Skip to main content
Log in

The Natural Link Between Virtue Ethics and Political Virtue: The Morality of the Market

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Against the idea that market economy is something greedy and immoral, we will set out the idea that market economy based on firms has a very positive moral content: the possibility of excellence of human action. Firms based on people acting together, sharing the culture of the organization, toward virtue-based ethics, create and distribute most of the economy’s wealth, innovate, trade and raise living standards. We will present a criterion which states that social coordination improves if the process of creation of individual possibilities of action, which is carried out in the social institutions—in our case, the firm—is extended. There is a retention of possibilities that is formed in the institutions and transmitted culturally. In that moment entrepreneurship emerges, the creative tension that expands, maintains, or diminishes the possibilities of action. Hence, the firm is the institution that carries out a very important practice: fostering new possibilities of individual action. In this paper, we will adopt the point of the view of the acting person. The reality we observe is personal action within its cultural and institutional dimensions. A theory of personal action in societal institutions bridges the way from virtue-based ethics toward ethics of institutions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As the Spanish philosopher Zubiri points out: “This with (with things, with other men, with-me myself) is not something extra, an extrinsic relation, added to man in the exercise of his life. This would be absolutely chimerical. It is something much more radical. The with is a formal structural stage of life itself and therefore of human substantiveness in its vital dynamism.” (2003, p. 255).

  2. Statman (1997) speculating about the relationship between virtue ethics and political philosophy suggests that communitarianism might turn out to be the political aspect of virtue ethics (Statman 1997, p. 18). In this article, I defend another possibility. For me, the political aspect of virtue ethics is liberalism. But liberalism not based on mainstream economics homo economicus. My account of liberalism is based on human action and institutional processes following Mises and the Austrian School of economics. On the differences within liberalism between the so-called scientific reductionism of the liberals of Chicago School (M. Friedman, G. Becker), and the humanistic approach of the Austrian School (Mises, Hayek); see Aranzadi (2006).

  3. The ideas presented in this section have been developed in depth in Aranzadi (2006, 2011).

  4. An anonymous referee has pointed out this possible outcome of the market process. I thank his or her comment on this point.

  5. Obviously, the opposite outcome is possible. An anonymous referee rightly says that there are many situations in which the games are zero sum. There are winners and losers. And he or she argues that it is the case “when self-interest overrides social interest”. As I have argued in note 2, I consider that we need theories of the market not based in the homo economicus. The idea perfectly expressed by Friedman (1970) dictum “the firm’s social responsibility is to maximize profits” has terrible consequences when it has been applied to real firms (Ghoshal 2005). In this article, I defend another approach in which the social role of the firm presented in “The Social Role of the Firm” section is to unify the individual interest (“liberty from”) with the social interest (“liberty for”). So I agree with Freeman et al. (2007) when they defend the idea that firms and theirs stakeholders can generate positive sum situations.

  6. On the relationship between entrepreneurship and ethics, see among others (Brenkert 2009; Etzioni 1987; Hannafey 2003; Harmeling et al. 2009; Machan 1999).

  7. It is impossible here to deal with the capabilities approach developed by Nussbaum and Sen (1993). The first point should mark the differences—remarkably I would say—between Sen and Nussbaum approaches. For instance, Sen (2009) presents what he considers to be distinctive of his approach, and Nussbaum (2011) does the same. For a general and critical assessment of both approaches see Richardson (2000, 2007).

  8. As Ratzinger wrote: “A scientific approach that believes itself capable of managing without an ethos misunderstands the reality of man. Therefore it is not scientific. Today we need a maximum of specialized economic understanding but also a maximum of ethos” (1986, p. 204).

  9. As has been noticed Grassl and Habitsh (2011) the Encyclical-Letter Caritas in Veritate emphasizes the same two basic ideas. First, business activity must be understood as personal action, and second management should foster the creativity of employees.

  10. And the development of the humanistic management approach (Argandoña 2007, 2010; Melé 2003, 2009; Spitzeck et al. 2009; Hartman 2011) among others.

  11. Koslowski (1996, p. 53) states emphatically that the market allows not only freedom of consumption but also of action and production.

  12. This efficiency criterion requires the two formulations in order to correspond to the two views of human freedom. Our first formulation refers to the conception of freedom as “freedom from.” In this view, the person is free from institutions to do what he or she likes. It represents the freedom of indifference. One may do this or that. In this view a person who chooses to be a thief is as free as one who chooses to undertake a great enterprise. This first view presents the freedom of indifference. To distinguish between such behaviors, I have introduced the second view corresponding to the concept of freedom as “freedom for.” This view presents the person as a generator of positive actions. It presents human’s freedom in the search for excellence in action. See Pinckaers (1985).

  13. Hartman (2011) makes a pertinent defense of profits from an Aristotelian point of view.

  14. The same idea was masterfully expressed by Professor Marías in the following words: “My life is not a thing, but rather a doing, a reality projected into the future, that is argumentative and dramatic, and that is not exactly being but happening” (1996, p. 126). More bluntly, Drucker says: “the best way to predict the future is to create it” (1998, p. 197).

References

  • Agle, B., Donaldson, T., Freeman, E., Jensen, M., Mitchell, R., & Wood, D. (2008). Dialogue: Towards superior stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(2), 153–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (1995). The morality of happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aranzadi. (2006). Liberalism against Liberalism. London: Routledge.

  • Aranzadi. (2011). The possibilities of the acting person within an institutional framework: goods, norms and virtues. Journal of Business Ethics, 99(1), 87–100.

  • Argandoña, A. (2007). Integrating ethics into action theory and organizational theory. Journal of Business Ethics, 78, 435–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Argandoña, A. (2010). Las Virtudes en una Teoría de la Acción, DI-880, IESE Business School.

  • Aristotle. (1969). Nicomachean Ethics (D. Ross, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Baumol, W. (1968). Entrepreneurship in economic theory. American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 58, 64–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W. (1993). Formal entrepreneurship theory in economics, existence and bounds. Journal of Business Venturing, 8, 197–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W. (1996). Entrepreneurship, management, and the structure of payoffs. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenkert, G. (2009). Innovation rule breaking and the ethics of entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Venturing, 29, 448–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casson, M. (1982). The entrepreneur. Totowa, NJ: Barnes & Noble Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R., & Slote, M. (Eds.). (1997). Virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1996). Creativity, flow and the psychology of discovery and invention. New York: Harper Collins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dew, N., Ramakrishna Velamuri, S., & Venkataranam, S. (2004). Dispersed knowledge and an entrepreneurial theory of the firm. Journal of Business Venturing, 19, 659–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobson, J. (2009). Alasdair Macintyre’s Aristotelian business ethics: A critique. Journal of Business Ethics, 86, 43–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drucker, P. (1998). El gran poder de las pequeñas ideas. Buenos Aires: Editorial Sudamericana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, A. (1987). Entrepreneurship, adaptation and legitimation. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 8, 175–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fort, T. (2007). Business, integrity, and peace. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, E. (2000). Business ethics at the millennium. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10(1), 169–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E., Harrison, J., & Wicks, A. (2007). Managing for stakeholders: Survival, reputation, and success. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1970, September 13), the social responsibility of business is to increase its profits, New York Times Magazine.

  • Ghoshal, S. (2005). Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 4(1), 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S., & Barlett, C. A. (1997). The individualized corporation: A fundamentally new approach to management. New York: HarperCollins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S., Bartlett, C., & Moran, P. (1999). A new manifesto for management. Sloan Management Review, 4(39), 9–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grassl, W., & Habisch, A. (2011). Ethics and economics: Towards a new humanistic synthesis for business. Journal of Business Ethics, 99, 37–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannafey, F. (2003). Entrepreneurship and ethics: A literature review. Journal of Business Ethics, 46(2), 99–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harmeling, S., Sarasvathy, S., & Freeman, R. (2009). Related debates in ethics and entrepreneurship, values, opportunities, and contingency. Journal of Business Ethics, 84, 341–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. (2011). Virtue, profit, and the separation thesis: An Aristotelian view. Journal of Business Ethics, 99, 5–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, I. (1973). Competition and entrepreneurship. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, I. (1979). Perception, opportunity and profit. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, I. (2000). The driving force of the market. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. (1921). Risk, uncertainty and profit. New York: Augustus Kelley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslowski, P. (1996). Ethics of capitalism and critique of sociobiology. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, C. (1987). Patterns of moral complexity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leibestein, H. (1968). Entrepreneurship and development. American Economic Review, 58, 72–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louden, R. (1984). On some vices of virtue ethics. American Philosophical Quarterly, 21, 227–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machan, T. (1999). Entrepreneurship and ethics. International Journal of Social Economics, 26(5), 596–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1985). After Virtue (2nd ed.). Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Marías, J. (1996). Persona. Madrid: Alianza Editorial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2003). The challenge of humanistic management. Journal of Business Ethics, 44, 77–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2009). Integrating personalism into virtue-based business ethics: The personalist and the common good principles. Journal of Business Ethics, 88, 227–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2002). On the implications of the practice-institution distinction: Macintyre and the application of modern virtue ethics to business. Business Ethics Quarterly, 12(1), 19–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2005a). Humanizing business: A modern virtue ethics approach. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(2), 237–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2005b). Corporate character: Modern virtue ethics and the virtuous corporation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(4), 659–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2008). Re-imagining the morality of management: A modern virtue ethics approach. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(4), 483–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, P., & Ghoshal, S. (1999). Markets, firms and the process of economic development. Academy of Management Review, 24(3), 390–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, R., & Winter, S. (1982). An evolutionary theory of economic change. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D. (1991). Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(3), 97–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M., & Sen, A. (1993). The Quality of Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinckaers, S. (1985). Le sources de la morale chrétienne. Friburgo: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratzinger, J. (1986). Church and economy: Responsibility for the future of the world economy. Communio, 13, 199–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhonheimer, M. (1992). Perché una philosophia politica. Elementi storici per una risposta. Acta Philosophica, 1(2), 232–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhonheimer, M. (2011). The perspective of morality. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, H. (2000). Some limitations of Nussbaum’s capabilities. Quinnipiac Law Review, 9, 309–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, H. (2007). The social background of capabilities for freedoms. Journal of Human Development, 3, 388–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneewind, J. (1990). The misfortunes of virtue. Ethics, 100, 42–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, J. A. (1934). Capitalism, socialism and democracy. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, J. A. (1947). The theory of economic development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2002). Rationality and freedom. Harvard: Harvard Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shane, S. (2000). Prior knowledge and the discovery of entrepreneurial opportunities. Organizational Science, 11(4), 448–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shane, S., & Venkataraman, S. (2000). The promise of entrepreneurship as a field of research. Academy of Management Review, 25(1), 217–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1992). Ethics and excellence: Cooperation and integrity in business. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (2004). Aristotle, ethics and business organizations. Organizations Studies, 25(6), 1021–1043.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spitzeck, H., Pirson, M., Amann, W., Khan, S., & von Kimakovitz, E. (Eds.). (2009). Humanism in business. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Statman, D. (1997). Introduction to virtue ethics. In D. Statman (Ed.), Virtue ethics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Venkataraman, S. (1997). The distinctive domain of entrepreneurship research. Advances in Entrepreneurship, Firm Emergence and Growth, 3, 119–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hayek, F. A. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. Econamica new series, 4, 33–50. (Reprinted in von Hayek, F. A. (1976). Individualism and Economic Order. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • von Hayek, F. A. (1989, December). The pretence of knowledge (Nobel lecture). American Economic Review, 79, 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. (1996). In B. B. Greaves (Ed.), Human action: A treatise on economics (4th ed. revised). New York: Foundation for Economic Education.

  • Wojtyla, K. (1979). The person: Subject and community. Review of Metaphysics, 33(2), 273–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zubiri, X. (2003). Dynamic structure of reality (N. R. Orringer, Trans.). Champaign: University of Illinois Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Javier Aranzadi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aranzadi, J. The Natural Link Between Virtue Ethics and Political Virtue: The Morality of the Market. J Bus Ethics 118, 487–496 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-012-1602-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-012-1602-1

Keywords

Navigation