Skip to main content
Log in

Sustainable growth

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper explores the view that a criterion of intergenerational equity serves to make choices according to ethical intuitions on a domain of relevant technological environments. In line with this view I first calibrate different criteria of intergenerational equity in the AK model of economic growth, with a given productivity parameter A, and then evaluate their performance by mapping the consequences of the criteria in various technological environments. The evaluation is based on the extent to which they yield social choice mappings satisfying four desirable properties. The Calvo criterion as well as sustainable discounted utilitarianism and rank-discounted utilitarianism yield sustainable growth in the AK model, the Ramsey technology and the Dasgupta–Heal–Solow–Stiglitz technology for any specifications of these technological environments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I use the term ‘wellbeing’ for what Roemer and his co-authors refer to as ‘welfare’. It is meant to indicate the current living situation and thus includes more than material consumption. Sentiments like altruism is, however, assumed not to be included in this indicator. In the technological environments considered in the current paper, net production is split between wellbeing and investment in reproducible capital, implying that wellbeing is measured in the same cardinal scale as capital.

  2. The analysis of the sustainable growth criterion in Llavador et al. (2010) is based on a conjectured ‘turnpike’ result, entailing that such an efficient balanced growth path is approached when the inputs initially are not in the proportions needed for efficient balanced growth. In Llavador et al. (2011) there is in addition a stock of CO\(_2\) in the atmosphere which is constant along the efficient balanced growth path.

  3. Asheim and Mitra (2010, Section 2) use the construction presented here to establish the existence of a SDU welfare function, while using their requirements (W.1)–(W.4) as the primitive definition.

  4. Hence, the RDU criterion combines an “absolute” Priority View with a “relative” one; see Fleurbaey (2015) and Buchak (2015).

  5. Conditions (2) and (3) of Asheim and Mitra (2010, Proposition 3) are satisfied since \(p_{t}/p_{t-1} = 1/A \ge \rho \) for all \(t \ge 1\), writing \(p_0 = 1\), and \({\sum }_{t=1}^\infty p_t x_t^e = k_0 = {\sum }_{t=1}^\tau p_t \tilde{x}_t + p_\tau \tilde{k}_\tau \ge {\sum }_{t=1}^\infty p_t \tilde{x}_t\) for any feasible stream \(_1 \tilde{x}\) and for all \(\tau \ge 1\).

  6. Zuber and Asheim (2012, Proposition 10) is based on Asheim (1991, Proposition 6), where the proof of Case 2 must be adapted to the AK model to show that \(_1 x^e\) maximizes \(w_\rho ^T(_1 x^+)\) over all non-decreasing streams \(_1 x^+\) when \(A \le 1/\rho \).

  7. Asheim and Mitra (2010, Lemma 1) is a formal demonstration of this result, as \(\sum _{t=1}^\tau \rho ^{t-1} \Lambda (1+g)^{t-1}\) would diverge for any \(\rho \) satisfying \(1/(1+g) \le \rho < 1\) if a wellbeing stream defined by \(x_t = \Lambda (1+g)^{t-1}\) for all t were feasible with \(\Lambda > 0\) and \(g > 0\).

  8. Use (7) combined with \(f(k) = k^\alpha \) and \(\dot{k} = sf(k)\) to obtain \(\dot{x}/x = s \alpha k^{\alpha - 1}\) and insert in (8).

  9. Mitra et al. (2013) do likewise in the continuous time version of the model.

  10. Asheim and Mitra (2010, Lemma 2) is a formal demonstration of this result, as \(\sum _{t=1}^\tau \rho ^{t-1} \Lambda (1+g)^{t-1}\) would diverge for any \(\rho \) satisfying \(1/(1+g) \le \rho < 1\) if a wellbeing stream defined by \(x_t = \Lambda (1+g)^{t-1}\) for all t were feasible with \(\Lambda > 0\) and \(g > 0\).

  11. The two parameters can be calibrated independently if there are two different combinations of gross productivity and growth rate, \((A^*, g^*)\) and \((A^{**}, g^{**})\), that appeal to ethical intuitions in the AK model.

References

  • Arrow KJ (1974) Rawls’ principle of just saving. Swed J Econ 75:323–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB (1988) Rawlsian intergenerational justice as a Markov-perfect equilibrium in a resource technology. Rev Econ Stud 55:469–483

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB (1991) Unjust intergenerational allocations. J Econ Theory 54:350–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, Ekeland I (2016) Resource conservation across generations in a Ramsey–Chichilnisky model. Econ Theory 61:611–639

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, Mitra T (2010) Sustainability and discounted utilitarianism in models of economic growth. Math Soc Sci 59:148–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, Nesje F (2016) Destructive intergenerational altruism. Memorandum 22/2015, Department of Economics, University of Oslo, revised April 2016, J Assoc Environ Res Econ (forthcoming)

  • Asheim GB, Zuber S (2014) Escaping the repugnant conclusion: rank-discounted utilitarianism with variable population. Theor Econ 9:629–650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, Zuber S (2016) Evaluating intergenerational risks. CESifo Working Paper No. 4728, revised April 2016, J Math Econ. doi:10.1016/j.jmateco.2016.05.005 (forthcoming)

  • Asheim GB, Buchholz W, Hartwick J, Mitra T, Withagen C (2007) Constant savings rates and quasi-arithmetic population growth under exhaustible resource constraints. J Environ Econ Manag 53:213–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beals R, Koopmans TC (1969) Maximizing stationary utility in a constant technology. SIAM J Appl Math 17:1001–1015

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchak L (2015) Relative priority. Mimeo, University of California, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvo G (1978) Some notes on time inconsistency and Rawls’ maximin criterion. Rev Econ Stud 45:97–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cass D, Mitra T (1991) Indefinitely sustained consumption despite exhaustible natural resources. Econ Theory 1:119–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky G (1996) An axiomatic approach to sustainable development. Soc Choice Welf 13:231–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta PS (1974) On some alternative criteria for justice between generations. J Public Econ 3:405–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta PS (2008) Discounting climate change. J Risk Uncertain 37:141–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta PS (2011) The ethics of intergenerational distribution: reply and response to John E. Roemer. Environ Resour Econ 50:475–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta PS, Heal GM (1974) The optimal depletion of exhaustible resources. Rev Econ Stud (Symp) 41:3–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta PS, Heal GM (1979) Economic theory and exhaustible resources. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta S, Mitra T (1983) Intergenerational equity and efficient allocation of exhaustible resources. Int Econ Rev 24:133–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietz S, Asheim GB (2012) Climate policy under sustainable discounted utilitarianism. J Environ Econ Manag 63:321–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M (2015) Equality versus priority. How relevant is the distinction? Econ Philos 31:203–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale D (1967) On optimal development in a multi-sector economy. Rev Econ Stud 34:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans TC (1960) Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica 28:287–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llavador H, Roemer JE, Silvestre J (2010) Intergenerational justice when future worlds are uncertain. J Math Econ 46:728–761

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llavador H, Roemer JE, Silvestre J (2011) A dynamic analysis of human welfare in a warming planet. J Public Econ 95:1607–1620

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llavador H, Roemer JE, Silvestre J (2013) Should we sustain? And if so, sustain what? Consumption or the quality of life? In: Fouquet R (ed) Handbook on energy and climate change. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitra T, Asheim GB, Buchholz W, Withagen C (2013) Characterizing the sustainability problem in an exhaustible resource model. J Econ Theory 148:2164–2182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus WD (2007) The Stern review on the economics of climate change. J Econ Lit 45:687–702

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) A theory of justice, revised edn. The Belknap Press of the Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray D (1987) Nonpaternalistic intergenerational altruism. J Econ Theory 41:112–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (2011) The ethics of intertemporal distribution in a warming planet. Environ Resour Econ 48:363–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (2013) Once more on intergenerational discounting in climate-change analysis: reply to Partha Dasgupta. Environ Resour Econ 56:141–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1979) Utilitarianism and welfarism. J Philos 76:463–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solow RM (1974) Intergenerational equity and exhaustible resources. Rev Econ Stud (Symp) 41:29–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern NH (2006) The Stern review of the economics of climate change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz J (1974) Growth with exhaustible natural resources: efficient and optimal growth paths. Rev Econ Stud (Symp) 41:123–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman ML (2007) The Stern review of the economics of climate change. J Econ Lit 45:703–724

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zuber S, Asheim GB (2012) Justifying social discounting: the rank-discounted utilitarian approach. J Econ Theory 147:1572–1601

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Geir B. Asheim.

Additional information

I am grateful for extensive discussions with Paolo Piacquadio and for correspondence with John Roemer and Joaquim Silvestre. The editors of the special issue and two referees have also contributed with helpful comments. Some text has with alterations been borrowed from earlier papers; this includes parts of Sect. 2, which appears in Asheim and Nesje (2016), and the introduction to Sect. 6, which appears in Zuber and Asheim (2012). This paper is part of the research activities at the Centre for the Study of Equality, Social Organization, and Performance (ESOP) at the Department of Economics at the University of Oslo. ESOP is supported by the Research Council of Norway through its Centres of Excellence funding scheme, Project Number 179552.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Asheim, G.B. Sustainable growth. Soc Choice Welf 49, 825–848 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0977-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0977-9

Navigation