Skip to main content

Quantum Physics and Cognitive Science from a Wittgensteinian Perspective: Bohr’s Classicism, Chomsky’s Universalism, and Bell’s Contextualism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
WITTGENSTEINIAN (adj.)

Part of the book series: The Frontiers Collection ((FRONTCOLL))

Abstract

Although Wittgenstein’s influence on logic and foundations of mathematics is well recognized, nonetheless, his legacy concerning other sciences is much less elucidated, and in this article we aim at shedding new light on physics, artificial intelligence, and cognitive science from a Wittgensteinian perspective. We focus upon three issues amongst other things: the Chosmky versus Norvig debate on the nature of language; a Neo-Kantian parallelism between Bohr’s philosophy of physics and Hilbert’s philosophy of mathematics; the relationships between cognitive contextuality and physical contextuality as shown by recent Bell-type results. The Chosmky versus Norvig debate may be seen as a battle between Wittgenstein’s earlier and later conceptions of meaning, i.e., picture theory and use theory. From a Wittgensteinian point of view, quantum physics may be seen as a physical version of the Linguistic Turn. The parallelism between Bohr’s philosophy of classical concepts and Hilbert’s philosophy of finitism builds upon transcendental philosophy in the Kantian tradition, both Bohr and Hilbert having been influenced by Neo-Kantian thinkers, such as Hertz, whose sign theory is actually a common root of Wittgenstein’s picture theory and Hilbert’s axiomatics. Wittgenstein is considered a root of contextualism in contemporary philosophy. Contextuality has different manifestations in physics and cognitive science, and contextuality studies across the sciences are rapidly developing in cutting-edge research. We elucidate both analogies and disanalogies between contextuality of reality and contextuality of reason in terms of the nature of probabilities involved. In passing, we also give a (less controversial) reformulation of Penrose’s quantum mind thesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Abramsky, Samson, and Brandenburger, Adam, 2011, The Sheaf-Theoretic Structure Of Non-Locality and Contextuality, New Journal of Physics, vol. 13, 113036.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baird, David, et al. (eds.), 1998, Heinrich Hertz: Classical Physicist, Modern Philosopher, Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bays, Timothy, 2008, Two arguments against realism, Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 58, pp. 193–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bella, Mara, 2001, Quantum Dialogue: The Making of a Revolution, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, Morris, 1981, The Reenchantment of The World, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, Niels, 1934, The quantum of action and the description of nature, in: Atomic theory and the description of nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, Niels, 1949, Discussions with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics, in: Philosopher Scientist, pp. 199–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourguignat, Christophe, 2014, Interpretable VS Powerful Predictive Models : Why We Need Them Both, Medium, 17 September 2014, retrieved on 23 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busemeyer, Jerome, and Bruza, Peter, 2014, Quantum Models of Cognition and Decision, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cass, Stephen, 2011, Unthinking Machines, MIT Technology Review, 4 May 2011, retrieved on 23 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst, 1923, Substance and Function, and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity, Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst, 1945, Structuralism in Modern Linguistics, Word, vol. 1, pp. 99–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst, 1955, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David, 1995, Minds, Machines, and Mathematics, Psyche, vol. 2, pp. 11–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David, 1996, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cervantes, Victor, and Dzhafarov, Ethibar, Snow Queen is Evil and Beautiful: Experimental Evidence for Probabilistic Contextuality in Human Choices, Decision, vol. 5, 193–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam, 1957, Syntactic Structures, Berlin: Mouton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam, 1975, Recent contributions to the theory of innate ideas, in: S. Stitch (ed.), Innate Ideas, Berlin: California University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam, and Ronat, Mitsou, 1979, Language and Responsibility: Based on Conversations with Mitsou Ronat, Paris: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam, 2011, Keynote Panel: The Golden Age — A Look at the Original Roots of Artificial Intelligence, Cognitive Science, and Neuroscience, MIT Symposium on Brains, Minds, and Machines, held in 2011, recording available at: https://mit150.mit.edu/symposia/brains-minds-machines.html, retrieved on 23 June 2019.

  • Christiansen, Frederik Voetmann, 2006, Heinrich Hertz’s Neo-Kantian Philosophy of Science, and its Development by Harald Hoffding, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, vol. 37, pp. 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, Leo, 2004, David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics (1898–1918), Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert, 2007, Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian, Philosophical Psychology, vol. 20, 247–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dzhafarov, Ethibar, et al., 2016, On contextuality in behavioural data, Philos. Trans. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci., vol. 374, 20150234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faye, Jan, 1991, Niels Bohr His Heritage and Legacy: An Anti-Realist View of Quantum Mechanics,

    Google Scholar 

  • Faye, Jan, 2002, Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, Gottlob, 1884, Grundlagen der Arithmetik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael, 2000, A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger, Chicago: Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gold, Kevin, 2011, Norvig vs. Chomsky and the Fight for the Future of AI, TOR.COM, 21 June 2011, retrieved on 26 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, Kurt, 1961, The modern development of the foundations of mathematics in the light of philosophy, in: Collected Works, vol. III, 1981, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, Kurt, 1995, Collected Works, vol. III, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, Jeremy, 2008, Plato’s Ghost: The Modernist Transformation of Mathematics, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, David, et al., 1992, Founders of Constructive Postmodern Philosophy: Peirce, James, Bergson, Whitehead, and Hartshorne, New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, David, 2001, Reenchantment without Supernaturalism, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, David, 1983, “On the Infinite", in: Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, Yarden, 2012, Noam Chomsky on Where Artificial Intelligence Went Wrong, The Atlantic, 1 November 2012, retrieved on 23 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, Hans, and Partee, B., 1995, Compositionality and Prototypes, Cognition, vol. 57, pp. 129–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn and Johnson, 2013, Applied Predictive Modeling, New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, Saul, 1982, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lofts, Steve, 2000, Cassirer: A “Repetition" of Modernity, Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markie, Peter, 2017, Rationalism vs. Empiricism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, James Clerk, 1990, The Scientific Letters and Papers of James Clerk Maxwell: 1846-1862, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norvig, Peter, 2011, On Chomsky and the Two Cultures of Statistical Learning, in: W. Pietsch, J. Wernecke, M. Ott (eds.), Berechenbarkeit der Welt? (pp. 61–83), Wiesbaden: Springer. (made available online in 2011; published in 2017)

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, Charles, 2014, Philosophy of Mathematics in the Twentieth Century: Selected Essays, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patton, Lydia, 2014, Hilbert’s Objectivity, Historia Mathematica, vol. 41, pp. 188–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, Roger, 1989, The Emperor’s New Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, Roger, 1994, Shadows of the Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peter C. Kjaergaard, 2002, Hertz and Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Science, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, vol. 33, pp 121–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pothos, Emmanuel, and Busemeyer, Jerome, 2009, A quantum probability explanation for violations of ‘rational’ decision theory, vol. 276, 1665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary, 1983, Realism and Reason, Philosophical Papers vol. 3, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Oman, 1969, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard, 1962, Realism, Categories, and the “Linguistic Turn”, International Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 2, pp. 307–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard, ed., 1967, The Linguistic Turn: Recent Essays in Philosophical Method, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard, 1970, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, Patrick, 2016, Epistemic Contextualism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya, 1977, Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundations of economic theory, Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 6, pp. 317–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tegmark, Max, 2000, Importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes, Phys. Rev. E, vol. 61, 4194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turney, Peter, and Pantel, Patrick, 2010, From Frequency to Meaning: Vector Space Models of Semantics, Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, vol., 37, pp. 141-188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D., 1982, Judgments of and by representativeness, in: Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Zheng, Solloway, Tyler, Shiffrin, Richard, and Busemeyer, Jerome, 2014, Context effects produced by question orders reveal quantum nature of human judgments, Proc. Nac. Aca. Sci., vol. 111, 9431–9436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weir, Kristen, 2016, A reproducibility crisis?, American Psychological Association, retrieved 23 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1961, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1969, On Certainty, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1970, Zettel, California: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1986, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zach, Richard, 2003, Hilbert’s program, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zach, Richard, 2007, Hilbert’s program then and now, in: Philosophy of Logic, Amsterdam: North Holland. pp. 411–447.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Samson Abramsky for discussions about contextuality, to Kohei Morita for discussions about Bohr and his philosophy of classical concepts, and to Takeo Uramoto for discussions about quantum physics as well as Wittgenstein’s philosophy of language. I hereby acknowledge financial support from JST (grant number: JPMJPR17G9) and JSPS (grant number: 17K14231).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yoshihiro Maruyama .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Maruyama, Y. (2020). Quantum Physics and Cognitive Science from a Wittgensteinian Perspective: Bohr’s Classicism, Chomsky’s Universalism, and Bell’s Contextualism. In: Wuppuluri, S., da Costa, N. (eds) WITTGENSTEINIAN (adj.). The Frontiers Collection. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-27569-3_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics