Skip to main content
Log in

Distributed Cognition in Scientific Contexts

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Even though it has been argued that scientific cognition is distributed, there is no consensus on the exact nature of distributed cognition. This paper aims to characterize distributed cognition as appropriate for philosophical studies of science. I first classify competing characterizations into three types: the property approach, the task approach, and the system approach. It turns out that the property approach and the task approach are subject to criticism. I then argue that the most preferable way to understand distributed cognition in science is provided by the system approach that takes a distributed-cognitive system as the unit of analysis. I clarify this position by considering possible objections and replies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It might be better to give psychological evidence for the limit of human calculation ability rather than to simply speculate although it does not undermine the point that I made. To my knowledge, however, there is no concrete empirical research on this. Rather, I think it is useful to mention two things among the world record of Mental Calculation World Cup. In the task of adding ten 10-digit numbers, Naofumi Ogasaware in 2012 produced 10 correct results in 3:11 min. In the task of multiplying two 8-digit numbers, Marc Jornet Sanz in 2010 produced 10 correct results in 4:56 min. It is excusable to say that at first approximation, those records might be close to the limit of human ability.

  2. You can notice that it is a sufficient condition for being a part of a distributed-cognitive system, allowing that some non-contributive parts might consist in the system. While I cannot reject the possibility decisively, I believe that the possibility is not among typical scientific cases of distributed cognition.

  3. Giere (2002, 294) suggests that a proper part of a system should “differentially influence” to the outputs “in scientifically relevant way”. This is meant to exclude the features that “merely make it possible for the system to generate any output at all.” I believe that by adopting the notion of semantic information processing, (DCS2-S) provides a clearer way to distinguish a proper part of a system from environments.

References

  • Brown, M. J. (2011). Science as socially distributed cognition: Bridging philosophy and sociology of science. In K. François, B. Löwe, T. Müller, & B. van Kerkhove (Eds.), Foundations of the formal sciences VII: Bringing together philosophy and sociology of science. v. 32 of Studies in Logic.

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2011). Semantic conceptions of information. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (spring 2011 Edition).

  • Fresco, N. (2012). The explanatory role of computation in cognitive science. Minds and Machines, 22, 353–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2002). Scientific cognition as distributed cognition. In P. Carruthers, S. P. Stich, & M. Siegal (Eds.), The cognitive basis of science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Giere, R. (2003). The role of computation in scientific cognition. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 15, 195–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2007). Distributed cognition without distributed knowing. Social Epistemology, 21(3), 313–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R., & Moffatt, B. (2003). Distributed cognition: Where the cognitive and the social merge. Social Studies of Science, 33(2), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr-Cetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures: How the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Magnus, P. D. (2007). Distributed cognition and the task of science. Social Studies of Science, 37(2), 297–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClamrock, R. (1995). Existential cognition: Computational minds in the world. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2005). Interpreting scientific and engineering practices: Integrating the cognitive, social, and cultural dimensions. In M. Gorman, R. Tweney, D. Gooding & A. Kincannon (Eds.), Scientific and Technological Thinking: Erlbaum.

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2006). Model-based reasoning in distributed cognitive systems. Philosophy of Science, 73, 699–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osbeck, L. M., & Nersessian, N. J. (2006). The distribution of representation. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 36, 141–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Scarantino, A. (2010). Computation vs information processing: Why their difference matters to cognitive science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 237–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poirier, P., & Chicoisne, G. (2006). A framework for thinking about distributed cognition. Pragmatics and Cognition, 14(2), 215–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 1–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(4), 625–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Forms of aggregativity. In A. Donagan, N. Perovich & M. Wedin (Eds.), Human nature and natural knowledge (pp. 259–293). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Wimsatt, W. (1997). Aggregativity: Reduction heuristics for finding emergence. Philosophy of Science, 64, S372–S384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2000). Emergence as non-aggregativity and the biases of reductionisms. Foundations of Science, 5, 269–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B. (2007). Who has scientific knowledge? Social Epistemology, 21(3), 337–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J. (1997). The nature of external representations in problem solving. Cognitive Science, 21, 179–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J., & Norman, D. A. (1994). Representations in distributed cognitive tasks. Cognitive Science, 18, 87–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J., & Patel, V. (2006). Distributed cognition, representation, and affordance. Pragmatics and Cognition, 14(2), 333–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Edouard Machery and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I also thank Dongwook Jung, Wonki Her, and the members of Philosophy of Science Working Group, Seoul National University for useful discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hyundeuk Cheon.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cheon, H. Distributed Cognition in Scientific Contexts. J Gen Philos Sci 45, 23–33 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9226-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9226-4

Keywords

Navigation