Skip to main content

Scientific Models Are Distributed and Never Abstract

A Naturalistic Perspective

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Models and Inferences in Science

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 25))

  • 593 Accesses

Abstract

In the current epistemological debate scientific models are not only considered as useful devices for explaining facts or discovering new entities, laws, and theories, but also rubricated under various new labels: from the classical ones, as abstract entities and idealizations, to the more recent, as fictions, surrogates, credible worlds, missing systems, make-believe, parables, functional, epistemic actions, revealing capacities. This article discusses these approaches showing some of their epistemological inadequacies, also taking advantage of recent results in cognitive science. I will substantiate my revision of epistemological fictionalism reframing the received idea of abstractness and ideality of models with the help of recent results related to the role of distributed cognition (common coding) and abductive cognition (manipulative).

The biological memory records, known as engrams, differ from the external symbols, or exograms, in most of their computational properties […]. The conscious mind is thus sandwiched between two systems of representation, one stored inside the head and the other outside […]. In this case, the conscious mind receives simultaneous displays from both working memory and the external memory field. Both displays remain distinct in the nervous system.

Merlin Donald, A Mind So Rare. The Evolution of Human Consciousness, 2001.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In philosophical tradition visual perception was viewed very often like a kind of inference (Kant 1929; Fodor 1983; Gregory 1987; Josephson and Josephson 1994). On visual perception as model-based abduction cf. chapter five of my book (Magnani 2009); its semi-encapsulated character is illustrated in Raftopoulos (2001a, b, 2009).

  2. 2.

    I have discussed this experiment in detail in Magnani (2012).

  3. 3.

    On this issue cf. Bertolotti (2012).

  4. 4.

    It has to be added that Suárez does not conflate scientific modeling with literary fictionalizing. He clearly distinguishes scientific fictions from other kinds of fictions—the scientific ones are constrained by both the logic of inference and, in particular, the requirement to fit in with the empirical domain (Suárez 2009, 2010)—in the framework of an envisaged compatibility of “scientific fiction'' with realism. This epistemological acknowledgment is not often present in other stronger followers of fictionalism.

  5. 5.

    I discussed the role of chance-seeking in scientific discovery in Magnani (2007). For a broader discussion on the role of luck and chance-seeking in abductive cognition see also Bardone (2011).

  6. 6.

    Representational delegations are those cognitive acts that transform the natural environment in a cognitive one.

  7. 7.

    The concept of cognitive niche is illustrated in detail in Odling-Smee et al. (2003). I adopted this interesting biologically oriented concept in my epistemological and cognitive research (Magnani 2009, Chap. 6), but also as an useful and synthetic theoretical tool able to clarify various puzzling problems of moral philosophy, (Magnani 2011, Chap. 4).

  8. 8.

    An analysis of the differences between models in biology and physics and of the distinction between natural, concrete, and abstract models is illustrated in Rowbottom (2009); unfortunately, the author offers a description of abstract models that seems to me puzzling, and falls under some of the criticism I am illustrating in the present article.

  9. 9.

    On the cognitive delegations to external artifacts see Magnani (2009, Chap. 3, Sect. 3.6). A useful description of how specific “formats” also matter in the case of external hypothetical models and representations, and of how they provide different affordances and inferential chances, is illustrated in Vorms (2010).

  10. 10.

    See also Chandradekharan (2014).

  11. 11.

    The detailed analysis of some seminal Peircean philosophical considerations concerning abduction, perception, inference, and instinct, which I consider are still important to current cognitive and epistemological research, is provided in Magnani (2009, Chap. 5).

  12. 12.

    On the puzzling problem of the “modal” and “amodal” character of the human brain processing of perceptual information, and the asseveration of the importance of grounded cognition, cf. Barsalou (2008a, b).

  13. 13.

    “The basic argument for common coding is an adaptive one, where organisms are considered to be fundamentally action systems. In this view, sensory and cognitive systems evolved to support action, and they are therefore dynamically coupled to action systems in ways that help organisms act quickly and appropriately. Common coding, and the resultant replication of external movements in body coordinates, provides one form of highly efficient coupling. Since both biological and nonbiological movements are equally important to the organism, and the two movements interact in unpredictable ways, it is beneficial to replicate both types of movements in body coordinates, so that efficient responses can be generated” (Chandrasekharan 2009, p. 1069): in this quoted paper the reader can find a rich reference to the recent literature on embodied cognition and common coding.

  14. 14.

    On the concept of multimodal abduction see Chap. 4 of Magnani (2009).

  15. 15.

    Written natural languages are intertwined with iconic aspects too. Stjernfelt (2007) provides a full analysis of the role of icons and diagrams in Peircean philosophical and semiotic approach, also taking into account the Husserlian tradition of phenomenology.

  16. 16.

    It is from this perspective that—for example—[sentential] syllogism and [model-based] perception are seen as rigorously intertwined. Consequently, there is no sharp contrast between the idea of cognition as perception and the idea of cognition as something that pertains to logic. Both aspects are inferential in themselves and fruit of sign activity. Taking the Peircean philosophical path we return to observations I always made when speaking of the case of abduction: cognition is basically multimodal.

  17. 17.

    To confront critiques and suspects about the legitimacy of the new number \( dx \), Leibniz prudently conceded that \( dx \) can be considered a fiction, but a “well founded” one. The birth of non-standard analysis, an “alternative calculus” invented by Robinson (Robinson 1966), based on infinitesimal numbers in the spirit of Leibniz’s method, revealed that infinitesimals are not at all fictions, through an extension of the real numbers system \( {\mathbb{R}} \) to the system \( {\mathbb{R}}^{*} \) containing infinitesimals smaller in the absolute value than any positive real number.

  18. 18.

    Myself I have already emphasized the importance of taking into account the dynamic aspects of science when criticizing the epistemology of models as “missing systems”: in the case of creative inferences the missing system is not, paradoxically, the one represented by the “model”, but instead the target system itself, still more or less largely unknown and un-schematized, which will instead appear as “known” in a new way only after the acceptation of the research process results Magnani (2012, pp. 21–24).

  19. 19.

    I extendedly treated the relationship between cognition and violence in my Magnani (2011).

  20. 20.

    I am deriving this expression from Thom (1988), who—in my opinion—relates “military intelligence” to the role played by language and cognition in the so-called coalition enforcement, that is at the level of their complementary effects in the affirmation of moralities and related conducts, and the consequent perpetration of possible violent punishments.

  21. 21.

    Indeed, in the recent epistemological debate about fictions, even the whole “experimental systems” are reframed as “materialized fictional ‘worlds’” Rouse (2009, p. 51).

  22. 22.

    Giere usefully notes that “Tolstoy did not intend to represent actual people except in general terms” and that, on the contrary, a “primary function [of models in science], of course, is to represent physical processes in the real world” (Giere 2007, p. 279).

  23. 23.

    On the powerful and unifying analysis of inter-theory relationships, which involves the problem of misrepresenting models—and their substitution/adjustement—and of incompleteness of scientific representation, in terms of partial structural similarity, cf. Bueno and French (2011) and the classic (da Costa and French 2003).

  24. 24.

    On the related problem of resemblance (similarity, isomorphism, homomorphism, etc.) in scientific modeling some preliminary comments are provided in Magnani (2012).

  25. 25.

    This distinction parallels the one illustrated by Morrison between models which idealize (mirroring the target systems) and abstract models (more creative and finalized to establish new scientific intelligibility). On this issue cf. Magnani (2012).

  26. 26.

    “In Sarsi [Lothario Sarsi of Siguenza is the pseudonym of the Jesuit Orazio Grassi, author of The Astronomical and Philosophical Balance. In The Assayer, Galileo weighs the astronomical views of Orazio Grassi about the nature of the comets, and finds them wanting (Galilei 1957, p. 231)]. I seem to discern the firm belief that in philosophizing one must support oneself upon the opinion of some celebrated author, as if our minds ought to remain completely sterile and barren unless wedded to the reasoning of some other person. Possibly he thinks that philosophy is a book of fiction by some writer, like the Iliad or Orlando Furioso, productions in which the least important thing is whether what is written there is true. Well, Sarsi, that is not how matters stand. Philosophy is written in this grand book, the universe, which stands continually open to our gaze. But the book cannot be understood unless one first learns to comprehend the language and read the letters in which it is composed. It is written in the language of mathematics, and its characters are triangles, circles, and other geometric figures without which it is humanly impossible to understand a single word of it; without these, one wanders about in a dark labyrinth” (Galilei 1957, pp. 237–238).

References

  • Bardone, E.: Seeking Chances. From Biased Rationality to Distributed Cognition. Springer, Heidelberg (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W.: Cognitive and neural contributions to understanding the conceptual system. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 17(2), 91–95 (2008a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W.: Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59, 617–645 (2008b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwich, A.-S.: Science and fiction: analysing the concept of fiction in science and its limits. J. Gen. Philos. Sci. 44, 357–373 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertolotti, T.: From mindless modeling to scientific models. The case of emerging models. In: Magnani, L., Li, P. (eds.) Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Western and Eastern Studies, pp. 75–104. Springer, Heidelberg/Berlin (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A.: How scientific models can explain. Synthese 1, 33–45 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., French, S.: How theories represent. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 62, 857–894 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N.: If no capacities then no credible worlds. But can models reveal capacities? Erkenntnis 70, 45–58 (2009a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, R.: Models: parables v. fables. Insights 1(8), 2–10 (2009b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A.: Informational versus functional theories of scientific representation. Synthese 172, 197–213 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chandradekharan, S., Nersessian, N.J.: Building cognition: the construction of computational representations for scientific discovery. Cogn. Sci. 2014. doi:10.1111/cogs.12203

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandradekharan, S.: Becoming knowledge. In: Osbek, L.M., Held, B.S. (eds.) Rational Intuition. Philosophical roots, scientific investigations, pp. 307–337. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2014)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chandrasekharan, S.: Building to discover: a common coding model. Cogn. Sci. 33, 1059–1086 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, K.L.: Negation as failure. In: Gallaire, H., Minker, J. (eds.) Logic and Data Bases, pp. 94–114. Plenum, New York (1978)

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G.: Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning. Philos. Sci. 74, 48–68 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G.: Scientific models and fictional objects. Synthese 172, 215–229 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cozzo, C.: Gulliver, truth and virtue. Topoi 31, 59–66 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, N.C., French, S.: Science and Partial Truth. A Unitary Approach to Models and Scientific Reasoning. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., De Smedt, J.: Mathematical symbols as epistemic actions. Synthese 190/1, 3–19 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.: Against Method. Verso, London (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. Fictionalism. In: Suárez M. (ed.) Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pp. 36–19. Routledge, London (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.: The Modularity of the Mind. The MIT Press, Cambridge (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S.: Keeping quiet on the ontology of models. Synthese 172, 231–249 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S.: The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (Translated by Strachey, J. in collaboration with Freud, A. et al.). Hogarth Press, London, 1953–1974

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R.: Fiction and scientific representation. In: Frigg, R., Hunter, M.C. (eds.) Beyond Mimesis and Nominalism: Representation in Art and Science, pp. 97–138. Springer, Heidelberg (2010a)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R.: Fiction in science. In: Woods, J. (ed.) Fictions and Models: New Essays, pp. 247–287. Philosophia Verlag, Munich (2010b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R.: Models and fiction. Synthese 172, 251–268 (2010c)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, G.: The Assayer [1623]. In: Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo (Translated and edited by S. Drake), pp. 231–280. Doubleday, New York (1957)

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N.: Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1988)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.: An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese 172, 269–281 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.: Why scientific models should not be regarded as works of fiction. In: Suárez, M. (ed.) Fictions in Science. Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pp. 248–258. Routledge, London (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P.: The strategy of model-based science. Biol. Philos. 21, 725–740 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P.: Models and fictions in science. Philos. Stud. 143, 101–116 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R.L.: Perception as hypothesis. In: Gregory, R.L. (ed.) The Oxford Companion to the Mind, pp. 608–611. Oxford University Press, New York (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J.: What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Trans. Charles S. Peirce Soc. 34, 503–533 (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E.: Cognitive artifacts. In: Wilson, R.A., Keil, F.C. (eds.) Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences, pp. 126–7. The MIT Press, Cambridge (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R., Josephson, S.G. (eds.) Abductive Inference. Computation, Philosophy, Technology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I.: Critique of Pure Reason (Translated by Kemp Smith, N. originally published 1787, reprint 1998). MacMillan, London (1929)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D., Maglio, P.: On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cogn. Sci. 18, 513–549 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A.: Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenntnis 70, 119–131 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Abduction, Reason, and Science. Processes of Discovery and Explanation. Kluwer Academic, Plenum Publishers, New York (2001)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Conjectures and manipulations. Computational modeling and the extra-theoretical dimension of scientific discovery. Mind. Mach. 14, 507–537 (2004a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Model-based and manipulative abduction in science. Found. Sci. 9, 219–247 (2004b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Abduction and chance discovery in science. Int. J. Knowl.-Based Intell. Eng. 11, 273–279 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Abductive Cognition. The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning. Springer, Heidelberg (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Understanding Violence. The Interwining of Morality, Religion, and Violence: A Philosophical Stance. Springer, Heidelberg (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Scientific models are not fictions. Model-based science as epistemic warfare. In: Magnani, L., Li, P. (eds.) Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Western and Eastern Studies, pp. 1–38. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U.: MISSing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis 70, 29–43 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M.: Idealizations and scientific understanding. Philos. Stud. 160(2), 237–252 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naylor, R.: Real experiment and didactic demonstration. Isis 67(3), 398–419 (1976)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J., Chandradekharan, S.: Hybrid analogies in conceptual innovation in science. Cogn. Syst. Res. 10(3), 178–188 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F.J., Laland, K.N., Feldman, M.W.: Niche Construction. The Neglected Process in Evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W.: Abduction and estimation in animals. Found. Sci. 17(4), 321–337 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S.: Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P. (eds.); vols. 7–8, Burks, A.W. (ed.). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, (1931–1958)

    Google Scholar 

  • Portides, D.P.: The relation between idealization and approximation in scientific model construction. Sci. Educ. 16, 699–724 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A.: Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of theory-ladenness of perception. Cogn. Sci. 25, 423–451 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A.: Reentrant pathways and the theory-ladenness of perception. Philos. Sci. 68, S187–S189 (2001) (Proceedings of PSA 2000 Biennal Meeting)

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A.: Cognition and Perception. How Do Psychology and Neural Science Inform Philosophy? The MIT Press, Cambridge (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, A.: Non-Standard Analysis. North Holland, Amsterdam (1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J.: Laboratory fictions. In: Suárez, M. (ed.) Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pp. 37–55. Routledge, London (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D.P.: Models in biology and physics: What’s the difference. Found. Sci. 14, 281–294 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D.: Epistemic values and the argument from inductive risk. Philos. Sci. 77, 14–34 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F.: Diagrammatology. An Investigation on the Borderlines of Phenomenology, Ontology, and Semiotics. Springer, Berlin (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M.: Scientific fictions as rules of inference. In: Suárez, M. (ed.) Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pp. 158–178. Routledge, London (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M.: Fictions, inference, and realism. In: Woods, J. (ed.) Fictions and Models: New Essays, pp. 225–245. Philosophia Verlag, Munich (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R.: Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. J. Econ. Method. 7, 1–31 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R.: Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis 70, 3–27 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thom, R.: Esquisse d’une s´emiophysique (Translated by Meyer, V.: Semio Physics: A Sketch, Addison Wesley, Redwood City, CA, 1990). InterEditions, Paris (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M.: Missing systems and the face value practice. Synthese 172, 283–299 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A.: The ontology of theoretical modelling: Models. Synthese 172, 301–315 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M.: The theoretician’s gambits: scientific representations, their formats and content. In: Magnani, L., Carnielli, W., Pizzi, C. (eds.) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Abduction, Logic, and Computational Discovery, pp. 533–558. Springer, Heidelberg (2010)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M.: Three kinds of idealizations. J. Philos. 104(12), 639–659 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., Rosales, A.: Unifying the fictional. In: Woods J. (ed.) Fictions and Models: New Essays, pp. 345–388. Philosophia Verlag, Munich (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., Rosales, A.: Virtuous distortion. Abstraction and idealization in model-based science. In: Magnani, L., Carnielli, W., Pizzi, C. (eds.) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology, pp. 3–30. Springer, Heidelberg (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (ed.): Fictions and Models: New Essays. Philosophia Verlag, Munich (2010)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For the instructive criticisms and precedent discussions and correspondence that helped me to develop my critique of fictionalism, I am indebted and grateful to John Woods, Shahid Rahman, Alirio Rosales, Mauricio Suárez, and to my collaborators Tommaso Bertolotti and Selene Arfini.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Magnani .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Magnani, L. (2016). Scientific Models Are Distributed and Never Abstract. In: Ippoliti, E., Sterpetti, F., Nickles, T. (eds) Models and Inferences in Science. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 25. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28163-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics