Skip to main content
Log in

Contrasting Views of Emotion in Learning: Alfred North Whitehead and Jerome Bruner

  • Published:
Interchange Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The article analyzes contrasting theories about the role of emotion in learning proposed by Alfred North Whitehead and Jerome Bruner. I argue that Whitehead’s account of experience and emotion in his educational philosophy is best understood in the context of the philosophy of organism. Here he takes issue with the empiricists’ view that sensa are the core of perception, and conceives of emotion as the primary bodily experience reaching out to the world as “prehensions” that provide continuity to experience. Bruner gives priority to cognition and the mental models that make problem solving possible. While he does acknowledge emotions as part of the fabric of the mind, they are shaped by what we know, which fully determines both experience and emotion. And when he embraces narrative thinking, it also excludes emotion in favour of “metacognitive sensitivity.” A possible reconciliation is attempted by considering the relationship between consciousness and emotion, but this serves to underline the differences. Whitehead’s realism and Bruner’s constructivism also highlight the philosophical divide between the two thinkers. I conclude that Whitehead’s theory of emotion in learning is richer and more inclusive than Bruner’s.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bruner’s account of emotions in their cultural context resembles that of Bedford (1964).

  2. For further analysis of Russell`s epistemology, see Pears (1967) and Jager (1972).

  3. For Whitehead, science presupposes metaphysical principles, which may or may not be warranted by empirical experience, and it assumes both modes of perception – causal efficacy and presentational immediacy. As he puts it (1961), “No science can be more secure than the unconscious metaphysics which tacitly it presupposes” (p. 154).

  4. Barrow and Milburn (1990) separate sensa from emotional feeling as follows: “the feeling itself is the aspect of an emotion least worth dwelling on, since we have no way of knowing whether the nature of our various sensations are similar” (p. 110).

  5. This means that emotions are not reactions or responses to external stimuli, and they contrast with Gilbert Ryle’s (1966) account of emotion as “an unwitnessed event” to be subsumed “under a law-like proposition” requiring no reference to the “necessarily occult … occurrences … in your or my secret world” (pp. 81, 87).

  6. Butler (2015) subscribes to a similar view: “The body,” she writes, “carries within it what remains enigmatic to consciousness and so exposes the insufficiency of consciousness: consciousness is not a term to which the body corresponds” (p. 48). Consciousness, then, is incapable of understanding the unfamiliar territory of the body, which does not correspond to its rhythmic pattern.

  7. For a full analysis of the various feelings in Whitehead’s philosophy of organism and their interrelationships, see Roy (2000), Cobb (2005), and Scarfe (2005).

  8. Collingwood (1961) makes a distinction between two kinds of presuppositions: relative presuppositions, which can be known by the historian and give meaning to the past and absolute presuppositions, which are not questioned in a particular era but are only known in retrospect and change from age to age. It is unclear which kind of presupposition underlies Bruner’s psychological, educational, and historical theories.

  9. As one reviewer put it, “Perhaps Bruner’s subjects live too much in their heads and not enough in their bodies.”

  10. Bruner’s early research began with an attempt to show that needs, which he equated with emotions, determine perceptions (Olson, 2007). But this is a category mistake; needs and emotions are quite different, as McMurtry (1998) shows: “N is a need if and only if, and to the extent that, deprivation of N always leads to a reduction of organic capability… [where] ‘organic capability’ … mean[s] the agent’s organic capabilities to move, think, and feel” (p. 164). Where a subject is deprived of their needs (for potable water, clean air, habitation, sufficient food as well as publicly funded health care and education etc.), their capacity to think, feel, and act is reduced. Children who come to school without sufficient nutrition are unlikely to learn as well as those who are well fed. This familiar example suggests that the feelings and emotions that enable learning to occur depend upon how well the subject’s life-needs are satisfied and enhanced (p. 165).

References

  • Barrow, R., & Milburn, G. (1990). Emotions. In R. Barrow & G. Milburn (Eds.), A critical dictionary of educational concepts: An appraisal of selected ideas and issues in educational theory and practice (pp. 109–111). New York: Teachers College Press. (Work first published 1986.)

  • Bedford, E. (1964). Emotions. In D. F. Gustafson (Ed.), Essays in philosophical psychology (pp. 77–98). London: MacMillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. (1960). The process of education. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. (1980). J.S. Bruner. In G. Lindszey (Ed.). The history of psychology in autobiography (Vol. VIII). San Francisco: Freeman.

  • Bruner, J. (1983). In search of mind: Essays in autobiography. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. (1996). The culture of education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (2015). Senses of the subject. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobb, J. B., Jr. (2002). Prehension. A lecture delivered to the Philosophy Department at the University of Budapest, Hungary, March 7. Retrieved January 2, 2006, from http://www.religion-online.org/showarticle.asp?title=1944.

  • Cobb, J. B., Jr. (2005). Education and the phases of concrescence. In F. G. Riffert (Ed.), Alfred North Whitehead on learning and education: Theory and application (pp. 19–33). Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1961). The idea of history. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Work first published 1946.)

  • Dewey, J. (1973). How we think: A restatement of the relation of reflective thinking to the educative process. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. (Work first published 1933.)

  • Dewey, J. (2005). Art as experience. New York: Berkeley Publishing. (Work first published 1934.)

  • Farmer, P. A. (2015). A whole universe of stories (and a little cosmic irony). In J. McDaniel & P. A. Farmer (Eds.), Replanting ourselves in beauty: Toward an ecological civilization (pp. 136–138). Anoka, MN: Process Century Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flynn, M. (1995). Conflicting views on the importance of emotion to human development and growth: Piaget and Whitehead. Interchange, 26(4), 365–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jager, R. (1972). The development of Bertrand Russell’s philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohl, H. (2009). Reawakening the heart of teaching: The Herb Kohl reader. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leclerc, I. (1958). Whitehead’s metaphysics: An introductory exposition. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMurtry, J. (1998). Unequal freedoms: The global market as an ethical system. Toronto, ON: Garamond Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, D. (2007). Jerome Bruner: The cognitive revolution in educational theory. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pears, D. F. (1967). Bertrand Russell and the British tradition in philosophy. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy, D. E. (2000). Toward a process psychology: A model of integration. Fresno, CA: Adobe Creations Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1959). My philosophical development. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1966). Emotion. In The concept of mind (pp. 81–111). Harmondsworth: Penguin. (Work first published 1949.)

  • Scarfe, A. C. (2005). Prehensive selectivity and the learning process. In F. G. Riffert (Ed.), Alfred North Whitehead on learning and education: Theory and application (pp. 123–158). Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarfe, A. C., & Woodhouse, H. (2008). Whitehead’s philosophy of education: Its promise and relationship to the philosophy of organism. In M. Weber & W. Desmond (Eds.), Handbook of Whiteheadian process thought (Vol. 1, pp. 185–197). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takaya, K. (2008). Jerome Bruner’s theory of education: From early Bruner to later Bruner. Interchange, 39(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M., & Weekes, A. (2009). Whitehead as a neglected figure of twentieth-century philosophy. In M. Weber & A. Weekes (Eds.), Process approaches to consciousness in psychology, neuroscience, and philosophy of mind (pp. 57–72). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1957). The aims of education and other essays. New York: The Free Press. (Work first published 1929.)

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1958). Symbolism: Its meaning and effect. New York: MacMillan. (Work first published 1927.)

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1961). Adventures of ideas. New York: The Free Press. (Work first published 1933.)

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1966). Modes of thought. New York: The Free Press. (Work first published 1938.)

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1978). In D. R. Griffin & D. W. Sherburne (Eds.), Process and reality: An essay in cosmology (Corrected Ed.). New York: The Free Press. (Work first published 1929.)

  • Wilson, S. M. (2014). Bruner, Jerome. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational theory and philosophy (Vol. 1, pp. 91–93). Los Angeles, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodhouse, H. (2011). Storytelling in university education: Emotion, teachable moments, and the value of life. Journal of Educational Thought., 43(3), 211–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodhouse, H. (2012). Mathematics as liberal education: Whitehead and the rhythm of life. Interchange, 43(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodhouse, H. (2014). Whitehead, Alfred N. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational theory and philosophy (Vol. 2, pp. 849–853). Los Angeles CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank members of the University of Saskatchewan Process Philosophy Research Unit—Mark Flynn, Bob Regnier, and Ed Thompson—for their valuable feedback and ongoing support. It was Mark (1995) who first alerted me to the contrasting views of emotion in Whitehead and Bruner. Both reviewers provided invaluable comments that improved the quality of the article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Howard Woodhouse.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Woodhouse, H. Contrasting Views of Emotion in Learning: Alfred North Whitehead and Jerome Bruner. Interchange 48, 217–230 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10780-016-9299-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10780-016-9299-1

Keywords

Navigation