Skip to main content
Log in

Collective Choices Under Ambiguity

  • Published:
Group Decision and Negotiation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We investigate experimentally whether collective choice environments matter for individual attitudes to ambiguity. In a simple two-urn Ellsberg experiment, one urn offers a 45 % chance of winning a fixed monetary prize while the other offers an ambiguous chance. Participants choose either individually or in groups of three. Group decision rules vary in the level of individual responsibility for the others’ payoffs: the collective choice is taken by majority, randomly delegated to two group members, or randomly delegated to a single group member. Although most participants display consistent ambiguity attitudes across their decisions, taking responsibility for the others tends to foster ambiguity aversion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Camerer and Weber (1992) for a comprehensive review of early empirical and theoretical work on ambiguity.

  2. It has also been shown that AA is affected by the comparison with more familiar events or more knowledgeable individuals (e.g., Fox and Tversky 1995; Chow and Sarin 2002; Fox and Weber 2002).

  3. Experiments in which a person decided for one or more others with no consequence to himself have also been carried out. Findings are again not unanimous. Indeed, while Reynolds et al. (2009) and Eriksen and Kvaløy (2010) found individuals to be more risk averse when deciding for others than when deciding for themselves, Chakravarty et al. (2011) detected increased risk taking in decisions for others.

  4. An alternative would have been to ask subjects to evaluate a given ambiguous prospect against a list of risky prospects, with varying expected values. This multiple price list (MPL) procedure would have enabled us to quantify ambiguity attitudes, but it unnecessarily complicates the design of the conditions with shared responsibility. Additionally, as remarked by Andersen et al. (2006), a MPL allows for multiple switching points, thus leading to potentially inconsistent decisions, and may be susceptible to framing effects.

  5. The standard experimental economics practice of randomly selecting one of the three binary choices to determine the final outcome is not a feasible option when responsibility for the group payoffs must be shared between two group members.

  6. The sequence makes no difference in case of transitive preferences and sincere voting. If subjects—despite the lack of preference information in our communication-free design—seek to be strategic, there is scope for misrepresentation of preferences in D2 and MV. This scope exists for any collective decision rule—sequential or not—if it is non-authoritarian and permits each bet to be selected (cf. the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem). Manipulation would, however, require very specific subjective beliefs and then affect only one’s choice of \(U_B\) versus \(U_W\).

  7. Note that if a participant wants to bet on, e.g., \(U_W\), so that the choice between \(U_B\) and \(K_Y\) becomes payoff irrelevant, this does not undermine the identification of the participant’s preference type because the two choice patterns selecting \(U_W\) as the relevant bet (namely \(U_W \succsim K_Y \succsim U_B\) and \(U_W \succsim U_B \succsim K_Y\)) are both classified as SEU.

  8. We refer readers to Braham and van Hees (2012) for a philosophical discussion of degrees of responsibility and the thorny issue of how individuals can be held responsible for a collective outcome for which their individual choices played no pivotal role.

  9. A translated version of the instructions can be found in the supplement.

References

  • Andersen S, Harrison GW, Lau MI, Rutström EE (2006) Elicitation using multiple price list formats. Exp Econ 9:383–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersson O, Holm HJ, Tyran J-R, Wengström E (2016) Deciding for others reduces loss aversion. Manag Sci 62:29–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton GE, Ockenfels A (2000) ERC: a theory of equity, reciprocity and competition. Am Econ Rev 90:166–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton GE, Ockenfels A (2010) Betrayal aversion: evidence from Brazil, China, Oman, Switzerland, Turkey, and the United States: comment. Am Econ Rev 100:628–633

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braham M, van Hees M (2012) An anatomy of moral responsibility. Mind 121:601–634

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunette M, Cabantous L, Couture S (2015) Are individuals more risk and ambiguity averse in a group environment or alone? results from an experimental study. Theory Decis 78:357–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer C, Weber M (1992) Recent developments in modeling preferences: uncertainty and ambiguity. J Risk Uncertain 5:325–370

  • Chakravarty S, Harrison GW, Haruvy EE, Rutström EE (2011) Are you risk averse over other people’s money? South Econ J 77:901–913

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness G, Karni E, Levin D (2013) Ambiguity attitudes and social interactions: an experimental investigation. J Risk Uncertain 46:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chow CC, Sarin RK (2002) Known, unknown, and unknowable uncertainties. Theory Decis 52:127–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox JC, Sadiraj V, Schmidt U (2015) Paradoxes and mechanisms for choice under risk. Exp Econ 18:215–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curley SP, Yates JF, Abrams RA (1986) Psychological sources of ambiguity avoidance. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 38:230–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg D (1961) Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Q J Econ 75:643–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eriksen KW, Kvaløy O (2010) Myopic investment management. Rev Finance 14:521–542

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Schmidt K (1999) A theory of fairness, competition and cooperation. Q J Econ 114:817–868

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischbacher U (2007) Zurich toolbox for readymade economic experiments. Exp Econ 10:171–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox CR, Tversky A (1995) Ambiguity aversion and comparative ignorance. Q J Econ 110:585–603

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox CR, Weber M (2002) Ambiguity aversion, comparative ignorance, and decision context. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 88:476–498

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa I, Schmeidler D (1989) Maxmin expected utility with a non-unique prior. J Math Econ 18:141–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gneezy U, Potters J (1997) An experiment on risk taking and evaluation periods. Q J Econ 112:631–645

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greiner B (2004) An online recruitment system for economic experiments. In: Kremer K, Macho V (eds) Forschung und wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003. Ges. für Wiss. Datenverarbeitung, Göttingen, pp 79–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt CA, Laury SK (2002) Risk aversion and incentive effects. Am Econ Rev 92:1644–1655

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey SJ, Renner E (2011). The social cost of responsibility. CeDEx Discussion paper No. 2011-02, University of Nottingham, School of Economics

  • Keck S, Diecidue E, Budescu D (2014) Group decisions under ambiguity: convergence to neutrality. J Econ Behav Organ 103:60–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller LR, Sarin RK, Sounderpandian J (2007) An examination of ambiguity aversion: are two heads better than one? Judgm Decis Mak 2:390–397

    Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff P, Marinacci M, Mukerji S (2005) A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 73:1849–1892

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maccheroni F, Marinacci M, Rustichini A (2006) Ambiguity aversion, robustness, and the variational representation of preferences. Econometrica 74:1447–1498

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muthukrishnan AV, Wathieu L, Xu AJ (2009) Ambiguity aversion and the preference for established brands. Manag Sci 55:1933–1941

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oechssler J, Roomets A (2014) A test of mechanical ambiguity. Discussion paper series No. 555, University of Heidelberg, Department of Economics

  • Pahlke J, Strasser S, Vieider FM (2012) Risk-taking for others under accountability. Econ Lett 114:102–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds DB, Joseph J, Sherwood R (2009) Risky shift versus cautious shift: determining differences in risk taking between private and public management decision-making. J Bus Econ Res 7:63–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutter M (2009) Individual behavior and group membership: comment. Am Econ Rev 99:2247–2257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trautmann ST, Vieider FM, Wakker PP (2008) Causes of ambiguity aversion: known versus unknown preferences. J Risk Uncertain 36:225–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vieider FM, Villegas-Palacio C, Martinsson P, Mejía M (2016) Risk taking for oneself and others: a structural model approach. Econ Inq 54:879–894

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker PP (2010) Prospect theory: for risk and ambiguity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank the editor and two anonymous referees for careful review and valuable comments. We are very grateful to Werner Güth for useful discussion and suggestions. We also benefited from the comments of participants at the 2013 Florence Workshop on Behavioral and Experimental Economics. Albrecht Noll and Claudia Zellmann provided valuable assistance in conducting the experiment. The authors bear full responsibility for any errors and omissions.

Funding This study was funded by the Max Planck Institute of Economics, Jena (Germany).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefan Napel.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest. They further confirm that they read and approved the manuscript and that there are no other persons who satisfied the criteria for authorship but are not listed.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Levati, M.V., Napel, S. & Soraperra, I. Collective Choices Under Ambiguity. Group Decis Negot 26, 133–149 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10726-016-9488-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10726-016-9488-4

Keywords

Navigation