerations. Hence the possibility of using ≺ for the relation ‘earlier than but contained in’ much in the way in which 3 precedes 4 but is also included in 4. ∃!i is short for: ∃i′ [i′=i…] along the lines of Blackburn (1994) discussed earlier. The present analysis remains neutral with regard to a presuppositional or assertive approach to tense.

  10. This places our research in a tradition in which Kratzer (1991a, 1991b), Enç (1996), Zimmermann (2000), Condoravdi (2002), Geurts (2005), Kissine (2008), Sarkar (1998), Nauze (2008) among many others are guided by the seminal work by Kripke (1963) and Lewis (1979) and made available technically in works like Hughes and Cresswell (1968), Thomason (1984), Gabbay and Guenthner (1984:Vol. II).

  11. Metaphysical modality plays no role in our analysis except as the background for all more specific sorts of modality. Only if different sorts of modality need to be kept apart, will we use the three terms or subscripts available.

  12. The rather informal notation of Enç is adapted to our notation. \(\mbox {$ [ \! [ \alpha ] \! ]$}_{\langle w,n\rangle} = 1\) means that α is true given a pair 〈w,n〉, which indicates that w is a world with a history in which n is a time. The variable t ranges over times taken as intervals.

  13. Kissine’s verb come is replaced here to evade the implicit deixis of this verb as well as it implicit appeal to its being actualized in the future, sing being a more neutral alternative.

  14. Apart from that it is also puzzling why (39b) has ‘not all w’ (∼ there is a w′) as the negation of ‘all w′’ rather than ‘no w′’. In other words, why does Kissine choose here the external negation of the all-quantifier rather than internal negation as it would be in the line of Enç?

  15. The literature on generalized quantification is abundant. We restrict ourselves here to Keenan and Westerståhl (1997); Peters and Westerståhl (2006).

  16. As observed earlier, Mischa moest spelen (Mischa past + must play) and Dat huis op de hoek stortte in ‘That house at the corner collapsed’ are less suitable for a posterior interpretation because Dutch prefers to use Mischa zou moeten spelen (lit: Mischa would must play) and Dat huis op de hoek zou instorten ‘That house at the corner would collapse.’

  17. In spoken language, it often happens that speakers will utter (57a) or (57b), but they are always prepared to admit that what they just said has an air of saying it twice or of strengthening the modal content.

  18. Iatridou and Zeijlstra (2010) observe that the deontic moeten ‘must’ scopes over negation as in Mischa moet niet spelen (‘Mischa must not play’). They explain this by assuming that must is a positive polarity item. We are not sure whether this carries over to the epistemic modal zullen ‘will’.

  19. It is interesting to see that the addition of niet ‘not’ to (59c) neutralizes as it were the difference between a current and posterior interpretation: collapsing is easier to locate as an eventuality either in i a or in i than not collapsing as a non-event. This leads to a sort of neutrality with respect to where to locate k.

  20. For example, in his discussion of the Chinese tense system Verkuyl (2008:162–179) suggests that the syn/post-opposition may occur in order to compensate for the absence of an (overt) pres/past-opposition.

  21. This is in line with Abusch (1997), Von Stechow (1995), Condoravdi (2002), Vincent (2010), among others.

  22. Condoravdi (2002:71) defines it as “a function, fixed by the context of use, from world-time pairs to sets of worlds,” namely those worlds compatible with the knowledge of the speaker.

  23. The distinction made by Condoravdi (2002) between stative and eventive predicates seems to be a different one than between durative and terminative. In terms of the well-known tripartition between aspectual classes—States, Processes and Events—Condoravdi seems to make an opposition between States on the one hand, and Processes + Events on the other. Unfortunately she uses the verb get in demonstrating her point. Thus get sick is opposed to be sick.

References

  • Abusch, Dorit. 1997. Sequence of tense and temporal de re. Linguistics and Philosophy 20: 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abusch, Dorit. 1998. Generalizing tense semantics for future contexts. In Events and grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein, 13–33. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ballweg, Joachim. 1988. Die Semantik der Deutschen Tempusvormen. Vol. 70 of Die Sprache der Gegenwart. Düsseldorf: Schwann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Patrick. 1994. Tense, temporal reference, and tense logic. Journal of Semantics 11: 83–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borer, Hagit. 1994. The projection of arguments. In Functional projections, eds. Elena Benedicto and Jeffrey Runner. Vol. 17 of Umass working papers in linguistics, 19–47. Amherst: GSLA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comrie, Bernard. 1985. Tense. Cambridge textbooks in linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Condoravdi, Leo. 2002. Temporal interpretation of modals: Modals for the present and for the past. In The construction of meaning, eds. David Beaver, Stefan Kaufmann, Brady Clark, and Luis Casillas, 59–88. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Den Hertog, C.H. 1903. Nederlandsche Spraakkunst. Amsterdam: W. Versluys.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieling, Klaus. 1982. Das Hilfsverb werden als Zeit- und als Hypothesenfunktor. Zeitschrift für Germanistik 3: 325–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Droste, Flip G. 1958. Het temporele in het moderne Nederlands. De Nieuwe Taalgids 51: 305–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enç, Mürvet. 1996. Tense and modality. In The handbook of contemporary semantic theory, ed. Shalom Lappin, 345–358. Oxford: Blackwell, Chap. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erb, Marie Christine. 2001. Finite auxiliaries in German. PhD diss, University of Tilburg, Tilburg.

  • Gabbay, Dov, and Franz Guenthner, eds. 1984. Handbook of philosophical logic. Vol. II of Extensions of classical logic synthese library 165. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, Bart. 2005. Entertaining alternatives: Disjunctions as modals. Natural Language Semantics 13: 383–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giorgi, Alessandra, and Fabio Pianesi. 1997. Tense and aspect. From semantics to morphosyntax. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, eds. Peter Cole and J. L. Morgan, 41–58. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haeseryn, Walter, Kirsten Romijn, Guido Geerts, Jaap de Rooij, and Maarten C. van den Toorn. 1997. Algemene nederlandse spraakkunst. Groningen/Deurne: Martinus Nijhoff/Wolters Plantyn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornby, Albert Sydney. 1975. Guide to patterns and usage in English, 2nd edn. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornstein, Norbert. 1990. As time goes by: Tense and universal grammar. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huddleston, Rodney, and Geoffrey Pullum. 1975. The Cambridge grammar of the English language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. E., and M. J. Cresswell. 1968. An introduction to modal logic. London: Methuen & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iatridou, Sabine, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2010. Negation, polarity and deontic modals. In Logic, language and meaning: 17th Amsterdam colloquium., eds. Maria Aloni, Harald Bastiaanse, Tikitu de Jager, and Katrin Schulz. Vol. 6042 of Lecture notes in computer science, 315–324. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, Theo A. J. M. 1988. Tense and temporal composition in Dutch. In Temporalsemantik, eds. Veronika Ehrich and Heinz Vater, 96–128. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, Theo A. J. M. 1989. Die Hilfsverben werden (Deutsch) und zullen (Niederländisch): modal oder temporal? In Tempus–Aspekt–Modus. Die lexikalischen und grammatischen Formen in den germanischen Sprachen, eds. Werner Abraham and Theo Janssen, 65–84. Tübingen: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jespersen, Otto. 1924. The philosophy of grammar. London: George Allen and Unwin. Tenth Impression [1968].

    Google Scholar 

  • Keenan, Edward L., and Dag Westerståhl. 1997. Generalized quantifiers in linguistics and logic. In Handbook of linguistics and logic, eds. Johan van Benthem and Alice ter Meulen, 837–893. Amsterdam: Elsevier, Chap. 15.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsner, Robert. 1969. The role of zullen in the grammar of modern standard Dutch. Lingua 24: 101–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kissine, Mikhail. 2008. Why will is not a modal. Natural Language Semantics 16: 129–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1991a. Conditionals. In Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, eds. Arnim von Stechow and Dieter Wunderlich, 651–656. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1991b. Modality. In Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, eds. Arnim von Stechow and Dieter Wunderlich, 639–650. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, Saul. 1963. Semantical considerations on modal logics. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16: 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lekakou, Marika, and Øystein Nilsen. 2008. What aspect can tell us about the future of must. In Proceedings of the 8th international conference of Greek linguistics. Ioannina: University of Ioannina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1979. Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs 13: 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nauze, Fabrice Dominique. 2008. Modality in typological perspective. PhD diss, University of Uppsala, Amsterdam.

  • Paardekooper, P. C. 1957. De tijd als spraakkunstgroep in het ABN. De Nieuwe Taalgids 50: 38–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, F. R. 1974. The English verb. London: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, F. R. 2001. Mood and modality, 2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, Barbara H., Alice ter Meulen, and Robert E. Wall. 1990. Mathematical methods in linguistics. Vol. 30 of Studies in linguistics and philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Stanley, and Dag Westerståhl. 2006. Quantifiers in language and logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, Arthur. 1967. Past, present and future. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quirk, Randolph, and Sidney Greenbaum. 1973. A university grammar of English. London: Longman. Based on A grammar of contemporary English by Randolph Quirk, Sidney Greenbaum, Geoffrey Leech and Jan Svartvik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans. 1947. Elements of symbolic logic, First free press paperback edition 1966 edn. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saltveit, Laurits. 1962. Besitzt die deutsche Sprache ein Futur? Der Deutschunterricht 12: 46–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Anoop. 1998. The conflict between future tense and modality: The case of will in English. Penn Working Papers in Linguistics 5: 91–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stowell, Tim. 2012. Syntax. In The Oxford handbook of tense and aspect, ed. Robert I. Binnick, 184–211. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Chap. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Te Winkel, L. A. 1866. Over de wijzen en tijden der werkwoorden. De Taalgids 8: 66–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, Richard. 1984. Combinations of tense and modality. In Handbook of philosophical logic, eds. Dov Gabbay and Franz Guenthner. Vol. II of Extensions of Classical Logic of Synthese library 165, 135–165. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vater, Heinz. 1975. Werden als Modalverb. In Aspekte der Modalität, ed. J. P. Calbert & H. Vater, 71–148. Tübingen: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl, Henk J. 2008. Binary tense. Vol. 187 of Csli lecture notes. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincent, Homer. 2010. Epistemic modals: High ma non troppo. In Proceedings of NELS 40, 14. Amherst: GSLA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Stechow, Arnim. 1995. On the proper treatment of tense. Vol. 5 of SALT, 362–386.

  • Zimmermann, Thomas Ede. 1999. Scepticism de se. Erkenntnis 51: 267–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, Thomas Ede. 2000. Free choice disjunction and epistemic modality. Natural Language Semantics 8: 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We have profited very much from Frank Veltman and Hedde Zeijlstra for very valuable discussions and feedback on versions presented to them. We also are grateful for the detailed and constructive remarks of the two reviewers on the prefinal version. We thank Andrei Stoevsky for his detailed criticism of that version. We would like to thank Johan van Benthem, Marcel den Dikken and Jan Wouter Zwart for their reactions on the consequences of doing away with temporal zullen ‘will’. We would like to thank audiences at the universities in Amsterdam (Meertens), Antwerp, Budapest, Groningen and Utrecht (UIL OTS). All responsibility for the present version is ours.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans Broekhuis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Broekhuis, H., Verkuyl, H.J. Binary tense and modality. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 32, 973–1009 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-013-9213-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-013-9213-9

Keywords

Navigation