Skip to main content
Log in

That-clauses and propositional anaphors

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that that-clauses do not reference propositions because they are not intersubstitutible with other expressions that do reference propositions. In particular, that-clauses are shown to not be intersubstitutible with propositional anaphors like so. The substitution failures are further argued to support a semantics on which that-clauses are predicates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout the paper, I use refer and cognate terms loosely. A reader bothered by my loose usage should feel free to read and hear designate in the sense of King (2002) instead. I also avoid framing the paper as being about whether that-clauses are singular terms. For reasons I give in van Elswyk (forthcoming), contemporary accounts of singular termhood are deficient in that they are not cross-categorial in their application.

  2. For relevant discussion, consult Dolby (2009), Trueman (2012, 2018), and Nebel (2019).

  3. This is simplified characterization of how anaphora to propositions is licensed. I proceed simply because the central argument of this paper does not turn on any details of licensing. See Snider (2017) for the most detailed discussion to date.

  4. Among others, see Kiparsky and Kiparsky (1970), Cushing (1972), Cornish (1992), Needham (2012), Sailor (2012), Krifka (2013), Moulton (2015), Snider (2017), and van Elswyk (2019, forthcoming).

  5. A referee suggests that so being of a different semantic type than its antecedent is a reason to doubt that it references a proposition. But note the recruited anaphors also have to have a different semantic type than their antecedents. This difference is not limited to postverbal embeddings like (4b) either. A declaratives like That / it is true is also felicitous reply to (4a). These are referring instances of the pronouns, and what goes for the pronouns goes for so.

  6. A referee notes that the pronoun him cannot replace Giannis in a postnominal position. For example, The athelete Giannis is grammatical whereas the athlete him is not. They suggest that this substitution failure does not count against names being referential. Accordingly, they wonder why postnominal substitutions failures with that-clauses should. First, I disagree that their substitution failures do not count against names being referential. At the very least, it is data to explain, and its explanation might require us to give up traditional assumptions about names and pronouns. For example, if names are predicates (Fara 2015) and pronouns are determiners (Elbourne 2005, 2013), the name/pronoun substitutions failures are explained. Second, the name/pronoun data is not sufficiently similar. The syntax of The athlete Giannis may be that of a close nominal appositive (Keizer 2007). If it is, we should also consider variants like Giannis the athlete. But substitution with variants does preserve grammaticality. Suppose we are selecting teammates for a pick-up game of basketball. I might point to an interested person and say I choose him the athlete. What I have said is grammatical, especially if there is comma-intonation between the pronoun and description. The postnominal data with that-clauses cannot be similarly improved.

  7. I am indebted to a referee for raising this objection.

  8. Corpus data provides further support. The Corpus of Contemporary American English (COCA) contains 72 instances of the fragment That seems so (Davies 2008-present). The so is a degree modifier of an adjective like scary or unnatural in every instance.

  9. Though I will not develop substitution failures with factives as an additional strike against that-clauses being referential, it should be noted that extant explanations of the failures favor a predicativist semantics for that-clauses. For example, Kastner (2015) proposes that factives exclusively take DP complements. That-clauses after factives are then headed by covert determiners. As evidence for his proposal, Kastner (2015, 173) cites the contrast in grammaticality between sentences like (26) and (27). Given that so is a CP, his proposal predicts the infelicity of (27). Unlike a referential view, a predicativist semantics smoothly applies to that-clauses headed by determiners. See my treatment of sentential subjects below and Moulton (2017) for relevant discussion.

  10. See Kratzer (2006), Arsenijevic (2009), Moulton (2009, 2015, 2017), and Moltmann (2018).

  11. de Cuba (2017) tackles this problem by analyzing postnominal that-clauses as close nominal appositives. I suspect such an approach is the most promising for those wanting to extend the referential view of that-clauses to postnominal clauses. Nevertheless, the inability to be intersubstitutible with so is still a problem for a referentialist view of that-clauses. See fn.7 for related discussion.

  12. The explanation just provided also resolves a tension a referee noted between the proposal of Nebel (2019) that hope occurs with for and so being an anaphor. Evidence for Nebel’s proposal is that hopes for appears with that-clauses in rearranged sentences like That Giannis will be named MVP is what Aaron hopes for. However, so is ungrammatical in the rearranged sentence as So is what Aaron hopes for shows. Therein lies the tension. But the that-clause in the rearranged sentence is a sentential subject. So cannot therefore appear with hopes for because it is a referring term as opposed to a predicate that can attached to a covert DP.

  13. I thank a referee for encouraging me to discuss this licensing difference.

  14. I’m indebted to Joshua Spencer for helpful conversation, and to a referee for extensive feedback that greatly improved this paper.

References

  • Alrenga, P. (2005). A sentential subject asymmetry in English and its implications for complement selection. Syntax, 8(3), 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arsenijevic, B. (2009). Clausal complementation as relativization. Lingua, 119(1), 39–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1997). Do belief reports report beliefs? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79, 215–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (1998). Propositions. Mind, 107, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, S., & Altshuler, D. (2017). ‘now’ with subordindate clauses. Proceedings of SALT, 27, 358–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H. (1975). Bridging. In Proceedings of the conference on theoretical issues in natural language processing (pp. 169–174).

  • Cornish, F. (1992). So be it: The discourse semantic roles of So and It. Journal of Semantics, 9(2), 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosse, M. (1996). Indefinite associative anaphora in French. In C. Hellman & K. Frarud (Eds.), Proceedings of the Indiana workshop on indirect anaphora. Lancaster: Unviersity of Lancaster.

  • Cushing, S. (1972). The semantics of sentence pronominalization. Foundations of Language, 9(2), 186–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2008). The corpus of contemporary American English: 520 million words, 1990-present. http://corpus.byu.edu/coca/, 2008-present.

  • Davies, W., & Dubinsky, S. (2010). On the existence (and distribution) of sentential subjects. In Hypothesis A/Hypothesis B: Linguistic explorations in honor of David M. Perlmutter (pp. 211–228). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • de Cuba, C. (2017). Noun complement clauses as referential modifiers. Glossa, 3, 1–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolby, D. (2009). The reference principle: A defence. Analysis, 69(2), 286–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne, P. (2005). Situations and individuals. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne, P. (2013). Definite descriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fara, D. G. (2015). Names are predicates. The Philosophical Review, 124(1), 59–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B. (2012). Accessibility and anaphora. In K. von Heusinger, C. Maienborn, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 3, pp. 2432–2460). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

  • Grimshaw, J. (1990). Argument structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallman, P. (2006). On a categorical distinction between stative and eventive verbs. In C. Davis, A. R. Deal & Y. Zabbal (Eds.), Proceedings of NELS (Vol. 36).

  • Hofweber, T. (2007). Innocent statements and their metaphysically loaded counterparts. Philosophers’ Imprint, 7(1), 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kastner, I. (2015). Factivity mirrors interpretation: The selectional requirements of presuppositional verbs. Lingua, 164, 156–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keizer, E. (2007). Close appositions. In E. Keizer (Ed.), The English noun phrase: The nature of linguistic categorization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • King, J. C. (2002). Designating propositions. Philosophical Review, 111(3), 341–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiparsky, P., & Kiparsky, C. (1970). Fact. In M. Bierwisch & K. E. Heidolph (Eds.), Progress in Linguistics: A collection of papers (pp. 143–73). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2006). Decomposing attitude verbs. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/DcwY2JkM/attitude-verbs2006.pdf.

  • Krifka, M. (2013). Response particles as propositional anaphors. In T. Snider (Ed.), Proceedings of SALT (Vol. 23, pp. 1–18).

  • Lasnik, H. (1999). Minimalist analysis. Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohndal, E. (2014). Sentential subjects in English and Norwegian. Syntaxe et sémantique, 1(14), 81–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meijer, A. M. (2018) The pragmatics and semantics of embedded polar responses with English so. In W. G. Bennett, L. Hracs, & D. R. Storoshenko (Eds.), Proceedings of the West Coast conference on formal Linguistics (pp. 269–279).

  • Moltmann, F. (2003). Propositional attitudes without propositions. Synthese, 135, 70–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2018). Clauses as semantic predicates: Difficulties for possible-worlds semantics. In R. Bhatt, I. Frana, & P. Menendez-Benito (Eds.), Festschrift for Angelika Kratzer. Amherst: University of Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulton, K. (2009) Natural selection and the syntax of clausal complementation. Ph.D. thesis, University of Masschusetts, Amherst

  • Moulton, K. (2015). Cps: copies and compositionality. Linguistic Inquiry, 46(2), 305–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulton, K. (2017). Determiners on clauses. In N. LaCara, K. Moulton, & A.-M. Tessier (Eds.), A Schrift to Fest Kyle Johnson (pp. 293–304). Linguistics Open Access Publications 1.

  • Nebel, J. (2019). Hopes, fears, and other grammatical scarecrows. Philosophical Review, 128(1), 63–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Needham, S. (2012). Propositional anaphora in English: The relationship between so and discourse. Master’s thesis, Carleton University.

  • Rosefeldt, T. (2008). ‘that’-clauses and non-nominal quantification. Philosophical Studies, 137(3), 301–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roussou, A. (1991). Nominalized clauses in the syntax of modern Greek. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics, 3, 77–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rundle, B. (1967). Transitivity and indirect speech. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 68, 187–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sailor, C. (2012). You can’t regret so (even if you think so) (Manuscript).

  • Schiffer, S. (1972). Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snider, T. (2017). Anaphoric reference to propositions. Ph.D. thesis, Cornell University.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1987). Semantics for belief. Philosophical Topics, 15(1), 177–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stowell, T. (1981) Origins of phrase structure. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Trueman, R. (2012). Dolby substitution (where available). Analysis, 72(1), 98–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trueman, R. (2018). Substitution in a sense. Philosophical Studies, 175(12), 3069–3098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Elswyk, P. (2019). Propositional anaphors. Philosophical Studies, 176(4), 1055–1075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Elswyk, P. The linguistic basis for propositions. In C. Tillman (Ed.), Routledge handbook of propositions. Routledge (forthcoming).

  • Wright, C. (1998). Why Frege did not deserve his ’granum salis.’ A note on the paradox of ‘the concept horse’ and the ascription of ‘bedeutung’ to predicates. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 55, 239–263.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter van Elswyk.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

van Elswyk, P. That-clauses and propositional anaphors. Philos Stud 177, 2861–2875 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01343-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01343-8

Keywords

Navigation