Skip to main content
Log in

Discounting climate change

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I offer a fairly complete account of the idea of social discount rates as applied to public policy analysis. I show that those rates are neither ethical primitives nor observables as market rates of return on investment, but that they ought instead to be derived from economic forecasts and society's conception of distributive justice concerning the allocation of goods and services across personal identities, time, and events. However, I also show that if future uncertainties are large, the formulation of intergenerational well-being we economists have grown used to could lead to ethical paradoxes even if the uncertainties are thin-tailed. Various modelling avenues that offer a way out of the dilemma are discussed. None is entirely satisfactory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Heal (1998, 2007) and Hoel and Sterner (2007) study inter-generational welfare economics when individual felicities depend on stocks of environmental capital.

  2. For the analysis involving multiple consumption goods, see Sterner and Persson (2008).

  3. This rules out the influence on an individual's felicity of habitual consumption or the average consumption of the person's peer group. The implications of habitual consumption on social rates of discount have been studied by Ryder and Heal (1973); the influence of peer group by Layard (1980, 2005) and Arrow and Dasgupta (2007), among others.

  4. Expression (1) has the structure of “utilitarianism”, though not necessarily its classical interpretation (see below). Some ethicists have proposed an ethical theory they call “prioritarianism”, which says that an increase in the well-being of a rich person (i.e., someone who enjoys a high consumption level) should be assigned less social value than the same increase in the well-being of a poor person (someone whose consumption level is low). I have not understood why such an ad hoc ethical principle should be awarded a name. I would have thought the utilitarian who is averse to inequality in consumption has it right: he assigns a lower social value to an increase in the consumption level of a rich person than to the same increase in the consumption level of a poor person.

  5. We write U′(C) = dU(C)/dC and U"(C) = dU′(C)/dC.

  6. If we wished to study the intra-generational distribution of consumption as well, the simplest move would be to disaggregate each generation by imagining that there are N people at each date (i = 1,2,...,N), as in expression (1), and assuming that people have the same felicity function, U. Intergenerational well-being at t = 0 would then be \(W_0 = _{t = 0} \sum ^\infty \left[ {{{V_t } \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{V_t } {\left( {1 + \delta } \right)^t }}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {\left( {1 + \delta } \right)^t }}} \right] = _{t = 0} \sum ^\infty \left[ {_i \sum \left\{ {{{U\left( {C_{it} } \right)} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{U\left( {C_{it} } \right)} {\left( {1 + \delta } \right)^t }}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {\left( {1 + \delta } \right)^t }}} \right\}} \right].\)

  7. In work under preparation, I have tried to construct a framework that builds an intergenerational welfare economics admitting the idea of selfhood. The model I have constructed permits someone to discount his own future felicities in any way he likes (that’s the demand of his “self”), but requires of him to give a weight to the lifetime well-being of each of his children that equals the weight he gives to his own lifetime well-being. The model would seem to reconcile the widespread finding from consumption behaviour that people do discount their future felicities at a non-negligible positive rate (see below) and the philosophical injunction that many people would seem to adhere to, namely, that they should not discriminate against their children’s futures (see below).

  8. Roughly, the “independence” assumption amounts to the requirement that the marginal rate of societal indifference between felicities in any two periods is independent of the felicities in all other periods.

  9. So,

    $${{C_{t + 1} } \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{C_{t + 1} } {C_t }}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {C_t }} = 1 + g\left( {C_t } \right).$$
    (F1)
  10. Formally, \(\eta = {{ - CU\prime \prime \left( C \right)} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{ - CU\prime \prime \left( C \right)} {U\prime \left( C \right) > {\text{ }}0}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {U\prime \left( C \right) > {\text{ }}0}}\)

  11. Arrow (1965) observed that the simplest U that is bounded at both ends is one for which η is an increasing function of C and is less than 1 at low values of C and greater than 1 at high values of C.

  12. Proof: Because the pair of variations ΔC t +1 and ΔC t leave the numerical value of expression (2) unaltered,

    $${{\text{U}}\prime {\left( {{\text{C}}_{{\text{t}}} } \right)}\Delta {\text{C}}_{{\text{t}}} } \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{{\text{U}}\prime {\left( {{\text{C}}_{{\text{t}}} } \right)}\Delta {\text{C}}_{{\text{t}}} } {{\left( {{\text{1 + }}\delta } \right)}^{{\text{t}}} }}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {{\left( {{\text{1 + }}\delta } \right)}^{{\text{t}}} } + {{\text{U}}\prime {\left( {{\text{C}}_{{{\text{t}} + {\text{1}}}} } \right)}\Delta {\text{C}}_{{{\text{t}} + {\text{1}}}} } \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{{\text{U}}\prime {\left( {{\text{C}}_{{{\text{t}} + {\text{1}}}} } \right)}\Delta {\text{C}}_{{{\text{t}} + {\text{1}}}} } {{\left( {{\text{1 + }}\delta } \right)}^{{{\text{t}} + {\text{1}}}} }}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {{\left( {{\text{1 + }}\delta } \right)}^{{{\text{t}} + {\text{1}}}} } = {\text{0}}{\text{.}}$$
    (F2)

    By definition,

    $$\rho _t = {{ - \Delta C_{t + 1} } \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{ - \Delta C_{t + 1} } {\Delta C_t - 1}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {\Delta C_t - 1}},$$
    (F3)

    where ΔC t +1 and ΔC t satisfy equation (F2). Now use equations (3), (F1)–(F3) to obtain equation (4) in the text.

  13. Proof: Take the logarithm of both sides of equation (4) and, using the fact that if x is small in absolute value, ln(1+x) \( \approx \) x, the approximate equation 4a follows.

  14. I have friends in the US who find illustrations involving negative economic growth to be unrealistic. In fact a number of countries in sub-Saharan Africa suffered from negative growth during the period 1970–2000. What discount rates should government project evaluators there have chosen in 1970 if they had an approximately correct forecast of the shape of things to come?

  15. See Dasgupta et al. (1999). This parallels the well-known fact that if the external disbenefits arising from anyone's use of a commodity are large enough, the commodity's shadow price will be negative even when its market price is positive.

  16. Nordhaus (2007) confirms this by using Stern's specifications for δ and η in the climate-change model he has developed over the past two decades. It should be noted that Nordhaus' ρ t = 4.30% a year is consistent with the US government's discount rate policy. On the latter, see Viscusi (2007).

  17. I am grateful to William Cline for correspondence on this way of studying how η should be chosen.

  18. Quite obviously, I am making outrageous assumptions regarding aggregation of capital. In this I am no different from contemporary growth economists.

  19. It requires justification because Professor Brad De Long took me to task over it in the critique he posted on his blog on November 30, 2006, under the title, “Partha Dasgupta Makes a Mistake”. His piece was a response to the review of Stern (2006) that was published in Dasgupta (2007).

  20. Proof: If ρ t is less than r, society would be advised to save a bit more at t. But to save a bit more at t is to consume a bit less at t, and this tilts consumption more toward the remaining future, which in turn raises ρ t . Alternatively, if ρ t exceeds r, society would be well advised to save a bit less at t. But to save a bit less at t is to consume a bit more at t, and that tilts consumption more toward t, which in turn lowers ρ t . It follows that along the optimum C t , ρ t = r.

  21. This is the same as approximation (4a), with r = ρ t .

  22. In Section 3.4 I suggest that in a deterministic world δ should be set equal to zero.

  23. The rigorous argument would have us check that the saving rate in equation (8) satisfies the transversality condition, namely, that the present discounted value of wealth (in well-being units) tends to zero as t tends to infinity. Readers can check that it does.

  24. Proof: Re-write equation (5) as

    $$K_{t + 1} - K_t = rK_t - \left( {1 + r} \right)C_t ,$$

    which says that a consumption level of C t at the beginning of period t is equivalent to the consumption level (1+r)C t at the end of that period. So saving out of output at the end of t is (rK t -(1+r)C t ). Therefore the ratio of saving to output is (rK t -(1+r)C t )/rK t , which, as is easily confirmed, equals the normalized saving-wealth ratio.

  25. This result is very old. It dates back to Ramsey (1928). In defense of his choice of η = 1,Stern (2008) complains that the 97% saving rate I have just obtained is a feature of a very artificial model. Of course it is. But “non”-artificial models, such as those Stern used in his computer runs, don’t reveal which parameter is doing what work in generating his findings. How is one to test the robustness of ethical assumptions if not by putting them to work in stark, artificial models?

  26. See Marglin (1963) and Dasgupta et al. (1972). Among economists writing on climate change, only Cline (1992) has mentioned the need to revalue capital in imperfect economies.

  27. Proof: a marginal additional unit of capital at t = 0 yields a small change in consumption, ΔC t , equal to (1-s)(s(1+r))t. At the consumption discount rate ρ, the present value of that small change, from 0 to ∞, is the expression for P k . (Note that, because s > (1+r)-1, the present value exists.) Equation (10) is due to Marglin (1963).

  28. Ramsey (1928: 261) famously wrote that to discount future well-being is “ethically indefensible and arises merely from the weakness of the imagination”. That is, of course, not an argument; merely an expression of one's beliefs. Broome (1992) contains a summary of the arguments that support Ramsey's position.

  29. Possible extinction of the human race offers a reason for δ > 0, but that is a different reason for positive time discounting. We discuss that in Section 4. We should also bear in mind that infinite-horizon deterministic models are mathematical artifacts: we know Humanity will not survive forever.

  30. In this context, Arrow (1963) can be interpreted as an attempt to discover an aggregator function of individual ethical preferences. It isn't an accident that the title of his classic is “Social Choice and Individual Values”. I have explored that interpretation in Dasgupta (2005).

  31. Barrett (2003) contains an interesting discussion of those obligations.

  32. Dasgupta and Maskin (2005) have offered an explanation for hyperbolic discounting (preference reversal, more generally), among starlings and pigeons, that is based on selection pressure over evolutionary time. The authors assume that the decision maker has to choose between two options: (i) a reward, V (> 0), that will appear at an uncertain date (the expected date being T), and (ii) a reward, V* (> 0), that too will appear at an uncertain date (the expected date being T*). Assuming V* > V and T* > T, the authors show that, under quite general circumstances concerning the distributions of the uncertain arrival times, a risk neutral decision maker would display preference reversal (from V to V*) if neither reward appeared for a while. In the present paper, I am studying social ethics, not private preferences. The viewpoint I am adopting here is that individual behaviour based on hyperbolic discounting is a constraint the social evaluator must take into account when he evaluates public policies, but that the evaluative criterion for social choice should be intergenerational well-being (expression (2)).

  33. The subsequent, asset-pricing literature (e.g., Brock 1982) has explored models that are more general than the one studied by Levhari and Srinivasan (1969). I use the Levhari-Srinivasan formulation to illustrate my points because of its simplicity and because its findings are directly comparable to those discussed in textbooks on asset pricing (e.g., Cochrane 2005), where asset prices are taken to be exogenous stochastic variables.

  34. It is easy to show that,

    $$1 + \overline r = \exp \left( {\mu {{ + \sigma ^2 } \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{ + \sigma ^2 } 2}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} 2}} \right),$$
    (F4)
    $$and\quad \operatorname{var} \left( {1 + \tilde r} \right) = \operatorname{var} \left( {\tilde r} \right) = \left( {\exp \left( {\sigma ^2 } \right) - 1} \right)\exp \left( {2\mu + \sigma ^2 } \right).$$
    (F5)
  35. Notice that s** = s* (equation (8)) if σ = 0.

  36. That is, \(\tilde s** = {{\left[ {s** - \left( {1 + \overline r } \right)^{ - 1} } \right]} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\left[ {s** - \left( {1 + \overline r } \right)^{ - 1} } \right]} {\left[ {1 - \left( {1 + \overline r } \right)^{ - 1} } \right]}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {\left[ {1 - \left( {1 + \overline r } \right)^{ - 1} } \right]}}\). See footnote 24.

  37. Alternatively, we could call it the “certainty-equivalent rate”.

  38. The proof, which makes use of the assumption that (1+r) is drawn from a lognormal distribution, is similar to the one that was used to arrive at equation 4a. The equation is familiar in the theory of finance (Cochrane 2005: p. 10). Notice that if σ = 0, equation (14) reduces to equation 4a.

  39. Approximation (12a) summarized a related finding that the optimum saving rate increases with increasing risk.

  40. See Lenton et al. (2007).

References

  • Arrow, K. J. (1965). Aspects of the theory of risk-bearing. Helsinki: Yrjö Jahnssonin säätiö.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley (1951).

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1999). Discounting, morality, and gaming. In P. R. Portney, & J. P. Weyant (Eds.), Discounting and intergenerational equity. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., et al. (1996). Intertemporal equity, discounting, and economic efficiency. In J. P. Bruce, H. Lee, & E. F. Haites (Eds.), Climate Change 1995: Economic and social dimensions of climate change, contribution of working group III to the second assessment report of the intergovernmental panel on climate change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., & Dasgupta, P. (2007). Conspicuous Consumption, Inconspicuous Leisure. Mimeo, Faculty of Economics, University of Cambridge.

  • Arrow, K. J., & Kurz, M. (1970). Public investment, the rate of return and optimal fiscal policy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, S. (2003). Environment and statecraft: The strategy of environmental treaty-making. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolin, B. (1989). Changing climates. In L. Friday, & R. Laskey (Eds.), The fragile environment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, W. A. (1982). Asset prices in a production model. In J. McCall (Ed.), The economics of information and uncertainty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (1992). Counting the cost of global warming. Cambridge: White Horse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2008). The Ethics of Climate Change, Scientific American June, 69-73.

  • Cline, W. R. (1992). The economics of global warming. Washington, DC: Institute for International Economics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cline, W. R. (1993). Give Greenhouse Abatement a Fair Chance, Finance and Development March, 3-5.

  • Cochrane, J. H. (2005). Asset pricing (2nd ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. (2001). Human well-being and the natural environment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. (2005). What do economists analyze and why: values or facts? Economics and Philosophy, 2(2), 221–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. (2007). Commentary: The Stern Review's economics of climate change. National Institute Economic Review, 199, 4–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., & Heal, G. (1979). Economic theory and exhaustible resources. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., Maler, K. G., & Barrett, S. (1999). Intergenerational equity, social discount rates, and global warming. In P. R. Portney, & J. P. Weyant (Eds.), Discounting and intergenerational equity. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., Marglin, S. A., & Sen, A. (1972). Guidelines for project evaluation. New York: United Nations.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., & Maskin, E. (2005). Uncertainty and hyperbolic discounting. American Economic Review, 95(4), 1290–1299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, R. E. (1988). Intertemporal substitution in consumption. Journal of Political Economy, 96(2), 339–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1955). Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy, 63(3), 309–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heal, G. M. (1998). Valuing the future: Economic theory and sustainability. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal, G. M. (2007). Climate Change Economics: A Meta-Review and Some Suggestions. Mimeo, Columbia Business School, Columbia University.

  • Hoel, M., & Sterner, T. (2007). Discounting and Relative Prices. Climate Change, doi:10.1007/s10584-007-9255-2.

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28(2), 287–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1972). Representation of preference orderings over time. In C. B. McGuire, & R. Radner (Eds.), Decision and organization. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (1980). Human satisfaction and public policy. Economic Journal, 90(4), 737–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2005). Happiness: Lessons from a new science. New York: Penguin.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lenton, T. M. et al. (2007). Tipping Elements in the Earth System. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (under review).

  • Levhari, D., & Srinivasan, T. N. (1969). Optimal savings under uncertainty. Review of Economic Studies, 36(2), 153–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lind, R. C. (Ed.) (1982). In Discounting for time and risk in energy planning. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

  • Little, I. M. D., & Mirrlees, J. A. (1969). Manual of industrial project analysis in developing countries: Social cost benefit analysis. Paris: OECD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marglin, S. A. (1963). The opportunity costs of public investment. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 77(2), 274–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirrlees, J. A. (1967). Optimum growth when technology is changing. Review of Economic Studies, 34(1), 95–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirrlees, J. A. (1971). An exploration in the theory of optimal income taxation. Review of Economic Studies, 38(1), 175–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus, W. D. (1994). Managing the global commons: The economics of climate change. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus, W. D. (2007). The Stern Review on the economics of climate change. Journal of Economic Literature, 45(3), 686–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus, W. D., & Boyer, J. (2000). Warming the world: Economic modeling of global warming. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pesaran, H., Pettenuzzo, D., & Timmermann, A. (2007). Learning, structural instability, and present value calculations. Econometric Reviews, 6(2-4), 253–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E. S., & Pollak, R. (1968). Second-best national savings and game equilibrium growth. Review of Economic Studies, 35(2), 185–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portney, P. R., & Weyant, J. P. (Eds.) (1999). In Discounting and intergenerational equity. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1928). A mathematical theory of saving. Economic Journal, 38(4), 543–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1972). A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, H. E., & Heal, G. M. (1973). Optimal growth with intertemporally dependent preferences. Review of Economic Studies, 40(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (1992). Human morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1999). Intergenerational discounting. In P. R. Portney, & J. P. Weyant (Eds.), Discounting and intergenerational equity. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solow, R. M. (1974). Intergenerational equity and exhaustible resources. Review of Economic Studies, 41(Symposium Issue), 29–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sozou, P. D. (1998). On hyperbolic discounting and uncertain hazard rates. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London (Series B), 265, 2015–2020.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, N. H. (1976). On the specification of models of optimum income taxation. Journal of Economic Theory, 6(1-2), 123–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, N. H., et al. (2006). The Stern Review of the economics of climate change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, N. H. (2008). The economics of climate change. American Economic Review, 98(2), 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterner, T., & Persson, U. M. (2008). An Even Sterner Review: Introducing Relative Prices into the Discounting Debate. Review of Environmental Economics and Policy, 2(1), 61–76. doi:10.1093/reep/rem024.

  • Viscusi, W. K. (2007). Rational discounting for regulatory analysis. University of Chicago Law Review, 74(1), 209–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman, M. L. (2001). Gamma discounting. American Economic Review, 91(1), 260–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman, M. L. (2007a). The Stern Review of the economics of climate change. Journal of Economic Literature, 45(3), 703–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman, M. L. (2007b). The Role of Uncertainty in the Economics of Catastrophic Climate Change. Discussion Paper, Department of Economics, Harvard University.

  • World Bank (2007). World development indicators. Washington, DC: World Bank.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yaari, M. (1965). Uncertain lifetime, life insurance, and the theory of the consumer. Review of Economic Studies, 32(2), 137–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Partha Dasgupta.

Additional information

The ideas I apply here were presented in my Plenary Lecture to the World Congress of Environmental and Resource Economists, held in Monterey, California, June 2002, and were explored in Dasgupta (2001: Ch. 11). For discussions and correspondence over the years, I am very grateful to Kenneth Arrow, Geir Asheim, and Karl-Göran Mäler. While revising the paper I have benefited greatly from the comments of William Cline, William Nordhaus, W. Kip Viscusi, and Martin Weitzman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dasgupta, P. Discounting climate change. J Risk Uncertain 37, 141–169 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9049-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9049-6

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation