Skip to main content
Log in

Logic and Semantics for Imperatives

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I will develop a view about the semantics of imperatives, which I term Modal Noncognitivism, on which imperatives might be said to have truth conditions (dispositionally, anyway), but on which it does not make sense to see them as expressing propositions (hence does not make sense to ascribe to them truth or falsity). This view stands against “Cognitivist” accounts of the semantics of imperatives, on which imperatives are claimed to express propositions, which are then enlisted in explanations of the relevant logico-semantic phenomena. It also stands against the major competitors to Cognitivist accounts—all of which are non-truth-conditional and, as a result, fail to provide satisfying explanations of the fundamental semantic characteristics of imperatives (or so I argue). The view of imperatives I defend here improves on various treatments of imperatives on the market in giving an empirically and theoretically adequate account of their semantics and logic. It yields explanations of a wide range of semantic and logical phenomena about imperatives—explanations that are, I argue, at least as satisfying as the sorts of explanations of semantic and logical phenomena familiar from truth-conditional semantics. But it accomplishes this while defending the notion—which is, I argue, substantially correct—that imperatives could not have propositions, or truth conditions, as their meanings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Exemplary references include [12, 17, 24, 3234, 41, 48, 50, 62, 87].

  2. See, e.g., [57, 75, 8486]. In addition to this, there is a great deal of work on imperatives and similar topics that originates from meta-ethical concerns; a small sampling: [3, 18, 37, 49, 65].

  3. See, e.g., [2, 5, 40, 47, 56, 58, 59, 68, 83].

  4. See, e.g., [6] and subsequent work in the STIT tradition.

  5. For views in this tradition, see [33]; [[88] Section 23]; [22, 50, 76, 92].

  6. On the notion of clause-type and the universality of the imperative, see especially [58].

  7. Since the standard interpretation of \(\wedge \) is commutative, this would seem to commit me to some degree of non-substitutivity-of-logical-equivalents principle for imperative contexts. In reality, I (along with a large contingent of working semanticists) think natural language conjunction is not in general commutative. Thus, if \(\wedge \) is to represent natural language conjunction, \(\wedge \) should not be given a commutative interpretation; if it is not to represent natural language conjunction (but, instead, the familiar Boolean connective), it is not generally correct to represent natural language conjunction using \(\wedge \). In particular, I think that and, when it coordinates distinct descriptions of actions by way of describing a complex action, should be understood as non-commutative: lighting the stunt double on fire and putting him in a protective suit is a much different action from putting the stunt double in a protective suit and lighting him on fire. It is, therefore, misleading to represent an imperative like put the stunt double in a protective suit and light him on fire using an expression in which the imperative operator takes scope over a sentence whose conjuncts can be reversed without affecting that sentence’s interpretation. For a logic that has a smooth time capturing such distinctions, see [70, 71]. (I would like to say more about this, but doing so would mean taking a stand on how to resolve the paradoxes I am describing here—something I would like to avoid.)

  8. There has been, for various reasons, a healthy amount of doubt, some of which I am sympathetic to, about the possibility of (valid) imperative inferences in the literature; see [35, 39, 87]. For general defenses of imperative inference, see [23, 85] (although, I should note that I do not find [85]’s defense persuasive). I should note that my own positive view will suppose that imperatives have a logic in only a relatively weak sense: their semantics should guarantee that certain constellations of attitudes that are constitutively connected to an agent’s acceptance of imperatives display inferential relations to other attitudes that are constitutively connected her acceptance of imperatives. I know of few people who deny that imperatives have a logic in this sense.

  9. Strictly speaking, the data I appeal to here do not support the claim of irreducible embeddability, since (i) the inability to represent a superficially embedded natural language imperative with a sentence of \(\mathcal {L}_{\mathtt {imp}}^+\) does not imply that (ii) there is no more expressive language that successfully represents that imperative, but represents it as embedded. Indeed, the discussion of Section 5.5 implicitly relies in the falsity of (ii). I hope the reader will forgive some imprecision here in the service of exposition. For clearer examples of embedding, see Section 6.2.

  10. For a substantially similar case involving deontic conditionals, see the Miner Paradox of [42]. Given that it will either rain or not, cases like these may feel puzzling in that they can seem, in a certain light, to support challenges to the validity of modus ponens (understood as a general rule sanctioning the inference of an indicative conditional’s consequent if the antecedent is true). But, as [28, 91] emphasize, and as I failed to properly appreciate in my [16], it is possible to formulate the notion of consequence that underwrites valid inference in such a way that insisting on the consistency of (13a)–(13c) is compatible with endorsing a rule of modus ponens.

    A common strategy for debunking this sort of example appeals to the idea that the antecedents of the CIs here are elliptical for sentences containing reference to the knowledge of the addressee. That is to say, (13a), on the salient reading, is actually given the reading if it rains and you know it, take the umbrella; if it is not given this reading, (13a)–(13c) are inconsistent. This is something I just deny. The salient reading of the CIs in question is not one that makes explicit reference to anyone’s epistemic states. Insofar as the salient reading yields a consistent interpretation of (13a)–(13c), assigning (13a)–(13c) a consistent interpretation does not require positing covert reference to anyone’s epistemic states in the antecedents of indicative conditionals. (For more direct arguments against the strategy I am considering here, see [11].)

  11. To forestall a possible response: it might be thought that this claim cannot be right, on the grounds that (i) \(!(\phi \rightarrow \psi )\) and \(!(\neg \phi \vee \psi )\) are “equivalent”, (ii) imperatives of the form \(!(\neg \phi \vee \psi )\) have permission content: disjunctive imperatives permit either disjunct, and this is why the Ross inference is bad. Whether or not this is true for disjunctive imperatives, it is irrelevant here. Clearly (15) does not permit robbing Jones gently.

  12. Two-valued approaches collapse into wide-scope-ism because a ci like (16) is either satisfied or not. Obviously it is not satisfied only if: you turn the A/C on and do not shut the window. So, since the semantics is bivalent, it is satisfied only if: you either do not turn the A/C on or do shut the window. In other words, it has the same satisfaction-conditions as an imperative of the form ! (you turn the A/C on \(\rightarrow \) you shut the window).

  13. This criticism also arguably applies to the Satisfaction-Conditional theory of [23] (although certain complexities Fox’s theory, in particular his treatment of Free Choice Permission, make the argument more complex). I am grateful to an anonymous referee for bringing this reference to my attention.

  14. See [[84], 547] for an argument that the sentences should be regarded as consistent (best as I can tell, the argument is a restatement of the claim that the sentences should be regarded as consistent because it is possible not to violate both). In reply, I am inclined to simply insist on the intuition—there is no argument that could persuade me of the consistency of (16) and (17). They are inconsistent in all of the ways that count (cf. Section 2.1).

  15. Possibly the study of Vranas’ imperative conditional could be motivated by appeal to the claim that the logic of this conditional is a topic of sui generis interest. I am doubtful. Imperatives do have a logic (and, like Vranas [84], I think there are valid imperative inferences). So far as I can tell, however, there are no logical or inferential phenomena about imperatives that are both interesting and proprietary to them. The phenomena Vranas cites (like, for instance, the fact that conditional imperatives can be avoided) tend only to loom large in the context of an approach, like his, that takes satisfaction conditions to be an appealing way to theorize about the semantics and logic of imperatives. Since I do not think this, I do not find the phenomena in question particularly interesting.

  16. Schroeder focuses his objections on Expressivist accounts of normative language, but they extend straightforwardly to both Expressivist and speech act accounts of imperatives.

  17. There are serious costs to relinquishing the canonical way of explaining object-language inconsistency—costs that far outstrip its canonicity. You can, for instance, forget about reductio ad absurdum reasoning in the metalanguage about object-language inconsistency. For the same reason, it seems that the familiar Tarskian technique of exploiting disquotation—e.g., inferring from the fact that ‘\(a\wedge b\)’ holds at X the fact that both ‘a’ and ‘b’ hold at X—as a tool of proof in the metalanguage will be unavailable. If X is a state of mind, disquotation in this sense is simply invalid.

  18. I have argued elsewhere [15] that the sort of semantics developed in this paper, designed in part to skirt the Frege-Geach problem, has a rightful claim to the Expressivist mantle, despite declining to assign speech acts or states of mind as the meanings of sentences. In light of this, here is a more precise statement of my claim here: Expressivism, as ordinarily understood, has a hard time with the Frege-Geach Problem. The issues here are complex, but see my [15] for discussion.

  19. See my [13] for an argument that this sort of wide-scope conjunction is obligatory.

  20. For this reason, the Modal Analysis of imperatives has frequently been seen as a contender in the historical discussion of imperatives. [29] in fact dates the Modal Analysis to Kant’s Groundwork! The Modal Analysis was certainly seen as a contender in the Hare-era debate on imperatives (see [24, 33]), but was generally dismissed on the grounds that imperatives, unlike deontic modals, were “two-valued” with regard to their prejacents. As Geach explained, “In answer to a request for orders, ‘am I to do P?’, only two answers are possible—‘do P’ and ‘do not do P’, which are contradictories. No other order is a direct answer to the question; and to say ‘you may either do P or not’ would not be an answer but a refusal to answer—I was asked for an order and I refuse to give any. But there are three relevant answers to the moral enquiry ‘ought I to do P?’” [[24], 49]. Geach’s observation is questionable—I think ‘it is up to you’ counts as a perfectly good answer to the question ‘what am I to do?’ (unless the interrogator is supposing that only an order will do). Even if it were right, it would show only that some imperative questions—some questions of the form am I to do P?—were distinct in meaning from deontic questions—questions of the form ought I to do P? This is irrelevant to the question of whether the answers to imperative questions are distinct in meaning from the answers to deontic questions.

  21. See also [2, 4, 31, 67].

  22. Exactly this fact is enthusiastically exploited by [67, 68] to support a modal account of imperative semantics.

  23. Something close enough, anyway. See [42, 91] for discussion.

  24. I assume, as is plausible, that (30b) can be represented with an imperative of the form \(!\neg \phi \).

  25. On the importance of accounting for this dimension of imperative meaning, see [59].

  26. Strictly speaking, the tests suggested here for whether a sentence has a representational function are not decisive. There are many philosophers who think that, although things like indicative conditionals, epistemic modals, and moral claims certainly can be called true/false and can be asserted and believed, they nevertheless lack both a representational use and a propositional semantics. Ultimately, I think the proper way to draw the representational/non-representational distinction for a sentence appeals to cognitive phenomena—whether, say, Bayesian probability functions are defined over its semantic value—rather than crude linguistic tests of the sort suggested here.

  27. Not to be confused with the syntactic mood of its main verb. The verbal mood of an interrogative is typically the same as its (declarative) answers. But interrogatives and declaratives are different kinds of clauses.

  28. Portner [58, 59] is a forceful defender of this sort of principle.

  29. This sort of idea is inspired by and closely related to the approach to semantic theorizing advocated by [77, 78], and to a somewhat lesser extent the approach of [89, 90].

  30. Disjunction is defined in terms of negation and conjunction as follows. \(S \models (\phi \vee \psi )\) iff \(S \models \neg (\neg \phi \wedge \neg \psi )\). This holds iff \(\forall w \in S: \{w\} \not \models \neg \phi \wedge \neg \psi \) iff \(\forall w \in S: \{w\} \not \models \neg \phi \) or \(\{w\} \not \models \neg \psi \) iff \(\forall w \in S: \{w\} \models \phi \) or \(\{w\} \models \psi \). This is the correct notion of disjunction for the sake of our cognitively oriented semantics: for a disjunction \((\phi \vee \psi )\) to hold (“be known”) at S, it is required only that, for every world in S, at least one of \(\phi \) or \(\psi \) holds at that world. This is crucially (and correctly) distinct from a notion of disjunction on which \((\phi \vee \psi )\) holds at S iff \(S \models \phi \) or \(S \models \psi \). Knowing \((\phi \vee \psi )\) does not require knowing at least one of \(\phi \) or \(\psi \); one can know a disjunction without knowing which disjunct is true.

  31. There is a familiar worry about treating these properties as full duals, i.e., about turning these ‘only if’ claims into ‘iff’ claims. For one way for a plan to fail to allow \(\neg \phi \) (without thereby requiring \(\phi \)), as well as to fail to require \(\neg \phi \) (without thereby allowing \(\phi \)), is for it to be undecided about \(\phi \) (see [21, 65, 66, 79, 80]).

    In my view, this is basically parallel to the problem of distinguishing strong permission that \(\neg\phi\) (allowing \(\neg\phi\)) from weak permission that \(\neg\phi\) (being undecided about \(\neg\phi\), i.e., failing to require that \(\phi\), while also failing to “actively” permit that \(\neg\phi\)). It is an old problem, and one on whose resolution I would like to avoid taking a stand on here. However, a natural idea here would be to imbue plans with more structure, so that the distinction between strong and weak permission can be represented (cf. Yalcin’s [90] addition of the sort of structure to information states allowing the representation of the attitude of treating something as an issue).

  32. Notice that the \(\lambda \)-notation here is to be read non-standardly (since describing the function using ‘only if’ instead of ‘iff’ means that we fail to pick out a unique such function). A \(\lambda \)-expression of the form \(\lambda z Fz\) will, therefore, refer to a (rather than the) function mapping z to \(Fz\).

    A referee for this journal has helpfully worried that this leaves the resulting semantics quite incomplete—that I have only described a class of functions that an imperative or permission sentences might denote, rather than the particular functions they do denote, and that the cognitive instruction an utterance of an imperative will, on my view, proffer is, thus, quite indeterminate. Quite so, and I agree that this is a shortcoming of the view as stated. But the view as stated is to be understood provisionally: the semantics I would, in the final instance, endorse does not assign families of functions as semantic values; a unique function will be assigned, and the cognitive instruction thus proffered in expressing such a function will be fully determinate. Since stating such a semantics would, of necessity, require taking a stand on the above mentioned paradoxes, I have declined to do so here. Instead, I have opted for stating precise necessary conditions on the function expressed by an imperative. I have done this for the sake of showing that the framework, no matter how it is filled out, will be able to give satisfactory explanations of the phenomena I am interested in here.

  33. For a similar view of the preferential content of imperatives, see [75].

  34. I am here ignoring the complication that truth may ultimately be relative to other things than plans.

  35. For a variety of reasons, I think the Kratzer semantics is inadequate (cf. [28, 91]), but to simplify I will work with it here.

  36. If we’re working in a Categorial or Variable-Free Grammar (see [38]), we could alternatively treat the open argument place as expressing the identity function \(\lambda X_{\langle st,t\rangle }.X\) and generate the correct meaning for the sentence by combining this semantic value with that of its sister node by the composition operation \(\lambda f\lambda g \lambda X.f(g(X))\).

  37. For strong criticisms of Han and Mastop, see, respectively, [60] and [75].

  38. Barker [5] concurs that imperatives express actions, although his broader theory is quite different from Portner’s.

  39. This isn’t to say there is no way to model the update that CIs might “execute” on a context; for such a model see [[14], 178ff]. But adopting such a model would require a rather major reworking of Portner’s theory—one that is not obviously available to him. Why? The idea that the semantic value of an unembedded imperative is an action fails to generate a plausible semantic value for a ci: saying that a ci’s semantic value is typed as an action collapses the theory into wide-scope-ism (since Portner’s theory would have this action be added to the To-Do List), while saying it is typed as something else is, insofar as (i) we expect clauses of the same type to have semantic values of the same type (see [58]) and (ii) conditionals are, per [7], typed as clauses according to the type of their matrix, rather than subordinate, clause (so that CIs are, in fact, typed as imperatives), prima facie undesirable.

    This said, Modal Noncognitivism in no way requires an account of how CIs update the context, contra Portner’s [60] remark that an “issue for [Modal Noncognitivism] is that it does not define a particular update to the context for a given imperative.” Modal Noncognitivism’s theory of imperative meaning is given, not by a theory of how imperatives update the context, instead by the semantic identities proposed in this section.

  40. This is something of which Portner is aware—indeed, enthusiastic. See his [61], which uses this fact in an analysis of permission interpretations of imperatives (e.g., go ahead, have an apple!). I have argued elsewhere that this is not a satisfactory treatment of permission imperatives [[14], 15ff]. Even if it were, this feature of the analysis would be undesirable in light of the argument I am giving here.

  41. For related reasons, we have reason to prefer a strategy which treats states that accept, for example, \(\Phi \wedge \Psi \) without accepting \(\Phi \) as contradiction-licensing (rather than barely possible, but irrational).

  42. What follows is not to be understood as a critique of dynamic semantics generally (except on the strongest understanding of the dynamic semantic program, on which the semantic value of any sentence is a deterministic program or update function). The dynamic semantic approach to, to pick an example at random, donkey anaphora (see, e.g., [30]) plausibly does not suffer from the problems I describe here.

  43. Here is some detail about Starr’s account to fill this point in. A preference state R is defined as a binary relation on a set of alternative propositions (typed as sets of worlds) such that \(\langle a,a' \rangle \in R\) iff a is preferred to \(a'\). For Starr, imperatives update preference states by strengthening their constituent preferences: updating R with \(!\phi \) yields \(R[!\phi ]\) such that (i) \(R \subseteq R[!\phi ]\), (ii) \(R[!\phi ]\) contains a preference for \(\phi \) to \(\neg \phi \), i.e., \(\langle ||\phi ||,||\neg \phi || \rangle \in R[!\phi ]\), and (iii) if \(\langle a,a'\rangle \in R\), \(\langle a[\phi ],a-a[\phi ] \rangle \in R[!\phi ]\) (where \(a[\phi ]=a \cap ||\phi ||\), i.e., is the result of intersecting a with the proposition that \(\phi \)). But component (iii) of the update amounts to a view about how prior preferences are revised on the adoption of a new preference (one that, in all likelihood, would need to be significantly complicated to yield a realistic account of its target). For a sense of the complexities involved here, see [81].

  44. The main remaining difference is that Starr does not suggest an explicitly modal understanding of notions like requirement and permission. Starr does aim to give accounts of phenomena we’ve decided to set to the side, e.g., Ross’ Paradox, but we do not, I think, disagree about the explanation of these phenomena. (For my treatment of Ross’ Paradox, see [[14], 137ff].) For this reason, I would disagree with his claim that “The preference semantics for imperatives developed above enjoys important empirical and conceptual advantages over existing accounts.”

  45. Perhaps such examples feel forced or contrived. For more persuasive examples; see [[14], 133ff]. There are also, it should be mentioned, cases like:

    1. (49)

      Stop or I’ll shoot!

    2. (50)

      Drink another beer and we’ll win the competition! ([64])

    Following roughly [19, 83], I claim that such sentences plausibly function to express assertions of conditionals:

    1. (51)

      \(\approx \)If you don’t stop, I’ll shoot [perhaps conjoined to an imperative: stop!]

    2. (52)

      \(\approx \)If you drink another beer, we’ll win the competition [perhaps joined to an imperative: drink another beer!]

    While there is a mystery about how to generate such readings, I think there is very little pressure for a semantics of imperatives to account for them. Instead, the pressure is to come up with an analysis of the relevant connectives (‘or’ and ‘and’) that allows them to transform imperatives into subordinate clauses functioning to restrict the domain of quantificational modals like ‘will’.

  46. I am grateful to Andrew Alwood for pressing this worry.

  47. One way to appreciate at least the second claim here is by considering Dreier’s [20] Hiyo example. In a language where the sentence ‘Bob is hiyo’ expresses, by stipulation, the speect act of accosting Bob, this sentence, despite being syntactically declarative, is not evaluable for truth.

References

  1. Adams, E.W. (1975). The logic of conditionals: an application of probability to deductive logic. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Aloni, M. (2007). Free choice, modals, and imperatives. Natural Language Semantics, 15, 65–94. doi:10.1007/s11050-007-9010-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Alwood, A. (2010). Imperative clauses and the Frege-Geach problem. Analysis, 70, 105–117. doi:10.1093/analys/anp146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Åqvist, L. (1964). Interpretations of deontic logic. Mind, 73, 246–253. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXIII.290.246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Barker, C. (2012). Imperatives denote actions. In A. A. Guevara, A. Chernilovskaya, R. Nouwen (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 16 (Vol. 1, pp. 57–70).

  6. Belnap, N.D., Jr., & Perloff, M. (1988). Seeing to it that: a canonical form for agentives. Theoria, 54, 175–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Bhatt, R., & Pancheva, R. (2006). Conditionals. In M. Everaert & H. van Riemsdijk (Eds.), The 1576 Syntax companion: volume I. Oxford: Blackwell. http://www-rcf.usc.edu/~pancheva/bhatt-pancheva_syncom.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the word. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Blackburn, S. (1998). Ruling passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cariani, F. (to appear). Ought’ and resolution semantics. Noûs. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00839.x.

  11. Carr, J. (2012). Subjective ought. Ms. http://web.mit.edu/jrcarr/www/pdfs/subjectiveought.pdf.

  12. Castañeda, H.N. (1960). Imperative reasonings. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 21, 21–49. doi:10.2307/2104787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Charlow N. (2010). Restricting and embedding imperatives. In M. Aloni, H. Bastiaanse, T. de Jager, K. Schulz (Eds.), Logic, language, and meaning: selected papers from the 17th Amsterdam Colloquium, ILLC. http://www.springer.com/computer/theoretical+computer+science/book/978-3-642-14286-4.

  14. Charlow, N. (2011). Practical language: its meaning and use. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Michigan. http://www.natecharlow.com/work/dissertation.pdf http://www.natecharlow.com/work/dissertation.pdf.

  15. Charlow, N. (to appear a). The problem with the Frege-Geach problem. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-013-0119-5.

  16. Charlow, N. (to appear b). What we know and what to do. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-011-9974-9.

  17. Chellas, B.F. (1971). Imperatives. Theoria, 37, 114–129. doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.1971.tb00064.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Copp, D. (2001). Realist-expressivism: a neglected option for moral realism. Social Philosophy and Policy, 18(1–43). doi:10.1017/S0265052500002880.

  19. Culicover, P.W., & Jackendoff, R. (1997). Semantic subordination despite syntactic coordination. Linguistic Inquiry, 28, 195–217. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4178974.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Dreier, J. (1996). Expressivist embeddings and minimalist truth. Philosophical Studies, 83, 29–51. doi:10.1007/BF00372434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Dreier, J. (2006). Negation for expressivists: a collection of problems with a suggestion for their solution. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Fox, C. (2012). Imperatives: a judgemental analysis. Studia Logica, 100, 879–905. doi:10.1007/s11225-012-9424-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Geach, P.T. (1958). Imperative and deontic logic. Analysis, 18, 49–56. doi:10.2307/3326785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Geach, P.T. (1965). Assertion. The Philosophical Review, 74, 449–465. http://www.jstor.org/pss/2183123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Gillies, A.S. (2010). Iffiness. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3, 1–42. doi:10.3765/sp.3.4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Green, M.S. (1997). The logic of imperatives. In E. Craig (Ed.), The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (pp. 717–721). New York: Routledge. http://people.virginia.edu/~msg6m/implogic.html.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14, 39–100. doi:10.1007/BF00628304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Han, C.-h. (1998). The structure and interpretation of imperatives: mood and force in universal grammar. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. http://www.sfu.ca/~chunghye/papers/dissertation.pdf.

  32. Hare, R.M. (1949). Imperative sentences. Mind , 58, 21–39. doi:10.1093/mind/LVIII.229.21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Hare, R.M. (1952). The language of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hare, R.M. (1967). Some alleged differences between imperatives and indicatives. Mind, 76, 309–326. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXVI.303.309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Harrison, J. (1991). Deontic logic and imperative logic. In P. Geach (Ed.) Logic and Ethics. Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3352-4n_6.

  36. Isaacs, J., & Rawlins, K. (2008). Conditional questions. Journal of Semantics, 25, 269–319. doi:10.1093/jos/ffn003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1998). A problem for expressivism. Analysis, 58, 239–251. doi:10.1111/1467-8284.00128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Jacobson, P. (1999). Towards a variable-free semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22, 117–185. doi:10.1023/A:1005464228727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Jørgensen, J. (1937). Imperatives and logic. Erkenntnis, 7(8), 288–296.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Kaufmann, S., & Schwager, M. (2009). A unified analysis of conditional imperatives. In E. Cormany, S. Ito, D. Lutz (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 19 (pp. 239–256). Ithaca: CLC Publications. http://www.semanticsarchive.net/Archive/TYzZWYyM/.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Kenny, A.J. (1966). Practical inference. Analysis, 26, 65–75. doi:10.2307/3326284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 115–143. http://johnmacfarlane.net/ifs-and-oughts.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Kratzer, A. (1977). What ‘must’ and ‘can’ must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1, 337–355. doi:10.1007/BF00353453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Kratzer, A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In H. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (Eds.), Words, worlds, and contexts (pp. 38–74). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Kratzer, A. (1991). Modality. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: an international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 639–651). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Kratzer, A. (1991). Conditionals. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: an international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 651–656). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Lascarides, A., & Asher, N. (2004). Imperatives in dialogue. In P. Kuehnlein, H. Rieser, H. Zeevat (Eds.), The semantics and pragmatics of dialogue for the new millennium. Philadelphia: Benjamins. http://homepages.inf.ed.ac.uk/alex/pubs/imps.html.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Lemmon, E.J. (1965). Deontic logic and the logic of imperatives. Logique et Analyse, 8, 39–71.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Lenman, J. (2003). Disciplined syntacticism and moral expressivism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 32–57. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2003.tb00242.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22, 18–67. doi:10.1007/BF00413598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Malden: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review, 85, 297–315. http://www.jstor.org/pss/2184045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Lewis, D. (1979). A problem about permission. In E. Saarinen, R. Hilpinen, I. Niiniluoto, M.B. Hintikka (Eds.), Essays in Honour of Jaakko Hintikka. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 339–359. doi:10.1007/BF00258436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. The Philosophical Review, 88, 513–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Mastop, R. (2005). What can you do? Ph.D. Dissertation, ILLC.

  57. Parsons, J. (2012). Cognitivism about imperatives. Analysis, 72, 49–54. doi:10.1093/analys/anr132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Portner, P. (2004). The semantics of imperatives within a theory of clause types. In K. Watanabe & R. Young (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 14. Ithaca: CLC Publications. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/mJlZGQ4N/.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Portner, P. (2007). Imperatives and modals. Natural Language Semantics, 15, 351–383. doi:10.1007/s11050-007-9022-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Portner, P. (to appear a). Imperatives. In M. Aloni & P. Dekker (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://www.semanticsarchive.net/Archive/Tc3YTc5M/Portner-Imperatives-draftFeb152012.pdf.

  61. Portner, P. (2012). Permission and choice. In G. Grewendorf & T. Zimmermann (Eds.), Discourse and grammar: from sentence types to lexical categories. Studies in generative grammar. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/jI1YjMyY/.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Rescher, N., & Robison, J. (1964). Can one infer commands from commands? Analysis, 24, 176–9. doi:10.1093/analys/24.5.176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Ross, A. (1941). Imperatives and logic. Theoria, 7, 53–71. doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.1941.tb00034.x.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Russell, B. (2007). Imperatives in conditional conjunction. Natural Language Semantics, 15, 131–166. doi:10.1007/s11050-007-9012-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Schroeder, M. (2008). Being for. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  66. Schroeder, M. (2008). How expressivists can and should solve their problems with negation, 42, 573–599. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2008.00693.x.

  67. Schwager, M. (2006). Conditionalized imperatives. In M. Gibson & J. Howell (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 16. Ithaca: CLC Publications. http://user.uni-frankfurt.de/~scheiner/papers/schwagerFEB07.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Schwager, M. (2006). Interpreting imperatives. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Frankfurt.

  69. Searle, J.R. (1962). Meaning and speech acts. The Philosophical Review, 71, 423–432. http://www.jstor.org/pss/2183455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  70. Segerberg, K. (1990). Validity and satisfaction in imperative logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 31, 203–221. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093635415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  71. Segerberg, K. (1992). Getting started: beginnings in the logic of action. Studia Logica, 51, 347–378. doi:10.1007/BF01028968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series 2) (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269–286. doi:10.1007/BF02379021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  74. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Starr, W.B. (2011). A preference semantics for imperatives. Ms.

  76. Stenius, E. (1967). Mood and language game. Synthese, 17, 254–274. doi:10.1007/BF00485030.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  77. Swanson, E. (2006). Interactions with context. Ph.D. Dissertation, MIT. http://www-personal.umich.edu/~ericsw/Swanson,%20Interactions%20with%20Context.pdf.

  78. Swanson, E. (to appear). The application of constraint semantics to the language of subjective uncertainty. Journal of Philosophical Logic.

  79. Unwin, N. (1999). Quasi-realism, negation and the Frege-Geach problem. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 337–352. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Unwin, N. (2001). Norms and negation: a problem for Gibbard’s logic. The Philosophical Quarterly, 51, 60–75. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  81. van Benthem, J., & Liu F. (2007). Dynamic logic of preference upgrade. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 17, 157–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  82. Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 221–261. doi:10.1007/BF00248150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2009). Covert modals? One particular case. Lecture delivered at LSA. Berkeley. http://web.mit.edu/fintel/lsa220-class-6-handout.pdf.

  84. Vranas, P.B.M. (2008). New foundations for imperative logic I: logical connectives, consistency, and quantifiers. Noûs, 42, 529–572. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2008.00684.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  85. Vranas P.B.M. (2010). In defense of imperative inference. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39, 59–71. doi:10.1007/s10992-009-9108-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  86. Vranas, P.B.M. (2011). New foundations for imperative logic II: pure imperative inference. Mind, 120, 369–446. doi:10.1093/mind/fzr032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. Williams, B.A.O. (1963). Imperative inference. Analysis, 23(1), 30–36. doi:10.2307/3326619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  88. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116, 983–1026. doi:10.1093/mind/fzm983.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  90. Yalcin, S. (2011). Nonfactualism about epistemic modality. In B. Weatherson, & A. Egan (Eds.), Epistemic modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Yalcin, S. (2012). A counterexample to modus tollens. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 1001–1024. doi:10.1007/s10992-012-9228-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  92. Zimmerman, D. (1980). Force and sense. Mind, 89, 214–233. http://www.jstor.org/pss/2253170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nate Charlow.

Additional information

This work has benefited greatly from the input of others. I would like to thank Andrew Alwood, Chris Barker, Simon Charlow, Allan Gibbard, Benj Hellie, Paul Portner, Will Starr, Eric Swanson, and Richmond Thomason, as well as audiences at the Association for Symbolic Logic’s 2011 APA Group Session on Dynamic Semantics, Cornell University, ´Ecole Normale Sup´erieure, NYU, University of Toronto, and York University. Thanks also to two anonymous referees for this journal.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Charlow, N. Logic and Semantics for Imperatives. J Philos Logic 43, 617–664 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9284-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9284-4

Keywords

Navigation