Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Case for Welfare Biology

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Animal welfare science and ecology are both generally concerned with the lives of animals, however they differ in their objectives and scope; the former studies the welfare of animals considered ‘domestic’ and under the domain of humans, while the latter studies wild animals with respect to ecological processes. Each of these approaches addresses certain aspects of the lives of animals living in the world though neither, we argue, tells us important information about the welfare of wild animals. This paper argues for the development of a new scientific discipline ‘welfare biology’ to address these issues and more, given the deficiencies of pre-existing life science disciplines to research the subject. Welfare biology is the study of the welfare of all living beings who have a welfare, with a value orientation toward promoting that welfare, regardless of the beings’ situation or relationship to humans and our activities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Different conceptions of welfare may change how animals are considered within a given normative theory – for example, bodily health and integrity might be considered objective goods in animals because of their intrinsic value, or instrumental toward other ends such as the reduction of unnecessary suffering or frustration of preferences (Nussbaum 2006, pp. 394–395). The aim of this paper is not to discriminate between these positions, so we assume that general markers of good and bad welfare are morally important.

  2. Exactly which animals are considered sentient and for what reasons we shall address in a later section.

  3. Cognitive ethology is sometimes mistaken for the pre-existing field of comparative animal psychology given their shared objectives in understanding the contents of animal minds. Major differences between the two relate to their conceptual orientations; cognitive ethologists tend to assume the presence of consciousness in their account of animal cognition, while it is common for comparative psychologists to limit their discussion of mentalistic events. Other differences include experimental variation, research methodology, and limitations that scientists working in these fields might expect to encounter (Vauclair 1997, pp. 36–38, Allen and Bekoff 2007, p. 309).

  4. Associated with the positivist view that the inclusion of non-epistemic values threatens ‘good science’ by increasing inductive risk (the risk of error in accepting or rejecting scientific hypotheses), expressed by Hempel and many others (Douglas2000, p. 561).

  5. e.g., large farm mammals are generally given much greater priority than other animal groups in the discussion of our ethical obligations toward animals (Walker et al. 2014, p. 86). Note, however, that in recent years farmed fish have increasingly been studied with reference to welfare concepts (Lund et al. 2007, Walker et al. 2014, p. 90).

  6. Held in addition to the common intuition that doing harm is ethically worse than allowing harm to occur.

  7. The term ‘balance’ is often used as a metaphor in fields such as population ecology to describe the concept of equilibrium. However, its use has been criticised for being restrictive, value laden, and a general hindrance to understanding relations between natural processes (Sterelny and Griffiths 1999, p. 266, Cuddington 2001).

  8. Examples include; (Mason and Littin 2003; Littin et al., 2004; Bruce Lauber et al. 2007; Riley et al., 2007; Mafbnz 2010; Harrop 2011; Harrington et al., 2013; Ramp et al., 2016; Dubois et al., 2017).

  9. Parallels between these two movements have increased more rapidly in recent years as the environmental impacts of industrial animal agriculture have become more apparent.

  10. Both fields do, of course, overlap in their practice, but it is generally the case that conservation science deals with populations of animals in nature while welfare science deals domestic or human-affiliated animals.

  11. Examples include; (Faria 2016b; Horta2010b, 2010c, 2010d, 2013, 2015, 2018; Johannsen 2016, 2017; Keulartz 2016; McMahan 2015; Moen 2016; Palmer 2019; Tomasik 2015; Torres 2015).

  12. ‘Good’ defined by the values held by participants in the movement.

  13. Examples include; (Clark 1979; Cowen 2003; Everett 2001; Fink 2005; Gould 1982; Hadley 2006; McMahan 2010; Næss 1991; Ng 1995; Sapontzis 1984; Simmons 2009).

  14. See (Lord Tennyson, 1850, Darwin 1860, Salt 1894, Dunham 2008, p. 119, Mill 2008, Murray 2008, p. 2; Schopenhaur 2010, p. 432).

  15. E.g., Peter Singer’s argument from bad consequences (that he later rejects) (Singer, 2015, p. 326, 2016), Tom Regan’s appeal to competence (Regan 2004, pp. 357 & 361), Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka’s ‘flourishing’ argument applied to sovereign wild animal communities (Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011, pp. 165–167), and Rosalind Hursthouse’s appeal to the virtue of respectful love (Hursthouse 2011, p. 133).

  16. In addition to other circumstances, such as disease, which we shall discuss later in this section.

  17. ‘Survive and reproduce’ meaning ‘survive to be able to successfully reproduce in accordance with one’s evolved life history strategy’, as survival does not benefit gene transmission ipso facto.

  18. The word ‘typically’ is used to acknowledge that there is occasionally a substantial inclusive fitness benefit to one’s continued survival post-reproduction such that the selection of traits to enhance their survival might still occur, albeit on a lesser basis.

  19. Unless they arise contingently with other selected traits as sometimes happens.

  20. Analysis of trade-offs between these two contrasting reproductive strategies has been termed r/K selection theory (in which r represents a species’ maximal intrinsic rate of natural growth, and K represents the carrying capacity of their local environment) (MacArthur and Wilson 1967, Pianka 1970, pp. 292–293). This method of life history classification has since received criticism for oversimplifying the study of population dynamics and producing empirically unsound predictions (Stearns 1992, p. 202, Reznick et al., 2002).

  21. This does not imply that all other offspring members will die prematurely, for many will plausibly survive into their adulthood yet fail to successfully reproduce. Even if all offspring die prematurely a population can remain stable so long as this deficit is compensated for by other reproducing individuals within that same population.

  22. The simple state of nonexistence is rarely considered an intrinsic source of disvalue, so we shall focus on the deprivation element of being dead.

  23. Barring the acceptance of particular theories of consciousness, such as panpsychism, in which sentience is an intrinsic property of certain natural phenomena rather than an evolved function.

  24. Researchers attempting to make progress on this issue include; (Barr et al., 2008; Carder 2017; Diggles 2019; Eisemann et al., 1984; Elwood 2011, 2012; Klein and Barron 2016; Lockwood 1987; Puri and Faulkes 2010; Sømme 2005).

  25. For more discussion, see; (Balcombe 2016; Broom 2016; Browman et al. 2019; Brown 2015; Hurtado-Parrado 2010; Sneddon et al. 2018; Woodruff 2018).

  26. For examples, see; (Derbyshire 2016; Hart 2016; Key 2016; Rose 2002, 2007; Rose et al., 2014).

  27. Additionally, it is not clear when sentience first emerged in the tree of life. One view, defended in Feinberg and Mallatt’s neuroevolutionary account of consciousness, posits that sentience evolved progressively throughout the phylogenetic history of vertebrates, but first appeared very early on during the Cambrian explosion (dating back some 560 or 540–520 mya) (Feinberg and Mallatt 2016, pp. 51 & 117, Godfrey-Smith 2017, p. 63).

  28. A widespread example of such a theory supporting mutliple realizability is functionalism, which identifies mental states in terms of the functional roles they play within an organism (Putnam 1975).

  29. E.g., even if we assume a 0.01 likelihood that terrestrial arthropods have a mental welfare, and if they do, that their moral standing is only 0.01 compared to a mammal, the case for considering their suffering might be between 10 and 10,000 times that of all extant mammals (Horta, 2010d, p.6) (Soryl, 2020, p.2). These conservative figures are intended to show the risks of ignoring the possible sentience of certain animals belonging to populous taxonomic groups, such as insects and fish.

  30. E.g., rescuing and rehabilitating injured and sick wild animals, caring for orphaned infants who are unlikely to survive independently, or assisting animals who are victims of natural disaster. Or even small actions that assist wild animals living in urban environments, such as the regular maintenance and cleaning of bird feeders which both helps starving birds and reduces the transmission of avian disease (Jones and James Reynolds 2008, p. 268, Robb et al. 2008, p. 481).

  31. Similar circumstances emerge in nature when there are temporarily abundant resources which cause overpopulation termed ‘Malthusian checks’.

  32. This also involves addressing questions about animal sentience, and possibly even incorporating uncertainty as a variable affecting our conception of welfare, given our earlier discussion about insects and fish.

  33. For examples, see; (Bekoff and Pierce 2016, 2017, p. 25, Donaldson and Kymlicka 2016, Horta 2016, Johannsen 2016, Leadbeater 2016, Marino 2016, Rollin 2019).

  34. For many reasons which due to limited space I shall not go into detail about. See; (Sagoff 1984, MacClellan 2012, Paez 2015, Campbell 2018, Faria and Paez 2019) for more discussion on this issue.

  35. Compassionate conservation is a good example of this, as well as the more recent proposal of conservation welfare. For examples, see; (Beausoleil et al., 2018; Bekoff 2002; Bekoff and Elzanowski 1997; Bekoff and Jamieson 1996; Fraser 2010; Paquet and Darimont 2010; Ramp and Bekoff 2015; Wallach et al., 2015, 2018).

  36. Alternatively, one might acknowledge the problem of WWAS and accept the position that wild animals have a negative welfare yet reject the onus of responsibility placed on humans to aid them. This position has been argued, and (in the authors view) convincingly refuted, in the following texts; (Faria 2015; Palmer 2015).

References

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (2007). Animal minds, cognitive ethology, and ethics. The Journal of Ethics, 11(3), 299–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, R. C., Wood, J. B., & Byrne, R. A. (2002). Octopus senescence: The beginning of the end. Journal of Applied Animal Welfare Science, 5(4), 275–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • EFSA, E.F.S.A., (2005). Aspects of the Biology and Welfare of Animals Used for Experimental and Other Scientific Purposes, Animal and Welfare Scientific Panel.

  • Balcombe, J. (2016). Cognitive evidence of fish sentience. Animal Sentience, 1(3), 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barr, S., Laming, P. R., Dick, J. T. A., & Elwood, R. W. (2008). Nociception or pain in a decapod crustacean? Animal Behaviour, 75(3), 745–751.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beausoleil, N. J., Mellor, D. J., Baker, L., Baker, S. E., Bellio, M., Clarke, A. S., Dale, A., Garlick, S., Jones, B., Harvey, A., Pitcher, B. J., Sherwen, S., Stockin, K. A., & Zito, S. (2018). “Feelings and fitness” not “feelings or fitness”–the raison d’être of conservation welfare, which aligns conservation and animal welfare objectives. Frontiers in Veterinary Science, 5(296), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M. (2002). The importance of ethics in conservation biology: Let’s be ethicists not ostriches. Endangered Species, 19(2), 23–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M., & Elzanowski, A. (1997). Collecting birds: the importance of moral debate. Bird Conservation International, 7(4), 357–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M., & Jamieson, D. (1996). Ethics and the study of carnivores: Doing science while respecting animals. In J. L. Gittleman (Ed.), Carnivore behavior, ecology, and evolution (pp. 15–45). Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M., & Pierce, J. (2016). Animal welfare cannot adequately protect nonhuman animals: The need for a science of animal well-being. Animal Sentience, 1(7), 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M., & Pierce, J. (2017). The animals’ agenda: Freedom, compassion, and coexistence in the human age. Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beldomenico, P. M., Telfer, S., Gebert, S., Lukomski, L., Bennett, M., & Begon, M. (2008). Poor condition and infection: A vicious circle in natural populations. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 275(1644), 1753–1759.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermond, B. (2003). The myth of animal suffering. In R. G. Botzler & S. J. Armstrong (Eds.), The animal ethics reader (pp. 79–85). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleicher, S. S. (2017). The landscape of fear conceptual framework: Definition and review of current applications and misuses. PeerJ, 5(9), e3772.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blosh, M., (2012). The History of Animal Welfare Law and the Future of Animal Rights. Unpublished thesis. The University of Western Ontario, Ontario.

  • Boal, C. W., Mannan, R. W., & Hudelson, K. S. (1998). Trichomoniasis in cooper’s hawks from Arizona. Journal of Wildlife Diseases, 34(3), 590–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, P., & Rodhouse, P. (2005). Cephalopods: Ecology and fisheries. Blackwell Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broom, D. M. (2011). A history of animal welfare science. ActaBiotheoretica, 59(2), 121–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broom, D. M. (2014). Sentience and animal welfare. CABI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broom, D. M. (2016). Fish brains and behaviour indicate capacity for feeling pain. Animal Sentience, 1(3), 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Browman, H. I., Cooke, S. J., Cowx, I. G., Derbyshire, S. W. G., Kasumyan, A., Key, B., Rose, J. D., Schwab, A., Skiftesvik, A. B., Stevens, E. D., Watson, C. A., & Arlinghaus, R. (2019). Welfare of aquatic animals: where things are, where they are going, and what it means for research, aquaculture, recreational angling, and commercial fishing. ICES Journal of Marine Science, 76(1), 82–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, C. (2015). Fish intelligence, sentience and ethics. Animal Cognition, 18(1), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruce Lauber, T., Knuth, B. A., Tantillo, J. A., & Curtis, P. D. (2007). The role of ethical judgments related to wildlife fertility control. Society & Natural Resources, 20(2), 119–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brueland, H., (1995). Highest Lifetime Fecundity. In: University of Florida Book of Insect Records. 41–45.

  • Burton, T., (2015). Review of research on public perceptions of naturalness. Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

  • Campbell, I. J. (2018). Animal welfare and environmental ethics: It’s complicated. Ethics and the Environment, 23(1), 49–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carder, G., (2017). A preliminary investigation into the welfare of lobsters in the UK. Animal Sentience, 2 (16).

  • Clark, S. R. L. (1979). The rights of Wild things. Inquiry, 22(1–4), 171–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowen, T. (2003). Policing nature. Environmental Ethics, 25(2), 169–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuddington, K. (2001). The “balance of nature” metaphor and equilibrium in population ecology. Biology & Philosophy, 16(4), 463–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curio, E. (1976). The ethology of predation. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C., (1860). Letter to Asa Gray [online]. Darwin Correspondence Project. Available from: https://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/letter/DCP-LETT-2814.xml [Accessed 4 Apr 2019].

  • Dawkins, M. S. (2017). Animal welfare with and without consciousness. Journal of Zoology, 301(1), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Franco, J. L. A. (2013). The concept of biodiversity and the history of conservation biology: From wilderness preservation to biodiversity conservation. História (São Paulo), 32(2), 21–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Plater, G. M., Milburn, P. J., & Martin, R. L. (2000). Venom from the platypus, ornithorhynchusanatinus, induces a calcium-dependent current in cultured dorsal root ganglion cells. Journal of Neurophysiology, 85(3), 1340–1345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Degrazia, D. (1999). Animal ethics around the turn of the twenty-first century. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 11(2), 111–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2016). Sentient nonpersons and the disvalue of death. Bioethics, 30(7), 511–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derbyshire, S. W. G. (2016). Fish lack the brains and the psychology for pain. Animal Sentience, 1(3), 18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diggles, B. K. (2019). Review of some scientific issues related to crustacean welfare. ICES Journal of Marine Science, 76(1), 66–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, S. and Kymlicka, W., (2011). Zoopolis: a political theory of animal rights. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Donaldson, S., & Kymlicka, W. (2016). Linking animal ethics and animal welfare science. Animal Sentience, 1(5), 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 559–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Droege, P. and Braithwaite, V.A., (2014). A Framework for Investigating Animal Consciousness. In: G. Lee, J. Illes, and F. Ohl, eds. Ethical Issues in Behavioral Neuroscience. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 79–98.

  • Dubois, S., Fenwick, N., Ryan, E. A., Baker, L., Baker, S. E., Beausoleil, N. J., Carter, S., Cartwright, B., Costa, F., Draper, C., Griffin, J., Grogan, A., Howald, G., Jones, B., Littin, K. E., Lombard, A. T., Mellor, D. J., Ramp, D., Schuppli, C. A., & Fraser, D. (2017). International consensus principles for ethical wildlife control: Principles for ethical wildlife control. Conservation Biology, 31(4), 753–760.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunham, S. A. (2008). The trinity and creation in augustine: An ecological analysis. SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisemann, C. H., Jorgensen, W. K., Merritt, D. J., Rice, M. J., Cribb, B. W., Webb, P. D., & Zalucki, M. P. (1984). Do insects feel pain? — A biological view. Experientia, 40(2), 164–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elwood, R. W. (2011). Pain and suffering in invertebrates? ILAR Journal, 52(2), 175–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elwood, R. (2012). Evidence for pain in decapod crustaceans. Animal Welfare, 21(1), 23–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, J. (2001). Environmental ethics, animal welfarism, and the problem of predation: A bambi lover’s respect for nature. Ethics & the Environment, 6(1), 42–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faria, C., 2015. Disentangling obligations of assistance: A reply to clare palmer’s “against the view that we are usually required to assist wild animals”. Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3 (2), 211–218.

  • Faria, C. (2016a). Animal ethics goes wild: The problem of wild animal suffering and intervention in nature. UniversitatPompeuFabra.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faria, C., (2016). Why we should not postpone awareness of wild animal suffering, 7 (14), 3

  • Faria, C., & Paez, E. (2019). It’s splitsville: Why animal ethics and environmental ethics are incompatible. American Behavioral Scientist, 63(8), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. (2016). The ancient origins of consciousness: How the brain created experience. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, C.K., (2005). The predation argument. Between the Species, 13 (5).

  • Fraser, D. (1999). Animal ethics and animal welfare science: Bridging the two cultures. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 65(3), 171–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, D., (2008). Understanding animal welfare: the science in its cultural context. Oxford; Ames, Iowa: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Fraser, D. (2010). Toward a synthesis of conservation and animal welfare science. Animal Welfare, 2(19), 121–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, A., Staaterman, E., & Dreyer, N. (2015). Kelp gulls prey on the eyes of juvenile Cape fur seals in Namibia. African Journal of Marine Science, 37(3), 411–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Other minds: the octopus, the sea, and the deep origins of consciousness. Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2017). Animal evolution and the origins of experience. In D. L. Smith (Ed.), How biology shapes philosophy (pp. 51–71). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1982). Nonmoral nature. Natural History, 91, 19–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, N. G. (2004). Physiology and behaviour of animal suffering. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadley, J. (2006). The duty to aid nonhuman animals in dire need. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23(4), 445–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hapgood, F. (1979). Why males exist, an inquiry into the evolution of sex. Morrow.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrington, L. A., Moehrenschlager, A., Gelling, M., Atkinson, R. P. D., Hughes, J., & Macdonald, D. W. (2013). Conflicting and complementary ethics of animal welfare considerations in reintroductions: Welfare in reintroductions. Conservation Biology, 27(3), 486–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrop, S. (2011). Climate change, conservation and the place for wild animal welfare in international law. Journal of Environmental Law, 23(3), 441–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, P. J. B. (2016). Fighting forms of expression. Animal Sentience, 1(3), 9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinckley, S. (1987). The reproductive biology of walleye pollock, theragrachalcogramma, in the bering sea, with reference to spawing stock. Structure, 85(3), 481–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O. (2010a). What is speciesism? Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 23(3), 243–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O. (2010b). Debunking the idyllic view of natural processes: Population dynamics and suffering in the wild. RevistaIberoamericana de EstudiosUtilitaristas, 17(1), 73–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O. (2010c). The ethics of the ecology of fear against the nonspeciesist paradigm: A shift in the aims of intervention in nature. Between the Species: An Online Journal for the Study of Philosophy and Animals, 13(10), 163–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O., (2010). Disvalue in nature and intervention. Pensata Animal, 34.

  • Horta, O. (2013). Zoopolis, Intervention, and the State of Nature. Law, Ethics, and Philosophy, 1, 113–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O., (2015). The problem of evil in nature: Evolutionary bases of the prevalence of disvalue. Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3 (2), 17–32.

  • Horta, O. (2016). Changing attitudes towards animals in the wild and speciesism. Animal Sentience, 3(7), 15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O. (2018). Concern for wild animal suffering and environmental ethics: What are the limits of the disagreement? Les ateliers de l’éthique, 13(1), 85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R., (2011). Virtue Ethics and the Treatment of Animals. In: T.L. Beauchamp and R.G. Frey, eds. The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford University Press, 119–143.

  • Hurtado-Parrado, C. (2010). Neuronal mechanisms of learning in teleost fish. UniversitasPsychologica, 9(3), 663–678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D. (1998). Animal liberation is an environmental ethic. Environmental Values, 7(1), 41–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D., & Bekoff, M. (1990). Cognitive ethology and applied philosophy: The significance of an evolutionary biology of mind. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 5(5), 156–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeyaseelan, M. J. P. (1998). Manual of fish eggs and larvae from Asian mangrove waters. United Nations Educational.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, K. (2016). Animal welfare at home and in the wild. Animal Sentience, 1(7), 10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, K. (2017). Animal rights and the problem of r-strategists. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(2), 333–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, D. N., & James Reynolds, S. (2008). Feeding birds in our towns and cities: A global research opportunity. Journal of Avian Biology, 39(3), 265–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keulartz, J. (2016). Should the lion eat straw like the Ox? Animal ethics and the predation problem. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 29(5), 813–834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Key, B., 2016. Why fish do not feel pain. Animal Sentience, 1 (3).

  • Klein, C. and Barron, A.B., (2016). Insects have the capacity for subjective experience. Animal Sentience, 1 (9).

  • Koch, L. K., & Meunier, J. (2014). Mother and offspring fitness in an insect with maternal care: Phenotypic trade-offs between egg number, egg mass and egg care. BMC Evolutionary Biology, 14(1), 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohl, M. T., Stahler, D. R., Metz, M. C., Forester, J. D., Kauffman, M. J., Varley, N., White, P. J., Smith, D. W., & MacNulty, D. R. (2018). Diel predator activity drives a dynamic landscape of fear. Ecological Monographs, 88(4), 638–652.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laal, M. (2009). A brief history of enviroethics and its challenges. Journal of Medical Ethics and History of Medicine, 2(10), 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laundré, J.W., Hernández, L., and Altendorf, K.B., (2001). Wolves, elk, and bison: reestablishing the ‘landscape of fear’ in Yellowstone National Park, U.S.A. Canadian Journal of Zoology, 79 (8), 1401–1409.

  • Leadbeater, S. (2016). Animal suffering calls for more than a bigger cage. Animal Sentience, 1(7), 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Littin, K., Mellor, D., Warburton, B., & Eason, C. (2004). Animal welfare and ethical issues relevant to the humane control of vertebrate pests. New Zealand Veterinary Journal, 52(1), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, J. A. (1987). The moral standing of insects and the ethics of extinction. The Florida Entomologist, 70(1), 70–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopez-Luna, J., Al-Jubouri, Q., Al-Nuaimy, W., & Sneddon, L. U. (2017). Impact of analgesic drugs on the behavioural responses of larval zebrafish to potentially noxious temperatures. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 188, 97–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopez-Luna, J., Al-Jubouri, Q., Al-Nuaimy, W., & Sneddon, L. U. (2017). Reduction in activity by noxious chemical stimulation is ameliorated by immersion in analgesic drugs in zebrafish. Journal of Experimental Biology, 220(8), 1451–1458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopez-Luna, J., Al-Jubouri, Q., Al-Nuaimy, W., & Sneddon, L. U. (2017). Impact of stress, fear and anxiety on the nociceptive responses of larval zebrafish. PLoS ONE, 12(8), e0181010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopez-Luna, J., Canty, M. N., Al-Jubouri, Q., Al-Nuaimy, W., & Sneddon, L. U. (2017). Behavioural responses of fish larvae modulated by analgesic drugs after a stress exposure. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 195, 115–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lord Tennyson, A., (1850) In Memoriam A. H. H. OBIIT MDCCCXXXIII: 55 [online]. Poetry Foundation. Available from: https://www.poetryfoundation.org/poems/45342/in-memoriam-a-h-h-obiit-mdcccxxxiii-55 [Accessed 14 May 2019].

  • Lund, V., Mejdell, C., Röcklinsberg, H., Anthony, R., & Håstein, T. (2007). Expanding the moral circle: Farmed fish as objects of moral concern. Diseases of Aquatic Organisms, 75, 109–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur, R. H., & Wilson, E. O. (1967). The theory of island biogeography. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacClellan, J.P., (2012). Minding Nature: A Defense of a Sentiocentric Approach to Environmental Ethics. Unpublished thesis. University of Tennessee.

  • MAFBNZ, (2010). How humane are our pest control tools? Lincoln: MAFBNZ Operational Research, MAF Biosecurity New Zealand Technical Paper No: 2011/01 No. 09–11326.

  • Marino, L. (2016). Why animal welfarism continues to fail. Animal Sentience, 1(7), 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, G., & Littin, K. E. (2003). The humaneness of rodent pest control. Animal Welfare, 12, 1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, S. J., Rowe, L., & Fortin, M. J. (2011). The deadly effects of “nonlethal” predators. Ecology, 92(11), 2043–2048.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGowan, C. (1997). The raptor and the lamb: Predators and prey in the living world. Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J., 2010. The Meat Eaters [online]. New York Times, Sep 19. Available from: https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/09/19/the-meat-eaters/ [Accessed 23 Sep 2019].

  • McMahan, J. (2015). The Moral Problem of Predation. In A. Chignell, T. Cuneo, & M. C. Halteman (Eds.), Philosophy comes to dinner: Arguments about the ethics of eating (pp. 268–294). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meine, C., Soule, M., & Noss, R. F. (2006). ‘A mission-driven discipline’: The growth of conservation biology. Conservation Biology, 20(3), 631–651.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. J., Patterson-Kane, E., & Stafford, K. J. (2009). The Sciences of animal welfare. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S., 2008. On Nature [online]. Early Modern Texts. Available from: https://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/mill1873b.pdf [Accessed 23 Sep 2019].

  • Moen, O. M. (2016). The ethics of wild animal suffering. Etikkipraksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics, 10(1), 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M.J., (2008). Nature red in tooth and claw: Theism and the problem of animal suffering. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Næss, A. (1991). Should we try to relieve clear cases of suffering in nature? Pan Ecology, 6(1), 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1970). Death. Noûs, 4(1), 73–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naish, D., 2010. Babirusas can get impaled by their own teeth: that most sought-after of objects does exist! [online]. ScienceBlogs. Available from: https://scienceblogs.com/tetrapodzoology/2010/03/08/babirusa-impales-own-head [Accessed 15 Aug 2019].

  • Ng, Y.-K. (1995). Towards welfare biology: Evolutionary economics of animal consciousness and suffering. Biology & Philosophy, 10(3), 255–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C., (2006). Frontiers of justice: disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge, Mass: The Belknap Press: Harvard University Press.

  • Nygård, B.C., (1995). Lowest lifetime fecundity. In: University of Florida Book of Insect Records. 39–40.

  • Paez, E., (2015). Refusing help and inflicting harm: A critique of the environmentalist view. Relations: Beyond anthropocentrism, 3 (2), 165–178.

  • Palmer, C., (2015). Against the view that we are normally required to assist wild animals. Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3(2), 203–210.

  • Palmer, C. (2019). Assisting wild animals vulnerable to climate change: Why ethical strategies diverge. Journal of Applied Philosophy, online first publication. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panafieu, J.-B., & Gries, P. (2007). Evolution. Seven Stories Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paquet, P. C., & Darimont, C. T. (2010). Wildlife conservation and animal welfare: Two sides of the same coin? Animal Welfare, 19, 177–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, D., (2015). A welfare state for elephants? A case study of compassionate stewardship. Relations: Beyond anthropocentrism, 3(2), 153–164.

  • Pianka, E. R. (1970). On r- and K-selection. The American Naturalist, 104(940), 592–597.

    Google Scholar 

  • Puri, S., & Faulkes, Z. (2010). Do decapod crustaceans have nociceptors for extreme pH? PLoS ONE, 5(4), e10244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The nature of mental states. Philosophical papers: Mind, language, and reality (pp. 429–440). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramp, D., & Bekoff, M. (2015). Compassion as a practical and evolved ethic for conservation. BioScience, 65(3), 323–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramp, D., Wilson, V., & Croft, D. (2016). Contradiction and complacency shape attitudes towards the toll of roads on wildlife. Animals, 6(40), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rand, A. L. (1954). On the spurs of birds’ wings. The Wilson Bulletin, 66(2), 127–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. (2004). The case for animal rights. Updated (2004th ed.). California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reznick, D., Bryant, M. J., & Bashey, F. (2002). r- and K-selection revisited: The role of population regulation in life-history evolution. Ecology, 83(6), 1509–1520.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riley, S. P. D., Bromley, C., Poppenga, R. H., Uzal, F. A., Whited, L., & Sauvajot, R. M. (2007). Anticoagulant exposure and notoedric mange in bobcats and mountain lions in Urban Southern California. Journal of Wildlife Management, 71(6), 1874–1884.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robb, G. N., McDonald, R. A., Chamberlain, D. E., & Bearhop, S. (2008). Food for thought: Supplementary feeding as a driver of ecological change in avian populations. Frontiers in Ecology and the Environment, 6(9), 476–484.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollin, B. E. (2019). Progress and absurdity in animal ethics. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 32, 391–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H., III. (1998). Challenges in environmental ethics. In M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren, & J. Clark (Eds.), Environmental philosophy: From animal rights to radical ecology (pp. 124–144). Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, J. D. (2002). The neurobehavioral nature of fishes and the question of awareness and Pain. Reviews in Fisheries Science, 10(1), 1–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, J. (2007). Anthropomorphism and ‘mental welfare’ of fishes. Diseases of Aquatic Organisms, 75, 139–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, J. D., Arlinghaus, R., Cooke, S. J., Diggles, B. K., Sawynok, W., Stevens, E. D., & Wynne, C. D. L. (2014). Can fish really feel pain? Fish and Fisheries, 15(1), 97–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (1984). Animal liberation and environmental ethics: bad marriage quick divorce. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 22(2), 297–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salt, H. S. (1894). Animals’ rights: Considered in relation to social progress. Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapontzis, S. F. (1984). Predation. Ethics and Animals, 5(2), 27–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhaur, A. (2010). On the sufferings of the world. In D. Benatar (Ed.), Life, death, and meaning: Key philosophical readings on the big questions (pp. 431–440). Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sillar, K. T., Picton, L. D., & Heitler, W. J. (2016). The neuroethology of predation and escape. West Sussex: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. (2009). Animals, predators, the right to life, and the duty to save lives. Ethics & the Environment, 14(1), 15–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, V. R. (2002). Wild animals as reservoirs of infectious diseases in the UK. The Veterinary Journal, 163(2), 128–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P., (2015). Animal Liberation: The Definitive Classic of the Animal Movement. 40th Anniversary Edition. Open Road Media.

  • Singer, P., (2016). The Suffering of Wild Animals: Should we do anything about it, and if so, what? [online]. High Meadows Environmental Institute. Available from: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1VYYHLH990A [Accessed 4 Apr 2019].

  • Sneddon, L. U. (2015). Pain in aquatic animals. Journal of Experimental Biology, 218(7), 967–976.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneddon, L.U., Lopez-Luna, J., Wolfenden, D.C.C., Leach, M.C., Valentim, A.M., Steenbergen, P.J., Bardine, N., Currie, A.D., Broom, D.M., and Brown, C., (2018). Fish sentience denial: Muddying the waters. Animal Sentience, 21 (1).

  • Solbrig, O. T., & Solbrig, D. J. (1979). Introduction to population biology & evolution. Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sømme, L.S., (2005). Sentience and Pain in Invertebrates. Dept. of Animal and Aquacultural Sciences: Norwegian University of Life Sciences, Report to Norwegian Scientific Committee for Food Safety.

  • Soule, M. E. (1985). What is conservation biology? BioScience, 35(11), 727–734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stearns, S. C. (1992). The evolution of life histories. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasik B (2015) The Importance of Wild-Animal Suffering. Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3(2), 133–152.

  • Tomasik, B., 2018. How Many Wild Animals Are There? [online]. Reducing Suffering. Available from: https://reducing-suffering.org/how-many-wild-animals-are-there/ [Accessed 31 Jan 2019].

  • Torres, M., (2015) The Case for Intervention in Nature on Behalf of Animals: A Critical Review of the Main Arguments against Intervention. Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3 (2), 33–49.

  • Vauclair, J. (1997). Mental states in animals: Cognitive ethology. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1(1), 35–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, M., Díez-León, M., & Mason, G. (2014). Animal Welfare Science: Recent publication trends and future research priorities. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 27(1), 80–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallach, A. D., Bekoff, M., Batavia, C., Nelson, M. P., & Ramp, D. (2018). Summoning compassion to address the challenges of conservation: Compassionate conservation. Conservation Biology, 32(6), 1255–1265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallach, A. D., Bekoff, M., Nelson, M. P., & Ramp, D. (2015). Promoting predators and compassionate conservation: Predators and compassionate conservation. Conservation Biology, 29(5), 1481–1484.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodruff, M. L. (2018). Pain in fish: Evidence from peripheral nociceptors to pallial processing. Animal Sentience, 3(21), 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, C., & Cuddington, K. (2007). Ambiguous, circular and polysemous: Students’ definitions of the “balance of nature” metaphor. Public Understanding of Science, 16(4), 393–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zoladz, P.R., (2008). An ethologically relevant animal model of post-traumatic stress disorder: Physiological, pharmacological and behavioral sequelae in rats exposed to predator stress and social instability. Unpublished thesis. University of South Florida.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are very grateful for the constructive and insightful comments on an earlier draft of this paper from two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mike R. King.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Soryl, A.A., Moore, A.J., Seddon, P.J. et al. The Case for Welfare Biology. J Agric Environ Ethics 34, 7 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-021-09855-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-021-09855-2

Keywords

Navigation