Skip to main content
Log in

Bohr’s Philosophy in the Light of Peircean Pragmatism

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Adopting Murdoch’s pragmatist reading of Bohr’s theory of meaning with regard to Bohr’s notion of complementarity, in this paper I try to see Bohr’s post-Como and, in particular, post-EPR philosophy of quantum mechanics in the light of Peircean pragmatism with the hope that such a construal can shed more light to Bohr’s philosophy. I supplement Murdoch’s position on Bohr’s pragmatism by showing that in addition to his complementarity, Bohr’s correspondence principle, instrumentalism and realism can be read on the basis of Peirce’s pragmatic maxim and his notion of indeterminism has commonalities with Peirce’s tychism. Also, Bohr’s practice of applying the correspondence principle can be interpreted in the light of Peirce’s fallibilism. However, when it comes to Bohr’s understanding of the symbolic character of quantum mechanics, Bohr’s philosophy deviates from Peircean pragmatism. Bohr’s philosophy distinguishes between the symbolic language of quantum formalism, which counts as a tool practically useful for prediction, and observation sentences which are visualizable in space and time and refer to the so-called individual phenomena. Such an epistemologically significant distinction is not recognized by Peircean pragmatism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Recently Maleeh and Amani (2013) have listed the shared elements between Bohr’s philosophy and logical positivism.

  2. This is why we sometimes witness huge differences among scholars on interpreting Bohr, even in recent research projects on him. For example, Bokulich (2008) reads Bohr's correspondence principle very differently from the way the majority philosophers read the principle.

  3. Quoted from Bohr (1922, 24).

  4. The adiabatic principle is the first fundamental principle of the older quantum mechanics which addresses the formal applicability of classical mechanics to quantum theory as far a given stationary state is concerned (Jammer 1966, 109).

  5. To achieve the goal of this paper and for the sake of simplicity there is no need to discuss more than these two aspects. I take the formal aspect to include the numerical one. Others have differentiated more than two aspects with regard to the analogy between classical and quantum mechanics in the light of the correspondence principle. For example Radder (1991) distinguishes three aspects: numerical, conceptual and formal. Hartmann (2002) claims that at least seven kinds of correspondence should be taken into consideration: correspondences between theoretical terms, numerical values, observations, initial or boundary conditions, laws, models and structures.

  6. Quoted from Bohr (1922, 12–13).

  7. Translated from German by Brigitte Falkenburg (2007, 190).

  8. Making use of macroscopic measuring devices as well as of quasi-classical measurement theories is inevitable in any quantum experiment. The latter theories “are based on constructing the scales of physical quantities quasi-classically, that is, as if there were physical objects with a given size, mass, charge, momentum and energy” (Falkenburg 2007, 76).

  9. In this way, the intension of a concept, as Carnap (1947) puts it, is pragmatically anchored.

  10. Practical consequences, according to Peirce, should meet two restrictions: they should be general. That is, for example, as regards ‘hard’ objects, we should search for laws that govern the way hard things behave and laws that show how such modes of behavior can make a difference in our rational action. This is the second restriction: practical consequences are restricted to those that affect our ‘intellectual purport’. James did not share such restrictions with Peirce. For him, practical consequences of a proposition can simply be the effects upon the believer.

  11. This phase has been discussed in detail in Radder (1988).

  12. Generally, a phenomenon is the resultant of the interaction between a physical object and measuring device under well-defined experimental conditions. The essential difference between classical and quantum physics is that the interaction in quantum domain must at least comprise one quantum and cannot be made arbitrarily small (Hilgevoord and Uffink 2006). Bohr acknowledges the difference by his ‘quantum postulate’: “[… the] essence [of the formulation of the quantum theory] may be expressed in the so-called quantum postulate, which attributes to any atomic process an essential discontinuity or rather individuality, completely foreign to classical theories and symbolized by Planck's quantum of action” (Bohr 1928, 580). According to Bohr’s construal of the term, in the quantum domain, as we will see soon, the concept of ‘phenomenon’, contrary to classical phenomena, requires indivisibility between the quantum object and the instrument. In this paper, in the context of quantum mechanics, I use ‘quantum phenomena (phenomenon)’ and ‘phenomena (phenomenon)’ interchangeably and to be distinguished from classical sense of the term.

  13. Note that the notion of object-instrument wholeness is not a substitute for the notion of object-instrument interaction. In Bohr’s philosophy the former presupposes the latter.

  14. From now on, till the end of this subsection, I will be summarizing Murdoch’s (1987) ideas on Bohr’s theory of meaning backed up by Bohr’s own quotes.

  15. The way I interpret Bohr’s preconditions of the meaningful ascribability slightly deviates from Murdoch’s interpretation. He distinguishes two meaning conditions: ‘weak meaning condition’ and ‘Strong meaning condition’. The former considers the reference to the experimental arrangement as the necessary, but not sufficient, condition for meaningful ascribability. The sufficient condition is satisfied not only by the reference to a well-defined measuring instrument but also by a phenomenon in Bohr’s technical sense. This idea embraces the notion of strong meaning condition (Murdoch 1987, 148). Thus construed, the reference to the measuring instrument and the notion of phenomenon jointly provide the sufficient condition for the meaningful ascribability. In my view, however, the notion of phenomenon as explicated earlier in this section would suffice as the condition for the meaningful ascribability since it already requires and presupposes reference to the complete description of the entire experimental arrangement. Such a construal squares better with Bohr’s later ideas on the notion of phenomena.

  16. Or as Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker (1980, 185) puts it, for Bohr, the objects are not behind the phenomena, but in the phenomena. Faye (2014) categorizes Bohr in taking such a view as being naturalized or a pragmatized Kantian.

  17. This is why Peirce’s notion of synechism is not in line with Bohr’s philosophy. In synechism, everything is regarded as continuous.

  18. Quantum mechanics qua mathematical theory of motion can be applied to both micro- and macrophysical objects. Quantum mechanics as the theory of matter and radiation, however, only applies to the microphysical realm.

  19. See also Bohr (1954, 67; 1958, 7).

  20. Bohr also rejects the strong instrumentalist view of Mach. Faye (1991, 209) interprets Bohr's statement on the reality of atoms (stated above) as not being a clue to Bohr's ontology, but "as a reaction to the denial in the late nineteenth century, by Ernst Mach and other chemists, of the existence of atoms. Mach was a phenomenalist par excellence … who maintained that both physical and mental phenomena are reducible to certain basic elements of perception, sense data (Empfindungen), which are claimed to be neutral."

References

  • Beller, M. (1999). Quantum dialogue: The making of a revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1913). On the constitution of atoms and molecules. Philosophical Magazine, 26, 1 (Part I); 476 (Part II); 857 (Part III). Reprinted in Bohr, N. (1972–2006). Collected works 2, 161–233.

  • Bohr, N. (1914). Om brintspektret. Fysisk tidsskrift, 12, 97–114; in English in Bohr, (1922), The theory of spectra and atomic constitution (pp. 1–19). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1918). On the quantum theory of line spectra. Reprinted in B. L. Van der Waerden (Ed.), Sources of quantum mechanics (pp. 95–136). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

  • Bohr, N. (1920). Uber die Serienspektren der Elemente. Z. Physik 2, 423–469. English translation in Bohr, (1922).

  • Bohr, N. (1922). The theory of spectra and atomic constitution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1925). Atomic theory and mechanics. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), Philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 1, pp. 25–51). Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1927). The quantum postulate and the recent development of atomic theory. In Atomic theory and the description of nature, 1961. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1928). The quantum postulate and the recent development of atomic theory. Nature, x121, 580–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1929). Introductory survey. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), Philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 1, pp. 1–24). Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1934). Atomic theory and the description of nature. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), Philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 1, pp. 92–101). Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 48(8), 696–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1937). Causality and complementarity. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 4, pp. 83–91).Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1938). The causality problem in atomic physics. Reprinted in Bohr, N. (1972–2006). Collected works (Vol. 7, pp. 303–322).

  • Bohr, N. (1948). On the notions of causality and complementarity. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 4, pp. 141–148). Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1949). Discussion with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 2, pp. 32–66). Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1954). Unity of knowledge. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 2, pp. 67–82). Woodbridge, CN: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1958). Quantum physics and philosophy—Causality and complementarity. In J. Faye & H. J. Folse (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr (Vol. 3, pp. 1–7). Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

  • Bohr, N. (1972–2006). Collected works (Vol. 1–12). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

  • Bohr, N., Kramers, H. A., & Slater, J. C. (1924). The quantum theory of radiation. Reprinted in Van der Waerden, 1967 (pp. 95–136).

  • Bokulich, A. (2008). Reexamining the quantum-classical relation: Beyond reductionism and pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosculluela, V. (1992). Peirce on tychism and determinism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 28(4), 741–755.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1982). Realism. Synthese, 52, 55–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fadner, W. L. (1985). Theoretical support for the generalized correspondence principle. American Journal of Physics, 53, 829–838.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falkenburg, B. (2007). Particle metaphysics. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faye, J. (1991). Niels Bohr: His heritage and legacy. An antirealist view of quantum mechanics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Faye, J. (2008). Niels Bohr and the Vienna Circle. In J. Manninen & F. Stadler (Eds.), The Vienna Circle in the Nordic Countries. (Series: The Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, 14). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Faye, J. (2014). Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/qm-copenhagen/

  • Folse, H. (1986). Niels Bohr, complementarity, and realism. In A. Fine & P. Machamer (Eds.), PSA 1986: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (Vol:1, pp. 96–104). East Lansing, PSA

  • Hartmann, S. (2002). On correspondence. Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, 33, 79–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1930). Physikalische Prinzipien der Quantentheorie, Hirzel, Leipzig. Reprinted in Bibliographisches Institut, Mannheim, 1958.

  • Hilgevoord, J. & Uffink, J. (2006). The Uncertainty Principle. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/qt-uncertainty/

  • Honner, J. (1987). The description of nature: Niels Bohr and the philosophy of quantum physics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (2013). Pragmatism. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/

  • James, W. (1907). Pragmatism: A new name for some old ways of thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (1966). The conceptual development of quantum mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maleeh, R., & Amani, P. (2013). Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(4), 353–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, D. (1987). Niels Bohr’s philosophy of physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1965). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. 1–6. In: C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss (Eds.); Vols. 7–8, A. W. Burks (Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reference in the text includes volume and paragraph number.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1878/1992). How to make our ideas clear. In N. Houser & C. Kloesel (Eds.), The essential Peirce (Vol. 1, pp. 124–141). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Plotnitsky, A. (2006). Reading Bohr: Physics and philosophy. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plotnitsky, A. (2010). Epistemology and probability: Bohr, Heisenberg, Schrödinger and the Nature of quantum-theoretical thinking. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plotnitsky, A. (2012). Niels Bohr and complementarity: An introduction. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pringe, H. (2007). Kant-Studien Ergänzungshefte. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (1988). The material realization of science. Assen: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (1991). Heuristics and the generalized correspondence principle. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 42(2), 195–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (2012). The material realization of science: From habermas to experimentation and referential realism. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Weizsäcker, C. F. (1980). The unity of nature. New York: Farrar Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahar, E. (1983). Logic of discovery or psychology of invention? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34, 243–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Phil Dowe of the School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics, The University of Queensland, for his support and supervision.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Reza Maleeh.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Maleeh, R. Bohr’s Philosophy in the Light of Peircean Pragmatism. J Gen Philos Sci 46, 3–21 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9274-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9274-4

Keywords

Navigation