1 Introduction

This paper contributes to the growing empirical social choice literature which was initiated by the investigations of participants’ individual and group distribution choices by Yaari and Bar-Hillel (1984) as well as Frohlich et al. (1987a) (for overviews see, for example, Konow 2003; Traub et al. 2005; Konow 2009, as well as Gaertner and Schokkaert 2012). This literature shows that participants’ distribution preferences are pluralistic and context-dependent (Konow and Schwettmann 2016). Distribution preferences are pluralistic if they consist of multiple fairness criteria. They are context-dependent if the weight that is given to each criterion depends on institutional factors and personal traits. Apart from the two most important criteria, equality and equity, need has also been identified as relevant in pluralistic justice theories (Konow 2001, 2003; Nicklisch and Paetzel 2020). Moreover, several studies (see, for example, Konow 2001; Schwettmann 2009) have found that people’s support for need-based fairness is balanced against accountability.

However, apart from these stylized facts, not much is known about the quantitative relationship between distribution principles like need and equity, on the one hand, and moderating factors like accountability, on the other hand. In this paper, we will contribute to filling this gap by reporting the results of a vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population in which we analyze the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions.

Following Miller (1999), we define need as the amount of some good that a member of society requires in order to avoid harm. Equity is understood as a variant of Aristotle’s proportionality principle, which holds that output should be allocated in proportion to the participant’s contribution in terms of her productive work effort (Konow 1996). The accountability principle (Konow 2001) is implemented both as responsibility for contribution to output and as responsibility for need.

Participants, who were recruited by an online platform, were asked to divide firewood needed for heating in winter between two hypothetical persons who differed in their need for heat and their productivity in terms of their ability to chop wood (and thus to contribute to the total stock of firewood available). As a novel feature, the study systematically varied the hypothetical persons’ accountability for their neediness as well as for their lower productivity in two separate scenarios.

Our main results are as follows. On average, participants distributed significantly fewer logs of wood to persons who were held accountable for their disadvantage in terms of exhibiting greater need or lower productivity. Independently of being held accountable or not, the needier person was always partially compensated for her disadvantage with a share of logs that exceeded her contribution, while the person who contributed less was given a share of logs smaller than her need share.

When accountability was low, participants did not differentiate between the source of a person’s disadvantage when compensating her with additional logs, that is, greater need and lower productivity were processed symmetrically. In contrast to this, high accountability gave rise to an asymmetry where a disadvantaged person’s compensation was significantly smaller when her disadvantage was due to lower productivity instead of greater need.

We explain this asymmetry by reference points and loss aversion (Tversky and Kahneman 1991), that is, a gain-loss domain effect. If participants perceive the equal-split distribution of logs as a natural reference point (Yaari and Bar-Hillel 1984), loss averse participants might recode the compensation for a self-inflicted disadvantage in terms of a contribution falling below half of the total logs as the reduction of a loss (negative domain) and the compensation for a self-inflicted disadvantage in terms of need exceeding half of the total logs as a gain (positive domain). Hence, due to loss aversion, the former case requires a smaller compensation to establish a just distribution of logs.

Increasing inequality (in terms of different need or productivity) among the two persons left the relative weight put to need and equity unchanged. One case where the disadvantaged person had a deficit of logs and the other person had a surplus made an exception. Here, some participants applied the “net split” principle where both persons received the absolute number of logs they needed plus (or minus) half of the oversupply (or undersupply) of logs.

The analysis of individual choices confirmed that participants were less generous towards the person who was accountable for her own disadvantage. It also showed that the negative impact of accountability was both due to a larger share of participants choosing not to compensate the disadvantaged person at all (extensive margin) and a diminished willingness to compensate her partially (intensive margin). Some participants applied complex distribution principles like the “net split” which cannot be formally represented by a simple convex combination of need, equity, and equality.

Our result concerning the impact of accountability on distribution choices is in line with the vast majority of the empirical and experimental social choice literature which will be reviewed in Sect. 2. For example, Schwettmann (2012), who also used a “heating-in-winter” scenario, found that when the disadvantage of the worse-off individuals was caused by their “careless behaviour” (p. 368), participants chose significantly less often the options that lifted the disadvantaged individual to the poverty line.

Schwettmann (2012) and related studies usually present participants with an exogenously given choice set of distributions that correspond to specific distribution principles such as egalitarianism, Rawls’ maximin principle, or truncated utilitarianism. In our study, we take a different approach by letting participants freely choose how many logs of wood they want to distribute to the persons who differ in their need and productivity. Eliminating the fixed choice set avoids a possible drawback of the expert approach, namely, researcher’s bias (Ahlert et al. 2012), and gives room for behavior more in line with participants’ rather pluralistic opinions about distributive justice.

Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012) comprehensively address methodological issues regarding empirical social choice. They also dwell on the pros and cons of (incentivized) laboratory and (non-incentivized) survey experiments. Empirical research on justice is useful for several reasons. For example, our study, which uses a stratified sample of the German adult population, shows that justice attitudes are linked to personal characteristics such as income; we discover unusual distribution principles like the “net split”; and we contribute data to the development of “empirically informed” pluralistic and context-dependent theories of justice (Konow and Schwettmann 2016). While game-theoretic experiments make predictions about actual behavior, which is to some extent driven by self-interest, Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012) underline that the aim of empirical social choice is to derive information about people’s norms. Vignette studies “provide a contextual richness that is better suited” than incentivized experiments to study fairness judgments embedded in real social institutions (Konow 2009, p. 109).

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 reviews the theoretical background of this study and introduces previous empirical research on the matter. In Sect. 3, we outline the research design, before presenting the data analysis and results in Sect. 4. Section 5 concludes the paper.

2 Literature review

Needs play an important role in political theory (Doyal and Gough 1984; Weale 1984; Nussbaum 1992; Dean 2013), as a policy goal (Esping-Andersen 1990; Boarini and d’Ercole 2006), and are deeply linked with conceptions of the welfare state (Dean 2002; Plant et al. 2009). Because of their fundamental nature—they refer to the basic conditions for human existence—needs have also been proposed by many as the principal normative grounding for human rights (see, for example, Brock 2005; Gasper 2005, and Renzo 2015). As a distributional criterion, need also features prominently in positive justice research (see, for example, Frohlich and Oppenheimer 1990; Scott et al. 2001; Konow 2003; Michelbach et al. 2003; Scott and Bornstein 2009, as well as Liebig and Sauer 2016), suggesting that voters, too, care about needs.

A need can be understood as an amount of some good that a member of society requires in order to avoid harm (see Miller 1999, for an overview on philosophical approaches to need-based justice, see Siebel and Schramme 2020 as well as Miller 2020). Some needs are biological (for example, the amount of calories a person should consume every day), while many others are social in nature (for example, the amount of money necessary to participate in social life). What separates needs from mere wants is, among other things, that the former are based on a socially shared understanding (Miller 1999). That is, for someone’s want to become a need, others must acknowledge that it is necessary for her in order not to be harmed. As an inter-subjectively acknowledged threshold, needs provide a fundamentally different basis of social justice than other criteria, such as equality, equity, and the Rawlsian maximin principle.

Equity is understood here in terms of Aristotle’s proportionality principle, which relates a person’s entitlement to her contribution (Aristotle 2009; Young 1994). Hence, in equity theory (Homans 1958; Adams 1965), this principle is often called the “contribution principle” (compare Diederich 2020).

Our understanding of accountability is based on Konow’s “principle of accountability”. He states that this principle “calls for allocations to be in proportion to volitional contributions” (Konow 2001, p. 138) and that “individuals are only held accountable for factors they may reasonably control” (Konow 2001, p. 142). Hence, the accountability principle differentiates between actual and controllable contributions.

In the context of distributive justice, one might also think of luck egalitarianism, which argues that someone being worse-off than others can only be justified if she is not accountable for her situation. The effects of “brute luck”, therefore, should be compensated, while those resulting from “option luck” do not qualify for compensation (see, for example, Dworkin 1981; Temkin 1993; Knight 2009; Cohen 2011; Tan 2012; an experimental investigation on attitudes towards compensation and risk-taking can be found in Cappelen et al. 2013a). Theoretical considerations in economics are also relevant. For example, Cappelen and Norheim (2005, 2006), Cappelen and Tungodden (2006), as well as Cappelen et al. (2010) investigated the possible relevance of accountability for liberal egalitarian theories of justice.

From an empirical point of view, Konow (2009) highlighted that many empirical and experimental studies have found preferences for unequal distributions, giving room for principles other than equality (for some examples that also include the principle of need, see Deutsch 1975; Leventhal 1976; Lerner 1977; Lamm and Schwinger 1980; Deutsch 1985; Scott et al. 2001; Cappelen et al. 2008).

Concerning need, participants have been found to prefer distributions that grant a minimum income to everyone. For example, Ahlert et al. (2012) have reported great support for the need principle in terms of “truncated utilitarianism” or a “truncated split” in a modified dictator game. Frohlich and Oppenheimer (1992) have demonstrated that maximizing the average income with a floor constraint is the overwhelmingly preferred distribution principle by groups (also see Frohlich et al. 1987a).

Concerning accountability, Weiner (1993) has found that being accountable leads to greater reward or punishment. Weiner and Kukla (1970) have also demonstrated that lack of effort is punished more severely than lack of ability. Skitka and Tetlock (1993a1993b) have shown that personal ideological orientation influences whether accountability has an impact on distribution decisions. Conservatives are in favor of withholding public assistance to people who are accountable for their predicament while liberals tend to help everyone. Konow (1996) has found support for the assumption that persons are only held accountable for variables they can control (for example a person’s work effort).

Moreover, there are some studies that explore need and accountability in combination. Lamm and Schwinger (1980) investigated the influence of social proximity and accountability, calling it “the perceived causal locus of the needs” (p. 426). However, they did not find a significant influence of accountability on distribution choices. Gaertner and Schwettmann (2007) used questionnaire-experimental studies to assess participants’ justice evaluations for scenarios that involved trade-offs between basic needs on the one hand and efficiency or accountability on the other hand. Incorporating a more efficient choice alternative often led to decisions against the needy person. Introducing personal accountability (in terms of having an innate or acquired handicap) had, if at all, a rather weak impact on justice evaluations. Using a charity game, Buitrago et al. (2009) explored whether it makes a difference if the causes of neediness were known or not, including cases in which neediness was self-inflicted by low effort. They did not find a significant effect, concluding that “help attitudes may result from idiosyncratic preferences, which are unaffected by the causes of neediness” (p. 83).

In contrast to this, Konow (2001) found that telephone and questionnaire survey participants’ support for need-based justice was balanced against both accountability and efficiency. Schwettmann (2012), using a questionnaire study, presented participants with distribution problems that required them to distribute a resource between two groups, providing them with information on benefit, need, efficiency, and accountability. He found strong support for need-oriented distribution choices that were not influenced by concerns for efficiency. Accountability, though, had a significant impact on distribution decisions. When a group was accountable for a shortage of supplies, fewer participants decided to lift its members up to the need threshold. Furthermore, Cappelen et al. (2013b) has found evidence for the influence of need (represented by subjects from low-income countries) and accountability (represented by “entitlement” through real-effort tasks) in a dictator game.

Skitka and Tetlock (1992) have investigated the influence of the causes of neediness on subjects’ readiness to help others. They concluded that subjects “are least likely to help victims whose need is attributed to internal-controllable causes—such as carelessness, laziness, greed, and self indulgence” (p. 496f.). This conclusion is supported by other studies, which all find that performance and accountability have an influence on the support for need as a distribution criterion (see Wagstaff 1994; Farwell and Weiner 1996, as well as Scott and Bornstein 2009).

A considerable literature deals with medical interventions that can obviously be considered as situations of (basic) need satisfaction. For example, Ubel et al. (2001) investigated the influence of accountability on hypothetical decisions for the allocation of transplant livers (also see Neuberger et al. 1998). Those who were accountable for their illness received the transplant less often. Diederich and Schreier (2010) have confirmed the relevance of accountability for prioritization in health care using a mixed-methods design (also see Diederich et al. 2014). Similar results have been obtained by Betancourt (1990), Karasawa (1991), Murphy-Berman et al. (1984), Turner DePalma et al. (1999), as well as Yamauchi and Lee (1999). Annas (1985) and Stanton (1999) have shown the relevance of accountability for the allocation of scarce life-saving technology. Finally, Fowler et al. (1994) have shown that clinical services directed at patients that can be held accountable for their illness were considered a lower priority.

In summary, apart from a small number of exceptions, the literature finds—in a wide range of different scenarios—a significant negative impact of a person’s accountability for her neediness on other persons’ willingness to distribute resources to her. This paper contributes to this literature by reporting the results of a novel vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population that analyzes the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions.

In the following section, we introduce the design of our vignette study. As noted by Konow (2003), vignette studies provide a flexible and easily controllable way to present relevant contextual information to participants. In particular, the empirical social choice literature, pioneered by Yaari and Bar-Hillel (1984), relies on such designs to study preferences for distributions in hypothetical scenarios (overviews are given by Schokkaert 1999; Schwettmann 2009, as well as Gaertner and Schokkaert 2012). As suggested by Konow (2003, 2005), subjects acted as impartial decision-makers in order to avoid self-serving bias. Like Schwettmann (2012), we used heating in winter as a background story. The accountability framing followed Diederich and Schreier (2010), who also used smoking and hereditary factors as causes for a disease, as well as Skitka and Tetlock (1992), who also named the disregard of a doctor’s warning and a gene defect as causes for low and high accountability.

However, most of the above mentioned experimental social choice studies (for example, Gaertner and Schwettmann 2007; Schwettmann 2012; Ahlert et al. 2012) are based on sets of predefined choice alternatives in terms of distributions of resources among two or more persons that correspond to certain normative distribution principles (such as egalitarianism, Rawls’ maximin criterion, and truncated utilitarianism). That is, in these settings, subjects or groups make choices between standards of behavior that were devised by experts. Like in a beauty contest, the standard of behavior that is met with the greatest approval from subjects is declared the winner.

A distinct advantage of this expert driven approach is its ability to provide direct tests of certain axioms and normative theories of distributive justice (see Frohlich et al. 1987a for a prototypical experiment; see Bauer and Meyerhuber 2019, 2020 for general considerations on the interplay of empirical research and normative theory). A drawback of this approach is that such preselections may involve researcher’s bias (Ahlert et al. 2012). Related to the previous argument, people’s opinions about distributive justice frequently are in conflict with these traditional norms and assumptions (see Schokkaert 1999; also see Amiel and Cowell 1999 as well as Traub et al. 2005). Moreover, as noted by Ahlert et al. (2012), rankings of monistic distribution principles according to their approval by subjects in choice experiments do not adequately reflect the fact that “pluralism of distribution principles is the predominant outcome of many empirical investigations” (p. 980; also see Konow 2003).

Consequently, although this study has been heavily inspired by the aforementioned literature, we took a different path by letting participants freely choose how much of a given resource they want to distribute among two persons who differ in their need, productivity, and accountability. This procedure is similar to Question 3 in (Konow 2009). A related approach, though in a modified dictator-game setting, was taken by Andreoni and Miller (2002) as well as Fisman et al. (2007), who let subjects divide fixed amounts of tokens between themselves and another subject with varying prices for payoffs. Hence, whether or not these endogenously determined distributions meet certain distribution principles is an outcome of the study. The main goal of this paper is to quantitatively measure the impact of giving information on accountability on participants’ distribution decisions while systematically varying recipients’ need and productivity.

3 Study design

In Sect. 3.1, we first describe the vignette-based study design. In Sect. 3.2, we then describes the procedure of the study. After that, in Sect. 3.3, we formulate working hypotheses about the impact of different accountability framings and scenarios on participants’ distribution choices.

3.1 The vignettes

In the vignettes, we asked participants to imagine two persons, denoted “Person A” and “Person B”, who do not know each other (for the instructions and the exact wording of the vignette, see Appendix A; we used a set of common German surnames to identify the protagonists). Participants were told that these two persons heat their homes exclusively with firewood and that both have enough logs in stock to survive the upcoming winter. Nonetheless, they need additional firewood so that they will not feel cold. With this in mind, the community allows them to chop wood in the community forest for a certain period of time. Both A and B have little money and, therefore, they have no other means of getting firewood or any other heating material.

In accordance with our definition of need as the amount of some good that a member of society requires in order to avoid harm, the vignettes described the consequences of unfulfilled need (“If they get less than they need, it will get unreasonably cold in their huts. The less firewood they get, the colder their huts will be.”). The participants’ task was to distribute an exogenously given number of logs among A and B. In order to justify unequal distributions of logs, we introduced heterogeneity between A and B with respect to their need for logs, or their productivity in terms of the number of logs contributed, and their accountability for their situation.

Participants’ distribution choices therefore reveal how far need is acknowledged, and whether and how the acknowledgment of need is affected by the two persons’ heterogeneity. Note that we intentionally described the consequences of unfulfilled need as mildly harmful (“[...] it will become unreasonably cold in their huts.”) and not as life threatening in order to leave participants more scope for judgment. We also allowed for over-fulfillment of need (“The persons can use more firewood than they need to heat their huts up to pleasant temperatures or store it for subsequent winters.”) in order to study how participants handle mixed situations (where one person has unfulfilled need and the other has fulfilled need) and situations of “oversupply” (where both persons have different fulfilled needs).

In the following, we call the framing of the vignette with respect to need and productivity scenario and the framing with respect to accountability treatment. The study consisted of two treatments (accountability framings). In the High Accountability Treatment, participants were told that Person A had continued to smoke heavily against the advice of her doctor, which caused a metabolic disease. This is the reason why she needs a higher room temperature (being accountable for greater need in the Need Scenario) or has chopped less wood (being accountable for lower productivity in the Productivity Scenario). In the Low Accountability Treatment, Person A suffers from a congenital metabolic disease, which is why she needs a higher room temperature (hence not accountable for greater need in the Need Scenario) or has chopped less wood (hence not accountable for lower productivity in the Productivity Scenario).

Participants were randomly assigned to one of the two treatments in the beginning of the study. That is, the treatment effect of the source of heterogeneity—high or low accountability—on participants’ distribution decisions was measured at the between-participants level. In both treatments, all participants were presented both scenarios in randomized order. Hence, the impact of the type of heterogeneity—need or productivity differences—on participants’ distribution decisions was measured at the within-participants level.

Table 1 Parametrization of the vignette by scenario and case

Pretests showed that we could place up to a dozen different cases in our online survey that should not last longer than 30 min altogether (including a post-survey questionnaire). Hence, we decided to present each participant with ten different cases, five per scenario (a sixth case per scenario, which we dropped from the analysis, was used only as a consistency check). The cases varied the amount and distribution of needs and contributed logs. Participants were presented the cases of each scenario in a randomized order. They were shown the number of logs contributed by Person A and Person B (productivity), the number of logs needed by A and B (need), the total number of logs needed and the total number of logs contributed. Participants were then asked to distribute the logs between the two persons according to what they thought to be “most just”. Participants distributed the logs freely among the hypothetical persons, without being provided with predefined or default options. However, participants always had to allocate all available resources to A and B.

When asking participants for the “most just” distribution, we assume (i) that they care about justice and (ii) that some possible distributions are judged as more just than others. In the literature, there are basically two approaches assuring that the elicitation of participants’ fairness preferences is unbiased by selfish motives. One approach holds that, in order to discover “which pattern is the most just” (Frohlich et al. 1987b, p. 2), participants must be able to rationally evaluate the fairness of different distributions “under conditions of very imperfect information”, that is, in a position that creates impartiality of involved social planners by a (more or less transparent) veil of ignorance. In this paper, we follow—like many of the empirical and experimental studies mentioned in the literature review—the quasi-spectator method. The quasi-spectator “is an observer who has no salient stakes in the matter at hand and possesses some, if not all, information relevant to his internalized moral values” (Konow 2009, p. 106). Hence, our vignette study is concerned with the fairness views of third parties.

Table 1 shows the parametrization of the vignette by scenario and case. Let \(p_i^s\) and \(n_i^s\) denote \(i\in \{A,B\}\)’s productivity and need in scenario \(s\in \{(N)eed,(P)roductivity\}\). As shown in the table, the Need Scenario provided both persons with \(p_A^N=p_B^N=1000\) logs (equal constant productivity), but different needs. For example, in case 2, A’s (B’s) need of \(n^N_A=1400\) (\(n^N_B=800\)) logs was greater (smaller) than her productivity of 1000 logs, and their joint need of \(n^N=2200\) logs was greater than their total productivity of \(p^N=2000\) logs. Likewise, the Productivity Scenario attached an equal constant need of \(n^P_A=n^P_B=1000\) logs to both persons, but varied their productivity. For example, in case 2, A’s (B’s) productivity of \(p^P_A=800\) (\(p^P_B=1400\)) logs was insufficient (more than sufficient) to meet her need of 1000 logs, and their joint productivity of \(p^P=2200\) logs was sufficient to meet their total need of \(n^P=2000\). Note that in both scenarios, Person A was always in the disadvantaged position, that is, she was more needy or less productive than Person B.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Study design. The figure shows the parametrization of the vignette in a log-distribution diagram by case and scenario. \(x_i^s\) is the number of logs distributed to Person \(i\in \{A,B\}\) in scenario \(s\in \{N,P\}\). \(P^s\) and \(N^s\) are the distributions of need and productivity, and \(n^s\) and \(p^s\) are the total need and total productivity that were presented to the participants. \(P^N\) and \(N^P\) are located on the \(\alpha =45^\circ\) line of equality (\(x_A=x_B\)). \(N^N\) is located on the \(\alpha '\) degree line through the origin, and \(P^P\) is located on the \(90-\alpha '\) degree line through the origin. It is expected that participants pick the just distribution from the line \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) in the Need Scenario and \(\overline{P^P\rho }\) in the Productivity Scenario. Distributions in the grey shaded area at the top right of \(P^N\) (\(N^P\)) involve a deficit (surplus) to both A and B. Distributions in the grey shaded area at the bottom left of \(P^N\) (\(N^P\)) involve a surplus (deficit) to both A and B. Distributions in the white areas are mixed

The parametrization of the vignettes enables studying the effect of the supply situation (D = deficit, S = surplus, X = exact need satisfaction) and the source of heterogeneity on the distribution of logs among A and B. Figure 1 illustrates the design of the cases. Case 1, displayed in the top left diagram, introduces a situation where both A and B have a deficit of logs (DD) in the Need Scenario and a surplus of logs (SS) in the Productivity Scenario.

In the Need Scenario, total productivity is displayed as a straight “supply” line with intercept \(p^N\). Point \(P^N\) on this line marks the actual distribution of productivity. Total need is displayed as a straight “demand” line with intercept \(n^N\). Point \(N^N\) on this line marks the distribution of need. Since \(N^N\) is located in the grey shaded area at the top right of \(P^N\), both A and B have a deficit. And since \(N^N\) is located to the right of the \(45^\circ\) line of equality (where \(x_A=x_B\)), A is worse off than B because she has a bigger deficit.

Analogously, in the Productivity Scenario, total productivity is displayed as a straight line with intercept \(p^P\), and point \(P^P\) on this line marks the actual distribution of productivity. Total need is displayed as a straight line with intercept \(n^P\), and point \(N^P\) on this line marks the distribution of need. Since \(P^P\) is located in the grey shaded area at the top right of \(N^P\), both A and B have a surplus. And since \(P^P\) is located to the left of the \(45^\circ\) line of equality, A is worse off than B because she has a lower surplus. Hence, case 1 in the Productivity Scenario is a mirror image of case 1 in the Need Scenario where the source of heterogeneity and A’s disadvantage is either need or productivity.

The other cases are constructed similarly. In case 2 in the top right diagram of Fig. 1, A has a deficit and B a surplus in the Need Scenario (point \(N^N\) is in the area at the bottom right of \(N^P\)), and A has a surplus and B a deficit in the Productivity Scenario (point \(P^P\) is in the area at the top left of \(P^N\)). Case 3 in the bottom left diagram shows a situation where A’s need is either exactly satisfied or she has surplus, and where B has a surplus or her need is exactly satisfied, depending on the scenario. In cases 4 and 5, \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) are located in the grey shaded area at the bottom left of \(P^N\) and \(N^P\), respectively, and, hence, both A and B have a surplus in the Need Scenario or a surplus in the Productivity Scenario. Case 5 “doubles” case 4, has a slightly different parametrization, and was included to study participants’ sensitivity towards need in more “extreme” situations. The results regarding this question will be reported in a different paper.

3.2 Procedures

Since participants received only a flat payment, we promoted internal validity by asking three control questions after the distribution task in order to make sure that the participants read the instructions carefully and actually understood the task. For the wording of the control questions, see Appendix B. Only those who passed at least two out of three checks were included in the final analysis.

In order to control for participants’ heterogeneity with regard to their socio-demographics and justice attitudes, we asked them, in a post-survey questionnaire, for their age, gender, and equivalent household net income and to state their support for three different distribution principles—need, equity, and equality (compare, for example, Skitka and Tetlock 1992 as well as Mitchell et al. 1993) as well as their evaluation of Person A’s accountability for her situation on a 7-point Likert scale. We also assessed participants’ perceived locus of control in a similar way (see Fong 2001; Phares and Lamiell 1975) and collected information on participants’ health status (dummy variables for being a smoker and suffering from a cardiovascular or metabolic disease). Ubel et al. (2001) found that smokers tend to punish unhealthy behavior regarding the need for transplant organs less often than participants who never smoked (also see Diederich and Schreier 2010). Participants were also asked for their political orientations using a 7-point Likert scale ranging from 1 (most left-wing) to 7 (most right-wing), see Appendix B for wordings.

The survey was programmed in oTree (Chen et al. 2016) and conducted online in September 2019. For reasons of external validity, participants were recruited via the private market research institute respondi. We used respondi’s Online Access Panel which offers a quota sample of the German adult population. Our sample is a random sample of the Online Access Panel, stratified by the three characteristics gender, age, and equivalent household net income, with a sample-size of \(N=200\) (for a breakdown of the sample by gender, age, and income, see Table 9 in Appendix E). The sampling rates of these characteristics in our sample are representative of the adult German population. On the importance of a sample being representative if empirical research is considered as relevant for normative theory, see Schwettmann (2020). Due to financial constraints, though, it was not possible to draw a larger sample that would potentially have captured more characteristics of the German population. The 200 participants who passed the control questions were paid a flat fee of 4.90 euro, equal to 9.80 euro per hour. Note that a further 203 persons started the survey but failed to pass the control questions. These persons were not asked any further questions and did not receive any payment. It was announced by respondi in the beginning of the study that failure to answer the control questions correctly would lead to exclusion from the study without being compensated. The control questions generated similar failure rates (Q1: 29%, Q2: 31%, Q3: 38%). Participants who failed to pass the control questions did not differ from included participants by their stratification characteristics (gender: \(\chi _1^2=0.517\), \(p=0.526\); age: \(\chi _4^2=5.083\), \(p=0.279\); income: \(\chi _4^2=3.447\), \(p=0.486\)). The enormous amount of dropouts shows that general population samples without performance-related incentives can potentially generate a lot of noise in the data. Hence, relatively strict exclusion criteria should be applied.

Before conducting the main study, we tested the efficacy of the vignette with respect to the accountability framing. All details of the pretest are reported in Appendix C. It clearly confirmed that participants attribute higher accountability to persons who disregard their doctor’s warning.

3.3 Working hypotheses

As explained above, participants were asked to distribute the logs between A and B according to what they thought to be most just. Let \(x_i^s\) denote the number of logs distributed to person \(i\in \{A,B\}\) in scenario \(s\in \{N,P\}\). We assume that participants maximize the justice J of the distribution \((x_A^s,x_B^s)\) subject to \(x_B^s=p_A^s+p_B^s-x_A^s\) where the parametrization of the vignette by case and scenario with respect to need \((n_A^s,n_B^s)\), productivity \((p_A^s,p_B^s)\), and accountability treatment \(T=\{low,high\}\) is given. Hence, the optimum number of logs distributed to person A is given by

$$\begin{aligned} x_A^{s*}=\arg \max J(x_A,p_A+p_B-x_A|n_A,n_B,p_A,p_B,T). \end{aligned}$$
(1)

Since we study the justice views of laypersons in terms of participants’ actual distribution choices \(x_A^{s*}\), J is not further specified or “axiomatized”. For a comprehensive account of justice evaluation functions, see Jasso (1978) and Jasso et al. (2016).

We consider two outcome measures of the experiment which both are based on \(x_A^{s*}\). Since the total number of logs available differs from case to case and between the scenarios, we normalize \(x_A^{s*}\) by Person A’s and Person B’s total productivity, \(p^s\), to obtain the first outcome measure, namely, the share of logs distributed to Person A:

$$\begin{aligned} \text{ logshare}_A^s=\frac{x_A^{s*}}{p^s}. \end{aligned}$$
(2)

For example, point \(P^N\) in case 1 in Fig. 1 shows a situation where the logs are distributed exactly according to productivity. Thus, we have \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=0.5\) and \(\tan ^{-1}(x^N_B/x^N_A)=\tan ^{-1}(1000/1000)=45^\circ =\alpha\). Analogously, point \(\nu\) where the line through the origin \(\overline{0N^N}\) and the “supply” line \(p^N\) intersect, shows a situation where the logs are distributed proportional to need. Thus, we have \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=0.6\) and \(\tan ^{-1}(800/1200)=\alpha '=34^\circ\).

The second outcome measure is the normalized deviation from the equal split in favor of Person A:

$$\begin{aligned} \text{ deviation}_A^s=\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \frac{\text{ logshare}_A^s-0.5}{n_A^s/n^s-0.5} &{} \quad \text{(Need } \text{ Scenario) } \\ \frac{0.5-\text{ logshare}_A^s}{0.5-p_A^s/p^s} &{} \quad \text{(Productvitiy } \text{ Scenario) }. \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(3)

The allocation that distributes resources equally—the equal split—has been demonstrated to serve as a natural reference point or social norm for bargaining processes (compare, for example, Yaari and Bar-Hillel 1984; Dawid and Dermietzel 2006, as well as Andreoni and Bernheim 2009). In bargaining experiments, participants frequently choose equal-split allocations even though they are Pareto dominated (Herreiner and Puppe 2010). However, in social choice experiments, only a minority of participants still opts for the equal split when objective reasons like need differences speak in favor of an unequal distribution (Gaertner and Schokkaert 2012). Hence, participants’ sense of justice is reflected in the deviation from the equal split.

We have \(\text{ deviation}_A^s=0\) (equal split) when participants think that heterogeneity among A and B is irrelevant. In Fig. 1, equal-split distributions are located on the \(45^\circ\) line which goes through points \(N^P\) (equal productivity) and \(P^N\) (equal need). We have \(\text{ deviation}_A^s>0\) when participants think that A should be compensated for her disadvantage due to greater need (clockwise rotation) or smaller productivity (counterclockwise rotation). Observations that do not meet the condition \(0\le \text{ deviation}_A^s\le 1\), that is, choices that make A’s situation even worse than it is or make A better off than B are considered as noise in the analysis.

We expect that, on average, participants distribute more than A’s productivity share and less than A’s need share to her, because they think it is just to partially compensate A for her disadvantage. Consequently, \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) in the Productivity Scenario is smaller than in the Need Scenario because A’s need share in the Productivity Scenario is 50% (the upper bound for \(\text{ logshare}_A^P\)), and her productivity share in the Need Scenario is also 50% (the lower bound for \(\text{ logshare}_A^N\)). Hence, the deviation from the equal split is between zero and one. Put into graphs, we expect participants to pick the just distributions from the line \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) in the Need Scenario and from the line \(\overline{P^P\rho }\) in the Productivity Scenario in Fig. 1.

Hypothesis 1

(Partial Compensation) Participants compensate Person A partially for her disadvantage: \(p_A^s/p^s<\text{ logshare}_A^s<n_A^s/n^s\). Partial compensation implies that \(\text{ logshare}_A^P<0.5<\text{ logshare}_A^N\) and \(0<\text{ deviation}_A^s<1\).

We expect that participants’ willingness to compensate Person A for her disadvantage is diminished by high accountability. Hence, participants distribute fewer logs to A and they favor smaller (greater) deviations from the equal split in the Need Scenario (Productivity Scenario).

Hypothesis 2

(Accountability) The just distribution of logs depends on A’s accountability such that

  1. (a)

    \(\text{ logshare}_A^s(low)>\text{ logshare}_A^s(high)\),

  2. (b)

    \(\text{ deviation}_A^N(low)>\text{ deviation}_A^N(high)\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^P(low)<\text{ deviation}_A^P(high)\).

If J is homogeneous in the number of logs, A’s just share of logs is determined by her need share and her productivity share, and not by total need and total productivity. Let \(\alpha ^s=\tan ^{-1}(x_B^{s*}/x_A^{s*})\) denote the angle of the line through the origin that contains all just distributions. Since Need Scenario and Productivity Scenario are mirror images of each other, we expect \(45^\circ -\alpha ^N=\alpha ^P-45^\circ\) which is equivalent to \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\text{ logshare}_A^P\). This implies that the just deviation from the equal split is independent of the scenario as indicated by the black arrows in Fig. 1.

Hypothesis 3

(Scenario) Disadvantages that are due to greater need and smaller productivity are treated symmetrically, that is, \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\text{ logshare}_A^P\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^N=\text{ deviation}_A^P\).

However, one could argue that the cognitive perception of the scenarios differs because the equal split is seen as a reference point (Trueblood 2015). Loss averse participants might find compensating A less justified when her disadvantage is due to lower contribution (negative domain, reduction of a loss for A) than when her disadvantage is due to greater need (positive domain, gain for A). Hence, there could be a gain-loss domain effect (Tversky and Kahneman 1991, also see Weiß et al. 2017) that would imply \(\text{ deviation}_A^P>\text{ deviation}_A^N\). Moreover, there could also be an interaction effect between scenario framing and accountability treatment.

As can be seen in Table 1 and Fig. 1, the five cases differ by their supply situation. Figure 1 shows that \(P^N\) and \(N^P\) remain constant, while \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) are obtained from systematically changing both relative inequality in productivity or need (visualized by the angles of the dashed lines through \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) to the line of equality) and total need or total productivity (visualized by the “demand” and “supply” lines). Hence, the study design does not allow the separation of both possible effects on the just distribution of logs. Keeping relative inequality constant would have led to very small absolute need and productivity differences in cases where \(N^N\) and \(P^P\) are located in the grey shaded area at the bottom left of \(P^N\) and \(N^P\). Hence, we decided to additionally increase relative inequality among A and B.

In order to deal with this problem, we first assume that the absolute supply situation in terms of A having a deficit or surplus (the location of the “demand” and “supply” lines) does not affect participants’ justice considerations. Hence, in the Need Scenario, we expect that the share of logs that is distributed to A increases in relative inequality when moving from case 1 to 5 because point \(\nu\) moves outward on the line of just distributions \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) and \(\alpha '\) decreases. The opposite applies to the Productivity Scenario where \(P^P\) moves outward on the line of just distributions \(\overline{P^P\rho }\) and \(90-\alpha '\) increases. Hence, in the Need Scenario (Productivity Scenario), we hypothesize that participants distribute relatively more (less) logs to A when a case exhibits greater inequality among A and B. Since the deviation from the equal split is normalized by the difference between A’s need share and her productivity share (the length of \(\overline{P^N\nu }\) and \(\overline{P^P\rho }\)), we expect it to be independent of the supply situation.

Hypothesis 4

(Supply situation) Let \(y,z\in \{1,2,3,4,5\}\) denote the number of the case where \(y<z\) and cases with lower numbers exhibit less inequality (with respect to need or productivity) among A and B, then we have \(\text{ logshare}_A^N(z)-\text{ logshare}_A^P(z)>\text{ logshare}_A^N(y)-\text{ logshare}_A^P(y)\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s(y)=\text{ deviation}_A^s(z)\).

If the absolute supply situation matters for the distribution of logs, it is likely to have a dampening effect in the Need Scenario (A receives relatively less, \(\alpha '\) decreases less) because increasing inequality is combined with an improving absolute supply situation (Person A starts with a deficit and ends up with a surplus). It is also likely to have a dampening effect in the Productivity Scenario (A receives relatively more, \(90-\alpha '\) increases less) because increasing inequality is combined with a worsening absolute supply situation (Person A starts with a surplus and ends up with a deficit). Hence, the two scenario differences in H4 might get smaller, but the effect of increasing inequality should remain.

4 Results

We begin the presentation of the results with participants’ responses to the accountability question posed in the post-survey questionnaire. In order to interpret the results of this study in terms of Person A’s accountability for her disadvantage, it is necessary to establish that the accountability framing actually worked. As noted in the previous section, the vignette design had already been successfully tested in a pretest, though with a student sample. Next, in Sect. 4.2, we test our working hypotheses by studying participants’ average distribution choices. In Sect. 4.3, we then turn to participants’ individual distribution choices, and we identify different distribution principles that participants consistently applied in order to distribute the logs of wood to Persons A and B.

4.1 Accountability judgments

Figure 2 shows participants’ mean judgment of Person A’s accountability for her greater need and her lower productivity on a 7-point Likert scale. A two-tailed t test confirms that, in both scenarios, the bar representing the High Accountability Treatment is significantly larger than the one representing the low accountability treatment (Need Scenario, High Accountability Treatment: mean \(=5.00\) (90% CI [4.72, 5.28]), Low Accountability Treatment: mean \(=4.04\) (90% CI [3.75, 4.34]), mean difference \(=0.96\) (90% CI [0.55, 1.36]), \(p\le 0.01\); Productivity Scenario, High Accountability Treatment: mean \(=5.16\) (90% CI [4.88, 5.43]), Low Accountability Treatment: mean \(=3.98\) (90% CI [3.68, 4.28]), mean difference \(=1.18\) (90% CI [0.78, 1.58]), \(p\le 0.01\); two-sample two-tailed t test, between-participants treatment). Hence, as already suggested by the pretest, the vignette was effective for inducing a low and a high accountability frame in participants with respect to Person A’s disadvantage.

Moreover, Fig. 2 indicates that there is no significant difference in participants’ mean judgment of Person A’s accountability between Need and Productivity Scenario. A pairwise two-tailed t test cannot reject the null hypothesis of equality of the mean accountability judgment (High Accountability Treatment, Need Scenario vs. Productivity Scenario: mean difference \(= -0.16\) (90% CI \([-0.31, 0.02]\)), \(p = 0.104\); Low Accountability Treatment, Need Scenario vs. Productivity Scenario: mean difference \(=0.07\) (90% CI \([-0.18, 0.31]\)), \(p = 0.659\); paired-sample two-tailed t test, within-participants treatment). Hence, we conclude that it did not matter to the participants whether A’s disadvantage was caused by need or productivity differences.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Mean accountability judgment by treatment and scenario. The figure shows participants’ mean judgment of Person A’s accountability for her greater need (lower productivity) in the Low (High) Accountability Treatment using a 7-point Likert scale. Larger numbers mean greater accountability. The grey (white) bars represent \(N=91\) (\(N=109\)) observations each. Error bars represent 90% confidence intervals for the mean. p value of a two-tailed two-sample t test (between-participants)

4.2 Average distribution choices

In this subsection, we turn to our main interest, namely, the impact of scenario and accountability treatment on the just distribution of logs. We also analyze how the supply situation affects the distribution of logs. The following analyses of \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s\) are based on 2000 distribution choices (10 per participant). Note that only 208 distribution choices (10.4%) do not meet the condition \(0\le \text{ deviation}_A\le 1\).

4.2.1 Means

Figure 3 displays \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) as a bar chart (left panels) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s\) as a range plot (right panels). The top panels show the distribution of logs by treatment and scenario; the middle (bottom) panels show the distribution of logs in the Need Scenario (Productivity Scenario) by treatment and case. Means, standard errors, cases numbers, and t tests can be seen in Tables 10 and 11 in Appendix E.

Fig. 3
figure 3

Distribution of logs. The bars show the mean share of logs distributed to Person A (\(\text{ logshare}_A^s\)) by scenario and treatment (top left panel), by treatment and case in the Need Scenario (middle left panel), and by treatment and case in the Productivity Scenario (bottom left panel). The solid (dashed) line indicates Person A’s need (productivity) share. The range plots show the mean relative deviation from the equal split (\(\text{ deviation}_A^s\)) by scenario and treatment (top right panel), by treatment and case in the Need Scenario (middle left panel), and by treatment and case in the Productivity Scenario (bottom left panel). Error bars represent 90% confidence intervals for the mean. For case numbers, means, standard errors, and t tests see Tables 10 and 11 in Appendix E. Supply situation of A and B: D = deficit, S = surplus, X = exact need satisfaction

Concerning the partial compensation hypothesis (H1), the bar charts show as hypothesized that participants on average distributed significantly more logs to Person A than her productivity share and significantly less than her need share in all scenarios, treatments, and cases. Consequently, \(\text{ logshare}_A\) exceeds 50% in the Need Scenario and falls below 50% in the Productivity Scenario. The range plots of \(\text{ deviation}_A\) lie between 0 and 1.

The accountability hypothesis (H2) is clearly confirmed by the data, too. As regards the share of logs distributed to A, the treatment effect of high accountability is significant in all cases except for case 1 in the Need Scenario (see Table 10). As regards the deviation from the equal split, the treatment effect is also significant (except for case 1), and it is negative in the Need Scenario and positive in the Productivity Scenario (see Table 11 in the Appendix) as hypothesized.

The hypotheses concerning the symmetry of the scenarios (H3) and the impact of the supply situation (H4) are tested using regression analysis. Test results are reported in the following paragraphs.

Fig. 4
figure 4

Marginal effects. Left panels: marginal effect (\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A^s\)) of the Productivity Scenario (top) and of High Accountability (bottom) estimated from a GLS random effects panel regression. The thick lines in the top left panel indicate the reference values for testing symmetry of the scenarios. Right panels: marginal effect (\(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A^s\)) and negative absolute marginal effect (\(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A^s|\)) of the Productivity Scenario (top) and the High Accountability Treatment (bottom) estimated from a tobit random effects panel regression. Error bars represent 90% confidence intervals for the mean

4.2.2 Marginal effects of scenario and supply situation

The analysis of means controls neither for participants’ socio-demographics and attitudes nor for potential ordering effects. Hence, we perform regression analysis. All statistical details and tables are given in Appendix D. The estimated marginal effects of scenario, supply situation, and accountability treatment are displayed in Fig. 4.

First, we turn to the marginal effects of scenario and supply situation on the share of logs. The top left panel of Fig. 4 displays the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario (the Need Scenario is the benchmark case) on the share of logs distributed to A by accountability treatment and case. All marginal effects are negatively significant as hypothesized by the partial compensation hypothesis (H1). There is no difference between the accountability treatments with respect to the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario, except for case 1 (see Table 5 in Appendix D).

A pairwise comparison of the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario by case shows that the negative impact of the Productivity Scenario in cases 4 and 5 is significantly greater than in case 1. This confirms the supply-situation hypothesis (H4) which holds that increasing inequality with respect to need or productivity among A and B causes greater differences of A’s just share of logs between the scenarios (see the top panel of Table 8 in Appendix D, significance levels are corrected for multiple hypotheses testing using the Bonferroni correction).

In order to test the symmetry of the scenarios (H3), we first compute \(\text{ logshare}_A^N\) and \(\text{ logshare}_A^P\), and then we test \(\text{ logshare}_A^N=1-\text{ logshare}_A^P\). In the top left panel of Fig. 4, the thick lines indicate the reference values for testing symmetry of the scenarios. As can be seen in Fig. 4, in the Low Accountability Treatment, symmetry cannot be rejected, except for cases 2 and 3 where the positive difference of A’s share of logs from 50% in the Need Scenario exceeded the negative difference of her share of logs from 50% in the Productivity Scenario. In the High Accountability Treatment, symmetry is clearly rejected (except for case 2). Just distributions are “biased” in the direction discussed in Sect. 3.3; participants deviated more from the equal-split distribution when A’s disadvantage was due to lower productivity than when it was due to greater need (see Table 6 in Appendix D).

The top right panel of Fig. 4 displays the marginal effect of the Productivity Scenario on the deviation from the equal split by accountability treatment and case (also see Table 5 in Appendix D). Except for case 2 in both treatments as well as cases 1 and 3 in the High Accountability Treatment, all marginal effects are positively significant, thereby rejecting the hypothesis that disadvantages due to greater need and smaller productivity are treated symmetrically (H3). High accountability dampens the asymmetry because the share of respondents who are not all willing to compensate Person A for her disadvantage is relatively high in both scenarios.

Case 2 differs significantly from all other cases. In this regard, we have to qualify our previous conclusion that H4 (\(\text{ deviation}_A^s(y)=\text{ deviation}_A^s(z)\)) is supported by the data. Remember that case 2 involves a deficit for A and a surplus for B in both scenarios. In Sect. 4.3, we show that some participants applied a specific distribution principle in this mixed supply situation, which we call “net split”.

4.2.3 Marginal effect of accountability

Now, we turn to the marginal effect of accountability (for statistical details, see Tables 7 and 8 in Appendix D). The bottom left panel of Fig. 4 displays the marginal effect of the High Accountability Treatment on the share of logs distributed to A (the Low Accountability Treatment is the benchmark case). Except for cases 1 and 2 in the Need Scenario, all marginal effects are negatively significant. The figure also shows that high accountability had a significantly greater negative impact in cases 4 and 5 than in case 1. Hence, the supply situation in terms of greater inequality among A and B caused a greater accountability effect with respect to the just share of logs distributed to A.

According to H2, we also expect \(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A<0\) in the Need Scenario and \(\Delta \text{ deviation}_A>0\) in the Productivity Scenario. Hence, we display \(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A|\) in the bottom right panel of Fig. 4 to ease visual comparisons. The bottom right panel displays the marginal effect of the High Accountability Treatment by scenario and case. As expected, the marginal effects are negatively significant (except for case 1 of the Need Scenario). There is no difference between the scenarios and there are case differences similar to the share of logs. In summary, the negative effect of high accountability is clearly confirmed (H2).

4.2.4 Control variables

Next, we address the control variables (for statistical details, see Table 4 in Appendix D). Participants with higher equivalent household net incomes were willing to allocate a greater share of logs to Person A. Among the health-related variables, only the smoker dummy exhibits a significant positive coefficient in the regressions on \(\text{ logshare}_A\) (and a negative coefficient in the regressions on \(\text{ deviation}_A\)), which may point to a “solidarity effect” among smokers.

The covariates that capture participants’ support for different distribution principles are significant in all regressions on the share of logs distributed to A. Participants who think that need is an important criterion of distributive justice distributed more logs to A and chose greater deviations from the equal split. Participants who think that equity is an important criterion of justice distributed less to A and, also, chose greater deviations from the equal split. Participants who show stronger support for equality gave more to A and, naturally, tolerated only smaller deviations from the equal split. The positive coefficient of the political-attitude variable indicates that people who place themselves rather on the right side of the political spectrum made less equal distribution choices.

Each participant submitted two accountability judgments—one for the Need Scenario and one for the Productivity Scenario. As can be seen in the bottom row of Table 4 in Appendix E, the accountability judgments do not have a significant impact on average distribution choices (\(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) and \(\text{ deviation}_A^s\)) when the accountability judgment enters the regression model as a differential intercept. Beyond that, it would be interesting to analyze whether the size of the accountability effect (\(\Delta \text{ logshare}_A^s\) and \(-1\times |\Delta \text{ deviation}_A^s|\)) depends on within-subjects differences between the accountability judgments of the two treatments in a given scenario. However, since participants were assigned to either the Low Accountability Treatment or the High Accountability Treatment, this analysis cannot be performed with our between-subjects design.

4.3 Individual distribution choices

In this subsection, we look at participants’ individual distribution choices. First, we group the five choices made by each participant in each scenario into several mutually exclusive categories according to the share of logs distributed to Person A. In the Need Scenario, the choice categories correspond to the following distribution principles: “less” than the equal split (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N<0.5\)), “equal split” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N=0.5\)), “partial compensation” (\(0.5<\text{ logshare}_A^N<n_A^N/n^N\)), A receives her “need share” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N=n_A^N/n^N\)), and A receives “more” than her need share (\(\text{ logshare}_A^N>n_A^N/n^N\)). In the Productivity Scenario, the categories correspond to the following distribution principles: A receives “less” than her productivity share (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P<p_A^P/p^P\)), A receives her “productivity share” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P=p_A^P/p^P\)), “partial compensation” (\(p_A^P/p^P<\text{ logshare}_A^P<0.5\)), “equal split” (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P=0.5\)), and “more” than the equal split (\(\text{ logshare}_A^P>0.5\)). With regard to the exact distribution principles “need share”, “productivity share”, and “equal split”, we tolerate that \(\text{ logshare}_A^s\) deviates 1 percentage point from the respective target value in order to account for typos and small rounding errors. Second, we identify participants who consistently applied the same distribution principle across all cases within a scenario.

Fig. 5
figure 5

Relative frequency of distribution principles by case and scenario. The bars show the relative frequency of five distribution principles by case and scenario. Dark-shaded bars represent the share of “Net split[s]” (A and B receive the logs of wood they need plus/minus half of the oversupply/undersupply) and “Swap[s]” (A receives \((1-p_A^P/p^P)\), B receives \(p_A^P/p^P\)) in the respective category

Figure 5 shows the relative frequency of individual choices that conform with one of the distribution principles by case and scenario. Grey (white) bars refer to the Low (High) Accountability Treatment. In the Need Scenario, equal split, partial compensation, and need share make up 89% of all choices in the Low Accountability Treatment and 92% in the High Accountability Treatment. Interestingly, participants almost never distributed logs of wood in exact accordance with A’s need share (except for case 1 which depicts a situation of severe undersupply). A comparison of participants’ distribution choices between the accountability treatments shows a clear shift towards the equal split when Person A is highly accountable for her disadvantage. The overall share of equal-split choices increases from 44% to 66% (\(\chi ^2_1=49.993\), \(p\le 0.01\)). Increasing inequality from case 1 to case 5 does not intensify the effect of high accountability on the share of equal splits, however.

The dark shaded bars indicate the share of choices in the respective category that are also compatible with a distribution principle that might be called “net split”. Here, A and B receive the absolute number of logs they need plus (minus) half of the oversupply (undersupply). Although the net split is an unusual distribution principle, 8% of all choices in the Low Accountability Treatment and 5% in the High Accountability Treatment are in line with the net-split principle, and it is particularly prevalent in the “mixed supply” case 2 (23% vs. 12%). Though we can conceive distribution principles which are perhaps more sophisticated than the ones displayed in the figure, other principles did not play a significant role in terms of having been chosen more than once or twice in the Need Scenario.

The right panel of Fig. 5 shows a slightly different picture for the Productivity Scenario. Here, 85% of the choices in the Low Accountability Treatment and 94% of the choices in the High Accountability Treatment distribute A’s productivity share to her, compensate her partially, or split the logs equally among A and B. The distribution of the choices to the categories is more balanced, however. There is a clear shift from equal split and partial compensation towards A’s productivity share in the High Accountability Treatment. The overall share of equal-split choices decreases from 35 to 19% (\(\chi ^2_1=33.035\), \(p\le 0.01\)). As in the Need Scenario, there is no significant interaction between the size of the need gap and the marginal effect of high accountability on the share of equal splits. Moreover, there is a striking number of choices (14% vs. 5%) which distribute more than 50% of the logs to A (though she has the same need as B and lower productivity than her). Many of these choices can be explained by the “swap” principle (displayed by the dark-shaded bars in the figure): A receives \((1-p_A^P/p^P)=p_B^P/p^P\)% of the logs and B receives \(p_A^P/p^P=(1-p_B^P/p^P)\)%. Note that, in the Productivity Scenario, the net-split principle coincides with the equal split because A and B have equal need of logs.

Fig. 6
figure 6

Relative frequency of consistent participants by distribution principle and scenario. The bars show the relative frequency of participants who consistently applied the same distribution principle across all cases by distribution principle and scenario. Asterisks denote significance levels of a \(\chi ^2\) test: \(^{*}p\le 0.10\), \(^{**}p\le 0.05\), \(^{***}p\le 0.01\)

Finally, we turn to participants who consistently applied the same distribution principle across all five cases within a scenario. In Fig. 6, we focus on the four most important distribution principles according to their choice frequencies in the scenarios (Need Scenario: equal split, partial compensation, A’s need share, and net split; Productivity Scenario: equal split, partial compensation, A’s productivity share, and swap). The number of participants sticking to one of these distribution principles across all cases is 17.6% (Low Accountability) and 38.5% (High Accountability) in the Need Scenario as well as 24.2% (Low Accountability) and 29.4% (High Accountability) in the Productivity Scenario. Considering six monistic distribution principles, Meyer (2019) found that across several experiments 37% of the subjects always chose in line with the same distribution principle. In five experiments that also involved need as a distribution principle, up to 18% chose the need principle.

In the Need Scenario, 37% of the participants consistently distributed logs to A and B according to the equal-split principle, when A was highly accountable for her disadvantage. This number is significantly greater than the 13% who applied the equal-split principle in the Low Accountability Treatment (\(\chi ^2_1=14.248\), \(p\le 0.01\)). Only a small percentage of participants always compensated A partially. 3% of the participants in the Low Accountability Treatment and none of the participants in the High Accountability Treatment distributed the logs according to A’s need (\(\chi ^2_1=3.648, p=0.056\)). Although Fig. 5 showed that there is a substantial number of choices in line with the net split, none of the participants consistently applied the principle. The right panel of Fig. 6 confirms a more balanced distribution of participants to the categories in the Productivity Scenario. 12% (Low Accountability) and 7% (High Accountability) of the participants consistently applied the equal-split principle, but the treatment difference is insignificant (\(\chi ^2_1=1.301\), \(p=0.254\)). Here, the only significant difference between Low Accountability Treatment and High Accountability Treatment can be observed with regard to the productivity principle (\(\chi ^2_1=6.621\), \(p=0.010\)).

In summary, the analysis of individual choices shows that we have to qualify hypothesis (H1), in particular when we focus on equal-split choices. The large number of equal-split choices indicates that partial compensation is a better prediction of average rather than of individual distribution choices. Our second main hypothesis (H2) is clearly confirmed, as participants’ individual choices became less generous towards Person A when she was highly accountable for her own disadvantage. The previous result suggests, however, that the accountability effect is partly due to a larger share of participants choosing not to compensate Person A at all (extensive margin) rather than to a diminished willingness to compensate her partially (intensive margin) in the High Accountability Treatment.

5 Conclusion

In this paper, we have reported the results of a vignette study with an online sample of the German adult population in which we analyzed the interplay between need, equity, and accountability in third-party distribution decisions. Participants, who were recruited via an online platform, were asked to divide firewood needed for heating in winter between two hypothetical persons who differed in their need for heat and their productivity in terms of their ability to chop wood (and thus their ability to contribute to the total stock of firewood available). The study systematically varied the disadvantaged person’s accountability for her neediness as well as for her lower productivity.

The findings presented in the previous section support our main hypothesis that the disadvantaged Person A’s accountability impacts participants’ willingness to compensate her for her greater need and her lower productivity. Participants distributed significantly fewer logs of wood to Person A when she was held accountable for her disadvantage. Independently of being held accountable or not, the needier person was always compensated with a share of logs that exceeded her contribution, while the person who contributed less was given a share of logs smaller than her need share.

This result is in line with the vast majority of the experimental social choice literature briefly reviewed in Sect. 2 of this paper. For example, Schwettmann (2012), who also used a “heating-in-winter” scenario, found that when the disadvantage of the worse-off individuals was caused by their “careless behaviour” (p. 368), participants chose significantly less often the options (“splits”) that lifted the disadvantaged individual to the poverty line. He therefore concluded that “[a]lthough support for people in need continued to be high, a conflict between the principles of needs and responsibility clearly existed” (p. 372).

Schwettmann (2012) and related studies usually present participants with an exogenously given choice set of distributions that correspond to specific distribution principles such as egalitarianism, Rawls’ maximin principle, or truncated utilitarianism. Like in a beauty contest, the distribution principle that meets with the most approval from participants is declared the winner. In our study, we took a different approach by letting participants freely choose how many logs of wood they wanted to distribute to Persons A and B, who differed in their need and productivity. Eliminating the fixed choice set avoids a possible drawback of the expert approach, namely, researcher’s bias (Ahlert et al. 2012), and leads to behavior more in line with participants’ rather pluralistic opinions about distributive justice (see Schokkaert 1999; Amiel and Cowell 1999; Konow 2003; Traub et al. 2005; Ahlert et al. 2012).

Apart from the main treatment effect of accountability, a regression analysis additionally revealed interesting differences between the two scenarios presented to the participants. In the analysis of the share of logs distributed to A, participants did not differentiate between the source of a person’s disadvantage when compensating her with additional logs in the Low Accountability Treatment, that is, greater need and lower productivity were processed symmetrically. In contrast to this, high accountability gave rise to an asymmetry, with a disadvantaged person’s compensation being significantly smaller when her disadvantage is due to lower productivity instead of greater need. Assuming that equality of need and productivity are perceived as reference points, this result points to a gain-loss domain effect (Tversky and Kahneman 1991, also see Weiß et al. 2017) and an increased perceptual sensitivity (Trueblood 2015) to Person A’s lower contribution (negative domain) than to her greater need (positive domain). In the analysis of the deviation from the equal split, the asymmetry between need and productivity prevailed even in the Low Accountability Treatment and was more pronounced.

With one exception, increasing inequality with respect to need or productivity among the two persons caused greater differences of the disadvantaged person’s just share of logs between the scenarios, and it left the deviation from the equal split unchanged. In other words, the relative weight put to need and equity was almost independent of the supply situation. The case where the disadvantaged person had a deficit of logs and the other person had a surplus made an exception. Here, some subjects applied the “net-split” principle where A and B received the absolute number of logs they needed plus (minus) half of the oversupply (undersupply).

Our sample is representative of the German population with respect to gender, age, and income distribution. We saw that participants with higher equivalent household net incomes were willing to allocate a greater share of logs to Person A. Regression analysis also showed that smokers were willing to distribute more logs to the disadvantaged person, which may point to a “solidarity effect” among smokers. Participants who thought that need was an important criterion of distributive justice distributed more logs to A and chose greater deviations from the equal split; participants who thought that equity was an important criterion of justice distributed less to A and chose greater deviations from the equal split; participants who showed stronger support for equality gave more to A and, naturally, were less tolerant to deviations from the equal split. Moreover, participants who placed themselves rather on the right side of the political spectrum made less equal distribution choices.

This quantitative analysis of individual distribution preferences clearly shows that participants trade off distribution principles like equity (contribution) and need against each other and take into account a person’s accountability for her disadvantage. Hence, the evidence presented here supports earlier studies on accountability and need-based justice (see, for example, Konow 2001; Schwettmann 2009). It also supports the empirical and experimental social choice literature (see Konow and Schwettmann 2016) that posits that participants’ distribution preferences are pluralistic (in terms of consisting of multiple fairness criteria) and context-dependent (the weight that is given to each fairness criterion depends on, for example, institutional factors and personal traits). Finally, our results also underline the (sometimes underestimated) importance of need as a distribution criterion.