Skip to main content
Log in

External representations and scientific understanding

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper provides an inferentialist account of model-based understanding by combining a counterfactual account of explanation and an inferentialist account of representation with a view of modeling as extended cognition. This account makes it understandable how the manipulation of surrogate systems like models can provide genuinely new empirical understanding about the world. Similarly, the account provides an answer to the question how models, that always incorporate assumptions that are literally untrue of the model target, can still provide factive explanations. Finally, the paper shows how the contrastive counterfactual theory of explanation can provide tools for assessing the explanatory power of models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This should not be taken as a stance in the ontology of models discussion. We do not deny that it makes sense to abstract away from the concrete instantiations of these artifacts to their inferential properties and define the identity in these terms (see Kuorikoski and Lehtinen 2009).

  2. Although realist, our view is therefore not ontic in the sense of equating explanations and explanatory factors. Indeed, it would be rather strange to insist that causes and mechanisms would somehow do the explaining by themselves. As has been noted in the literature, little of substance depends on this metaphysical (or more likely grammatical) issue alone (Illari 2013).

  3. The checkerboard model is perhaps also the most used stock example in the philosophy of social science literature, and worries have been raised that using it repeatedly may have created biases in philosophical views. Granted, the checkerboard model might not be representative of economic and sociological models in general. However, as the model has been heralded as an example of a good explanation in social sciences (Sugden 2000; Hedström and Ylikoski 2010), it must embody at least some of the key virtues that social scientists expect their theoretical models to have. Secondly, and more importantly, in the present context it just provides a simple and well-known example to illustrate our points about using external representations in science. Nothing in our argument depends on the choice of this specific example.

  4. Suárez (2003) presents arguments based on the variety of ways of representation, the logical properties of the representation relation, the necessity of accounting for misrepresentation, and nonsufficiency and nonnecessity arguments, to persuasively discredit proposed philosophical accounts of “the” representation relation between scientific models and their targets.

  5. In this sense, the representational properties of a model are still defined in relation (and in this sense “subjective”) to the cognitive agent using the model. However, there is nothing subjective or relative about the correctness, range, and reliability of the inferences carried out by the extended cognitive system.

  6. More qualifications and caveats to the epistemic role of robustness analysis are provided in Kuorikoski et al. (2010) and (2012).

  7. There remains the logical possibility that a model originally not intended to represent a specific system or one built using unsound epistemic principles could reliably facilitate correct counterfactual inferences by purely accident. We do not know of any cases of such accidental representational success,

References

  • Aydinonat, N. E. (2007). Models, conjectures and exploration: An analysis of schelling’s checkerboard model of residential segregation. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14, 429–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexandrova, A., & Northcott, R. (2013). It’s just a feeling: why economic models do not explain. Journal of Economic Methodology, 20, 262–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoría, 21, 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representation and discursive commitment. Cambridge MA and London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruch, E., & Mare, R. (2006). Neighborhood choice and neighborhood change. American Journal of Sociology, 112, 667–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruch, E., & Mare, R. (2009). Preferences and pathways to segregation: Reply to van de Rijt, Siegel, and Macy. American Journal of Sociology, 114, 1181–1198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, W., & Fossett, M. (2008). Understanding the social context of the schelling segregation model. PNAS, 105, 4109–4114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2011). Scientific models and representation. In Steven French & Juha Saatsi (Eds.), The continuum companion to the philosophy of science. Continuum Press.

  • Fossett, M. (2006). Ethnic preferences, social distance dynamics, and residential segregation: Theoretical explorations using simulation analysis. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 30, 185–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2003). A model-theoretic account of representation (or, I don’t know much about art.. but I know it involves isomorphism). Philosophy of Science, 70, 1472–1483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation: Rethinking the questions in social theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71, S742–752.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Ylikoski, P. (2010). Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology, 36, 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesslow, G. (1983). Explaining differences and weighting causes. Theoria, 49(2), 87–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. A. (2006). Tractability assumptions and the musgrave-Mäki typology. Journal of Economic Methodology, 13, 401–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science, 64(Supplement), S325–S336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Integrating the ontic and epistemic. Erkenntnis, 78, 237–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. (2003). Folkscience: coarse interpretations of a complex reality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(8), 368–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 262–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. (2011). Simulation and the sense of understanding. In P. Humphreys & C. Imbert (eds.), Models, simulations, and representations. Routledge: 168–187.

  • Kuorikoski, J., & Lehtinen, A. (2009). Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenntnis, 70, 119–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2010). Economic modeling as robustness analysis. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 541–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A. & Marchionni, C. (2012). Robustness Analysis Disclaimer: Please Read the Manual Before Use! Biology and Philosophy, 27(6), 891–902.

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54, 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. Abington: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1974). The Cement of the universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macy, M., & van de Rijt, A. (2006). Ethnic preferences and residential segregation: Theoretical explorations beyond detroit. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 30, 275–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, J., & Weisberg, M. (2009). The structure of tradeoffs in model building. Synthese, 170(1), 169–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean Idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 16, 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. (2012). The World in the model: How economists work and think. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., Smith, T.,&Weisberg, M. (2012). Segregation that no one seeks. Philosophy of Science, 79, 38–62.

  • Mäki, U. (2009). MISSing the world: Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, 70, 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2012). The explanation paradox. Journal of Economic Methodology, 19, 43–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rozenblit, L., & Keil, F. (2002). The misunderstood limits of folk science: An illusion of explanatory depth. Cognitive Science, 26, 521–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. London & New York, NY: W. W. Norton.

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Harvard: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2003). Scientific representation: Against similarity and isomorphism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17, 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71, 767–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M. (2011). Representing with imaginary models: Formats matter. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 287–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waskan, J. (2006). Models and cognition: Prediction and explanation in everyday life and in science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, K. (2007). Causes that make a difference. Journal of Philosophy, 104(11), 551–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2006). Robustness analysis. Philosophy of Science, 73, 730–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953/1997). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2007). The Idea of Contrastive Explanandum. In J. Persson & P. Ylikoski (Eds.), Rethinking Explanation. Springer.

  • Ylikoski, P. (2009). The illusion of depth of understanding in science. In H. De Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 100–119). Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

  • Ylikoski, P. (2013). Causal and constitutive explanation compared. Erkenntnis, 78, 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2014). Agent-based simulation and sociological understanding. Perspectives on Science, 22, 318–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P., & Aydinonat, E. (2014). Understanding with theoretical models. Journal of Economic Methodology, 21, 19–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P., & Kuorikoski, J. (2010). Dissecting explanatory power. Philosophical Studies, 148, 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper is based on a presentation given in a Workshop on Explanatory Power at Ruhr University Bochum in 2012, and presented in the Philosophy of Science Seminar at the University of Helsinki in 2013. We thank the audiences of these events, as well as the reviewers, for their valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Petri Ylikoski.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kuorikoski, J., Ylikoski, P. External representations and scientific understanding. Synthese 192, 3817–3837 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0591-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0591-2

Keywords

Navigation