1 Introduction

The past 30 years have seen a vast evolution in the world of sport. Significant investment, both public and private, has caused the industry to flourish, and there is increasingly more at stake for all those involved: athletes, clubs, agents, sponsors and fans—not to mention the State. In 1997, Ebsworth J commented that “sport today is big business”Footnote 1; but if it was big then, it is prodigious now. Sport is a booming industry and a central part of modern life. It is “part of our national identity”.Footnote 2

With so much riding on every match, race or tournament, it is vital that there is good governance within each sport. This is the job of Sports Governing Bodies (“SGBs”) at national and international level—for example, in England, the Football Association (FA) or the Rugby Football Union (RFU). These incorporated associations have a monopoly in their sporting market,Footnote 3 with extensive regulatory powers enabling them to exclusively determine and apply the rules affecting athletes, coaches, clubs, agents (collectively “participants”) and even supporters. The propriety of these competences is not in doubt, but, given the industry’s growth, the need for accountability is greater than ever.

This paper will focus on the use of judicial review (“JR”)Footnote 4 as a way of challenging SGB decisions and rules, to achieve legal accountability. English law is settled in its view that SGBs are not amenable to JR following the Court of Appeal (“CA”) decision in R v Disciplinary Committee of the Jockey Club, ex p Aga KhanFootnote 5 but, as Beloff et al. suggest, “it is not clear that the last word has been said on the subject”.Footnote 6 This paper will argue that, 27 years on from the leading decision, the issue merits reconsideration owing to flaws in judicial reasoning and, in particular, the subsequent growth of the government’s involvement in sport. Moreover, the availability of JR in other jurisdictions and against other self-regulatory organisations suggests that the position of SGBs in English law is anomalous.

Since Aga Khan, the courts have developed a private law “supervisory jurisdiction” which somewhat accounts for the absence of JR, but, as it will be argued, private law remedies suffer from substantive and, particularly, procedural limitations, such that JR may be a preferable forum for sporting litigants. The standing requirements and hearing process of JR give it particular appeal in the sports context, and it can be seen as a more efficient alternative to private law actions. The approach of New Zealand, allowing challenges to SGBs in public or private law,Footnote 7 should be followed.

In Finnigan v NZRFU, Cooke J, as he then was, considered that SGBs fall into a “special area where…a sharp boundary between public and private law cannot realistically be drawn”Footnote 8 and, ultimately, it is this fundamental issue which has made this area of law so fraught with controversy. Though this paper does not aim to assess the propriety of a divide between public and private law, which an orthodox view of English law would prescribe,Footnote 9 the analysis undertaken herein allows conclusions to be drawn about the softer nature of that divide today.

2 The state of play

Whether a body may be subject to JR is a question which has troubled courts for decades. Determining the precise scope of JR is incredibly difficult, and it can only be inferred from “the catalogue of the borderline cases”.Footnote 10

Various criteria for determining amenability have emerged over the past 100 years, with the traditional approach being the “source of power” test.Footnote 11 Under this formula, if the power to make the decision in question was derived from statute or the Royal Prerogative, it would be amenable to JR but, if the power was rooted in contract, it would be excluded from public law.Footnote 12 However, the law in this area has developed such that it is now proper to speak of a “public function” test.Footnote 13

2.1 The public function test

The potential scope of JR was extended in R v Panel on Takeovers and Mergers, ex p Datafin,Footnote 14 in which Lloyd LJ held:

I do not agree that the source of the power is the sole test whether a body is subject to judicial review…the source of the power will often, perhaps usually, be decisive. If the source of power is a statute, or subordinate legislation under a statute, then clearly the body in question will be subject to judicial review. If, at the other end of the scale, the source of power is contractual, as in the case of private arbitration, then clearly the arbitrator is not subject to judicial review…

But in between these extremes there is an area in which it is helpful to look not just at the source of the power but at the nature of the power. If the body in question is exercising public law functions, or if the exercise of its functions have public law consequences, then that may…be sufficient to bring the body within the reach of judicial review.Footnote 15

This decision led to the emergence of the public function test, which has since been formally adopted into the Civil Procedure Rules (“CPR”).Footnote 16 As such, a claim for JR can only be brought in respect of an enactment, a decision, an action or a failure to act relating to the exercise of a “public function”.Footnote 17

The precise meaning of this term has been the subject of much deliberation, and there remains some uncertainty. In Datafin itself, Sir John Donaldson MR spoke simply of a “public element, which can take many forms”,Footnote 18 while in the more recent case of Hampshire County Council v Beer t/a Hammer Trout Farm,Footnote 19 Dyson LJ spoke of the need for sufficient public “flavour” to bring a body’s decision within the reach of public law.Footnote 20 This criterion is “very broad, not to say question-begging”,Footnote 21 but there is a growing body of case law from which principles can be extracted.Footnote 22

In Beer, the CA held that a decision of Hampshire Farmers Markets Limited, a private company, had sufficient public flavour in order to be amenable to JR, largely owing to its close relationship with Hampshire County Council and the fact that it was regulating access to a public market. Similarly, the International Stock Exchange of the United Kingdom (“UK”) and the Republic of Ireland (a limited company) was held amenable to JR owing to its wider “public” role.Footnote 23

In Datafin, the Panel on Take-overs and Mergers was found to be susceptible to JR. The panel was a self-regulating body in charge of enforcing the City Code on Take-overs and Mergers, with no statutory, prerogative or common law powers. The court noted the panel’s immense power and thought the fact it was not a statutory body was a “complete anomaly”Footnote 24 explicable only as an accident of history. It was also key that the government had “incorporated the panel into its own regulatory network”Footnote 25 and that private law control would be ineffective.Footnote 26 Therefore, though Sir John Donaldson MR suggested that amenability depends simply on finding a “public element”, the reasoning in the cases suggests a narrower approachFootnote 27—there will only be a public function where certain “public” features can be identified.

Yet there may also be uncertainty about what “publicness” is. As Hoffman LJ stated in Aga Khan, in line with previous authorities,Footnote 28 public law and public interest are not the same thing:

Private power may affect the public interest…But that does not subject it to the rules of public law.Footnote 29

The court in Aga Khan considered that, to be amenable to JR, the power must be “governmental”.Footnote 30 It may be that this interpretation is too narrow,Footnote 31 but, for the purposes of this paper, it suffices that “public” means “governmental”.

Therefore, it follows from the CPR and an established body of case law that the modern test for amenability to JR is one of the public functions. Though the source of the power may be relevant, the existence of a contractual relationship is not necessarily inconsistent with JR,Footnote 32 provided that the rights asserted are not purely contractual.Footnote 33

2.2 The position of SGBs

Traditionally, SGBs have fallen outside the scope of JR, following the CA decision in Law v National Greyhound Racing Club.Footnote 34 Primarily, this was justified on the basis that the source of the SGB’s power was contractual and the appropriate remedy was, therefore, in private law. This approach was applied by the courts in, inter alia, R v Football Association of Wales, ex p Flint Town United FCFootnote 35 and R v Football Association, ex p Football League.Footnote 36

However, the issue returned to the CA in Aga Khan, where the applicant sought to challenge a decision by the disciplinary committee of the Jockey Club (an SGB) to disqualify his horse for failing a drugs test. Notwithstanding the functional shift instigated by Datafin, the position in Law was upheld and JR denied. Hoffman LJ, as he then was, held that the SGB operated “entirely in the private sector and its activities are governed by private law”.Footnote 37

While he made clear that private clubs are capable of also exercising public powers, he found that “there is no public source for any of [the Jockey Club’s] powers”.Footnote 38 The court heavily emphasised the existence of a contractual relationship between the parties and noted that the applicant would likely have a remedy in private law.Footnote 39 Farquharson LJ stressed that “public law remedies do not lie against domestic bodies, as they derive solely from the consent of the parties”.Footnote 40

For JR to lie, according to Hoffman LJ, the power may be de facto or de jure, but it must be “governmental in nature”.Footnote 41 As Sir Thomas Bingham MR stated:

the Jockey Club…has not been woven into any system of governmental control of horseracing…This has the result that while the Jockey Club’s powers may be described as, in many ways, public they are in no sense governmental.Footnote 42

A final thread of the CA’s reasoning was the rejection of the argument that “but for” Jockey Club’s existence, the government would be forced to intervene to regulate horseracing and, as such, its powers could be considered “public”. Farquharson LJ straightforwardly dismissed the idea that “any governmental body would assume control of racing”,Footnote 43 while Sir Thomas Bingham MR accepted that “the government would probably be driven to create a public body to do so”Footnote 44 but ultimately held that this did not alter the fact that its powers derived from contract and were thus not “governmental”.Footnote 45

This approach has been definitive in English law and has been followed consistently,Footnote 46 surviving its most recent challenge in R (Mullins) v Jockey Club (No. 1).Footnote 47

3 The case for judicial review

Given the case law to date, SGBs are highly unlikely to be considered amenable to JR without a Supreme Court (“UKSC”) decision overruling Aga Khan.Footnote 48 It is submitted that there is a strong case for such a decision and that the existing line of authority has been a “wrong turn”Footnote 49 in English law. This Part will re-evaluate Aga Khan, criticising the court’s reasoning, drawing on support from analogous English case law and that of other jurisdictions. SGBs perform a public function now more than ever, and so, properly applying the test laid out in Part 2.1, should be amenable to JR.

It is important to establish at the outset that, though the argument herein will refer to SGBs in the abstract, each case would turn on its own facts and it is likely that some SGBs would be more readily susceptible to JR than others.Footnote 50 However, given the fundamental similarities between the position and powers of SGBs, and the broad government interest in sport as a whole, it is legitimate to predicate the argument on the basis that they would generally be treated alike.

3.1 Re-evaluating Aga Khan

The argument for overruling Aga Khan rests on two main propositions: that it places too much weight on the source of SGB power and fails to appreciate its public flavour—something which has become more pronounced in subsequent years. These central strands of argument shall be considered in turn, though it is impossible to separate them entirely.

3.1.1 The source of the power

Firstly, it is argued that Aga Khan focuses too much on the source of the powers of SGBs, as opposed to their function, which sits uncomfortably with the decision in Datafin and subsequent authorities.Footnote 51 The court emphasised that JR was unavailable because the source of the power was a consensual, contractual relationship between the parties. However, this approach fails to recognise the true nature of the relationship between participants and SGBs, as well as the nature of SGB power.

The “contract” is fictional

To describe the relationship between a participant and an SGB as purely contractual is artificial and unrealistic. SGB regulations bind participants regardless of any express contract and may even preclude individuals participating altogether.Footnote 52 In Modahl v British Athletics Federation,Footnote 53 the CA held that there are three ways in which a contractual link can be established between an SGB and an athlete: the “club basis” (a chain of mutually interdependent contracts starting with an employment contract with a sports club in which the athlete agrees to be bound by the SGB regulations), the “participation basis” (a contract is implied by virtue of the athlete’s participation under the regulations) or the “submission basis” (a contract is implied by virtue of the athlete’s submission to the SGB’s regulatory procedures).Footnote 54 Though there will be exceptions,Footnote 55 in the archetypal case, there is no express contract with the SGB. Indeed, in Modahl, Parker LJ dissented, considering there to be no real intention to create legal relations, nor any consideration to speak of.Footnote 56

As Lord Denning MR observed in Enderby Town FC v Football Association,Footnote 57 this “contract” is simply a “fiction created by the lawyers to give jurisdiction”.Footnote 58 It is necessary for the effective administration of sport,Footnote 59 as there is no statutory scheme by which to otherwise enforce the rules. SGBs, as argued below, are de facto public bodies: it is simply an accident of history that they must rely on the contractual jurisdiction. Using a fiction created to increase oversight of SGBs to now deny such oversight via JR lacks common sense—the law should be “mature enough” to “do away with” such fictions.Footnote 60

The lack of genuine consent

There is also a lack of genuine consent to SGBs’ jurisdiction, undermining further the argument against JR in Aga Khan. Each SGB has its own set of regulationsFootnote 61 which cover an incredibly broad array of issues including discipline, doping, intermediaries, corruption, betting, safety, safeguarding, player licensing, eligibility, transfers, club ownership and finance, as well as the rules of the sport itself. They are even able to limit freedom of expression.Footnote 62 As Lord Denning MR observed, such regulations are, in reality, a “legislative code”Footnote 63 going far beyond a contractual regime. They regulate an entire sphere of conduct, both commercial and personal, and give SGBs the enormous power to impose sanctions which can range from 1-week suspensions, to lifetime bansFootnote 64 as well as points deductions, fines, or even relegation.

Enormous power alone, though, is insufficient to undermine the purported contractual relationship. Freedom of contract is a fundamental feature of English contract law, and, as such, parties are free to agree to all these things. The key point, however, is that there is no “agreement” in the true sense of the word—these are rules which are imposed rather than consented to.

One might argue this is true of most contracts entered into in the modern day—for example, employment or consumer contracts. However, the enormous power of SGBs is doubly significant because they hold a monopoly. As such, participants are in an incredibly weak position and have no choice but to accept the regulations.Footnote 65 This is ultimately “Hobson’s choice”—terms are imposed on a “take it or leave it” basis, and the latter is no option at all. By contrast, in the employment and consumer contexts, there will ordinarily be other job opportunities and other products to buy in the market.Footnote 66 In such monopolistic circumstances, “consensual submission” provides no basis on which to exclude JR,Footnote 67 as there is no genuine consent.

This argument was rejected by Farquharson LJ in Aga Khan. He suggested that the “reality of the consent” was not undermined, as the imposition of rules was necessary for the administration of sport.Footnote 68 The latter is certainly true, so it would be dangerous to suggest that there is insufficient consent for the “contract” to be binding, but it must nonetheless be recognised that the consent is artificial.Footnote 69 The court here took an “unusually two-dimensional view”Footnote 70 which is particularly unsatisfactory because “when genuine consent is absent, this is precisely when abuse of power is most likely, and judicial protection most needed”.Footnote 71 The court should instead have focused on the unavoidability of submission to the decision-maker.Footnote 72

Farquharson LJ’s view was echoed by the CA in Stretford v Football Association,Footnote 73 but the European Court of Human Rights recently took a different approach,Footnote 74 holding that an arbitration clause enclosed in an SGB’s regulations had not been agreed in a “free and unambiguous manner”Footnote 75 and, thus, the athlete’s rights under Art.6(1) ECHR had not been validly waived. Though this was a human rights case, it nevertheless recognised that consent to SGB regulations is not real—a decision English courts will have to take into account.Footnote 76

Should consent preclude judicial review?

It is also arguable that the reasoning in Aga Khan is unsound because it could be applied to all forms of voluntary activity subject to a statutory licensing regime.Footnote 77 It could be said that an applicant to a statutory licensing authority “voluntarily” submits to its jurisdiction, as they could choose not to engage in the relevant activity. Of course, in such cases, “consensual submission” would not preclude JR. Nor should it for SGBs.

That said, Sir John Donaldson MR said in Datafin that “bodies whose sole source of power is a consensual submission to its jurisdiction” (emphasis added) will be excluded from the scope of JR.Footnote 78 Consensual submission is not a statutory licensing authority’s sole source of power. However, the same is arguably true of SGBs, as they wield de facto public power—power which is impliedly devolved, or perhaps even expressly derived, from government, as explained below.

Indeed, the source of the power cannot be fully separated from the nature of the power. The dicta in Datafin properly suggest that where a body is exercising a public function, there will not be a purely contractual relationship—the very publicness of the power means that public law is applicable, regardless of any contract.Footnote 79

Given the fictional nature of the “contract” and the artificiality of the consent to SGBs’ jurisdiction, placing such weight on the source of the power as the court did in Aga Khan is inappropriateFootnote 80—particularly when the modern test for amenability requires a more functional approach, and the existence of a contract has been held not to be fatal to JR claims in subsequent decisions.Footnote 81 SGBs’ power may formally be predicated on contract, but the reality is that they are performing a public function.

3.1.2 Satisfying the public function test

Having established that there should be no contractual and/or consensual bar to an application for JR against an SGB, it can now be argued that SGBs should be amenable to JR because they satisfy the public function test set out in Part 2.1. Though there has always been a strong case for SGBs satisfying this test,Footnote 82 it has now become irrefutable owing to the change in government policy, which allows the missing “governmental” element to be found.

The enormous public interest in sport gives it great potential as a government policy tool to achieve social and political objectives, and it is undoubtedly used to promote national standing.Footnote 83 Indeed, throughout modern history, sport has been used as a bargaining tool in international relations.Footnote 84 This immediately suggests a public element, but more specific arguments can be made. These arguments are ones which have often been put forward, but it is submitted that the wider context has changed such that they can now be made more forcefully.

The “But For” argument

Firstly, it is submitted that, but for the work of SGBs, the government—owing to its direct interest in sport and its governance—would itself be driven to regulate sport, demonstrating that SGBs are, in reality, carrying out a public function. This is a test frequently used to determine amenabilityFootnote 85 but was answered in the negative in Aga Khan,Footnote 86 endorsing the view of Rose J in R v FA, ex p Football League:

I find no sign of underpinning directly or indirectly by any organ or agency of the State or any potential government interest…nor is there any evidence to suggest that if the FA did not exist the State would intervene to create a public body to perform its functions.Footnote 87

With respect, it is suggested that such views are out of date and merit reconsideration. The government today has a clear, direct interest in sport,Footnote 88 and there is plenty to suggest that, in the absence of SGBs, they would intervene.

In the first decade of the twenty-first century, Exchequer funding of sport reached unprecedented levelsFootnote 89 and, in 2002, sport was properly recognised in government, as a key policy objective of the Department for Digital, Culture, Media and Sport (“DCMS”).Footnote 90 The DCMS is now primarily responsible for administering public sports policy, albeit at arm’s length via several non-departmental public bodiesFootnote 91 (“NDPBs”), including Sport England and UK Sport. The traditional view that “‘the government does not and should not run sport’ no longer reflects the complexities of modern sports policy”,Footnote 92 nor the reality of its implementation in the UK.

The 2015 DCMS “Sporting Future” policy paper gave some telling indications of the government’s direct interest in sport, setting out the government’s strategy of “harnessing the power of sport for the good of our whole society”,Footnote 93 emphasising sport’s personal, economic and social impact. Sport’s role in the pursuit of public health goals is significant,Footnote 94 and SGBs are often key to implementing such policy.Footnote 95

In addition, as the 2015 paper announced, government agencies Sport England and UK Sport have developed a new Code for Sports Governance setting out the levels of “transparency, accountability and financial integrity” required of SGBs seeking public funding.Footnote 96

Furthermore, the DCMS Committee (“DCMSC”)Footnote 97 has conducted detailed enquiries into matters of concern within sport, including homophobia,Footnote 98 women and sport,Footnote 99 match-fixing in tennisFootnote 100 and, currently, sports governance more broadly.Footnote 101 The DCMSC’s very existence demonstrates a government interest in sport, but the nature of its enquiries reveals a particular desire to ensure accountability. This is perhaps best exemplified by its 2018 “combatting doping in sport” report which followed an intrusive and very public enquiry, centred around British Cycling.Footnote 102

Indeed, the government is particularly concerned with anti-doping. In 2003, the UK government signed the Copenhagen Declaration on Anti-Doping in Sport, in which they agreed to formally recognise and implement the World Anti-Doping Code (“WADC”) and, in 2006, ratified the International Convention against Doping in Sport. Moreover, the government showed its dedication to the anti-doping movement by creating the UK Anti-Doping agency in 2009, another NDPB. It is responsible for the sample collection, testing and whereabouts programmes of the majority of UK athletes. By funding an anti-doping programme and by signing up to internationally agreed anti-doping objectives, the government seeks to promote fair and clean sport, further highlighting its direct interest.

A further example of government expansion into sport has been in the field of anti-corruption. The Gambling Commission—another NDPB—created the Sports Betting Intelligence Unit (“SBIU”) in 2005 to monitor gambling and uphold integrity in sport, while s.42 of the Gambling Act 2005 was introduced by the government specifically to target match-fixing.Footnote 103 Section 42 makes it a criminal offence to “cheat at gambling”,Footnote 104 which includes interference with a sporting event to which the gambling relates.Footnote 105

More recently, in 2014, the government published the UK Anti-Corruption Plan, which set out a cross-governmental approach to tackle corruption, including specific measures addressing corruption in sport. Principal among these was the Sport and Sports Betting Integrity Action Plan, launched by the Gambling Commission in 2015, which delineates the responsibilities of, inter alia, SGBs and government in combatting corruption. Such an initiative is yet another example of how the government’s interest and involvement in sport has grown since the early 1990s.

There is thus a strong argument that “but for” SGBs, the government would be driven to regulate sport itself, such is its interest in the sector. SGBs are therefore exercising a public function.

The “Interwoven” argument

Moreover, as required by the courts in Datafin and Aga Khan, SGBs are “woven into the fabric of public regulation”.Footnote 106

For example, the role of administering anti-doping rules is not exclusive to UKAD. All SGBs adopt the WADC into their own regulations and assume responsibility, along with UKAD, for its implementation. Indeed, it is often the SGBs themselves that act as prosecutor in doping cases and who are responsible for enforcing bans imposed by the National Anti-Doping Panel.

Much the same point can be made with regard to anti-corruption. Working closely alongside the police and the SBIU, SGBs have taken a proactive role in the fight against corruption.Footnote 107 All major SGBs have extensive anti-corruption regulationsFootnote 108 aimed at deterring and punishing conduct which is corrupt, or potentially so, through sporting sanctions. While not all conduct punished by SGBs is also criminal, the most serious cases will be and, by implementing such comprehensive regulations, SGBs play an important role in preventing criminal behaviour.

However, SGBs’ jurisdiction does not cover those who may be involved from outside of sport in corruption and, thus, an effective approach to tackling the problem requires cooperation with, inter alia, law enforcement agencies and government.Footnote 109 As aforementioned, this joined-up approach is explicitly recognised in the Sport and Sports Betting Integrity Action Plan, which imposes certain requirements on each of the key stakeholders, including the Gambling Commission—a government agency. In this context, too, SGBs are therefore woven into the fabric of public regulation.

Moreover, the SGBs of sports such as rugby, football, boxing and other contact sports have exclusive jurisdiction over an area which would ordinarily be governed by the criminal law. Following R v Barnes,Footnote 110 violent conduct in the sporting arena is exempted from criminal sanction, as long as it remains within reasonable bounds of the rules. As such, these SGBs fulfil the function of policing those bounds by ensuring that violent conduct in breach of the rules is sanctioned appropriately. In other words, a jurisdiction is carved out of the criminal law for certain SGBs. This specific function has strong public flavour in itself, given the otherwise public nature of the sanctions the conduct would attract, and it is also an example of how SGBs are woven into public regulation.

Indeed, this is highlighted explicitly in the memorandum of understanding between the FA, FAW, the Crown Prosecution Service and the Association of Chief Police Officers.Footnote 111 It recognises that there are often situations in which football’s SGBs will have concurrent jurisdiction with law enforcement agencies and sets out the terms of their cooperation in relation to both investigating and sanctioning.

A further example is the statutory regulation of football hooliganism, which was the culmination of prolonged efforts by the government, in combination with the police and football’s SGBs, to gain control of the issue.Footnote 112 For the offences under the Football (Offences) Act 1991 to be made out, or for a Football Banning Order to be imposed under the Football Spectators Act 1989, the match with which the relevant conduct is connected must be a “designated” football match—ultimately, a game under the authority of the SGBs.Footnote 113 In this regard, football’s SGBs are inextricably integrated into governmental regulation.

Of course, these latter examples are confined to certain sports and as such can only advance the argument insofar as those specific SGBs are concerned. However, there is strong evidence of a more general integration of SGBs into the public sphere and, in any event, as noted above,Footnote 114 it may be that certain SGBs are more susceptible to JR than others.

Implied devolution of power

One might nonetheless argue that the government has still abstained from directly intervening in day-to-day sports regulation; it is left to private bodies and as such falls properly within the private sector. Indeed, in 2018, the government rejected a petition to create an independent regulator for English football, on the basis that the existing authorities do a satisfactory job, negating any need or desire to create a government body.Footnote 115 Government:

believes sports are best governed by modern, transparent, accountable and representative governing bodies, able to act decisively in the long-term interest of each sport and its participantsFootnote 116

However, this reflects an implied devolution of governmental power. By actively choosing not to legislate in this field, owing to its satisfaction with the work of the FA, the government is impliedly granting the SGB power to continue regulating football, in the same way that Lloyd LJ considered the panel in Datafin to be operating.Footnote 117 The same can be said of many SGBs, though there isn’t such explicit evidence. The government has a strong interest in sport’s regulation, but, due to their expertise and natural independence, it considers existing SGBs better-placed to perform that function and thus, far from abstaining, gives them implied authority to continue doing so. That sport is administered by private bodies is simply an accident of history.Footnote 118

In any event, SGBs’ receipt of public funding, via Sport England and UK Sport, suggests that their power may be somewhat derived from government expressly.

Public interest

Finally, the “massive public interest in sport”Footnote 119 plays a role in creating public flavour. The fact that sport can affect people’s lives in so many ways, as fans, participants and aspiring participants, means that the public at large has an interest in its good governance. Though “public interest” has been considered distinct from “public law”,Footnote 120 it is suggested that the two can be linked. Public interest affects government decision-making and ultimately drives public policy. As such, an area of significant public interest is almost inevitably an area of government interest, such that its regulation will have public flavour. Sport is one such area.

Moreover, all SGBs act, or at least purport to act, in the public interest.Footnote 121 They commonly cite as their object the promotion and growth of the sport throughout their territory.Footnote 122 This may include commercialisation, but the primary objective remains the development of the sport itself, which is in the public interest. SGBs thus perform a function which is “other-regarding”Footnote 123—something typical of government—which might further suggest that a public function is being exercised.Footnote 124

There are thus multiple ways to demonstrate that SGBs wield de facto public power. Undeniably, as the sports industry has grown exponentially over the past two decades, so has the government’s interest in it. In Aga Khan, Hoffman LJ considered that the English legislator’s attitude to racing was “akin to its attitude to religion…something to be encouraged but not the business of government”.Footnote 125 This statement can no longer hold true. Aga Khan merits reconsideration: SGBs are performing a public function.

3.1.3 Supporting case law

The argument premised herein is not altogether unsupported by English case law. Indeed, in Aga Khan itself, Farquharson LJ refused to “discount the possibility that in some special circumstances the remedy might lie”,Footnote 126 while Lord Woolf MR similarly left the possibility open in Wilander v Tobin (No. 2).Footnote 127 It is suggested that the new-found governmental element provides such special circumstances.

In R v Jockey Club, ex p RAM Racecourses,Footnote 128 Brown J held that he would have allowed JR of the Jockey Club but for the fact that he was bound by the decision in Law. He considered the function of regulating a sport “strikingly akin to the exercise of a statutory licensing power” and, as such, had “no difficulty in regarding it as one of a public law body”.Footnote 129 The court in R v Disciplinary Committee of the Jockey Club, ex p Massingberg-MundyFootnote 130 considered itself similarly bound, but otherwise would have allowed JR. More recently, in Jockey Club v Buffham, Gray J described the Jockey Club as a “public authority in every sense”.Footnote 131 The Jockey Club—no longer the regulator of horseracing in Britain—was no different in its role and powers than other SGBs.

Support can also be derived from the “borderline cases”, particularly those in which “self-regulatory bodies” have been held amenable to JR. For example, the Advertising Standards Authority (“ASA”)Footnote 132 and the former Press Complaints CommissionFootnote 133 have been considered to be subject to JR, as has the Code of Practice Committee of the British Pharmaceutical Industry (“CPC”).Footnote 134 All are/were private, self-regulatory organisations without any statutory basis but which regulate(d) important parts of public life and were woven into the fabric of public regulation.

Indeed, in R v Advertising Standards Authority Ltd, ex p Insurance Service plc,Footnote 135 Glidewell LJ, in holding that the ASA was subject to JR, said:

The Authority has no powers granted to it by statute or at common law, nor does it have any contractual relationship with the advertisers whom it controls. Nevertheless it is clearly exercising a public law function which, if the Authority did not exist, would no doubt be exercised by the Director General of Fair Trading.

For the reasons outlined in Part 3.1, it is argued that SGBs are analogous.

In Professional Counselling Aids,Footnote 136 Popplewell J reluctantly found the CPC amenable to JR, emphasising that Datafin had “enlarge[d] enormously”Footnote 137 the scope of JR and placing reliance on the decision in Insurance Service. The latter was endorsed specifically in Aga Khan.Footnote 138

Likewise, the Bar Council was held reviewable in R v General Council of the Bar, ex p PercivalFootnote 139, a body “empowered by its rules to prosecute [complaints] before the disciplinary tribunal as an adjudicating body exercising powers delegated by the judges”.Footnote 140 The Council has an important role in regulating the Bar—a field in which the government certainly has an interest, given the way barristers affect the determination of individuals’ fundamental rights. But for the Bar Council it seems incredibly likely that a statutory authority—like the Solicitors Regulatory Authority—would be created. SGBs perform a similar role, regulating an area of government interest and quasi-judicially determining fundamental rights.

Furthermore, parallels can be drawn between the position of SGBs and the limited company subjected to JR in Beer. In the same way that Hampshire Farmers Markets Ltd. regulated access to a market in which there was significant public interest, so too do SGBs. Indeed, the market to which SGBs regulate access is an awful lot larger, as it operates at national level.

More recently, the Independent Press Standards Organisation (“IPSO”), which is one of several independent regulators of the UK press, was subjected to JR.Footnote 141 Though the court did not formally decide the jurisdictional point, Warby J allowed JR to proceed in spite of the fact that IPSO has not been recognised by the statutory Press Recognition Panel and his own recognition that “the argument against IPSO decisions being amenable to [JR] is stronger than it was in the case of the Jockey Club”.Footnote 142 Though it operates in the public interest, IPSO does not operate a monopoly and the court doubted that government would step in if it did not exist, as the Leveson Report did not recommend state regulation of the press.Footnote 143 This might be seen as a further enlargement of the scope of JR which, in fact, goes beyond SGBs.

Therefore, allowing JR of SGBs would not be at odds with existing case law and would, in fact, make it more coherent—that they are not considered amenable is anomalous.

3.1.4 The comparative argument

It is also relevant that other jurisdictions have recognised the public function of SGBs. In French law, sports disciplinary sanctions are classed as administrative acts which can therefore only be reviewed by the administrative courts,Footnote 144 while in Spain the public nature of sport is recognised in constitutional lawFootnote 145 and there is a specific administrative court dedicated to resolving sports regulatory disputes.Footnote 146

Turning to other common law jurisdictions, the High Court of Australia allowed JR of an SGB in Forbes v NSW Trotting Club,Footnote 147 where the function of controlling the sport—“a public activity”—was considered significant. The same position has been reached in New Zealand,Footnote 148 Canada,Footnote 149 South AfricaFootnote 150 and, albeit to a limited extent,Footnote 151 the USA.Footnote 152 The English position thus appears to be an anomaly, “unjustifiably lagging behind its Commonwealth counterparts”.Footnote 153

The argument here runs deeper than simply saying “they do it, so we should do it”. The crucial point is that these jurisdictions have recognised the public flavour of SGBs: they have recognised why SGBs properly fit into the public sphere. SGBs have much the same role and powers world over, so it appears incongruous that English law is asking the same question and getting a different answer. This is particularly significant as regards the other common law jurisdictions, as the principles at play are broadly the same. That England is the odd one out is telling.

Most concerning perhaps is that JR of SGBs has long been available in Scotland.Footnote 154 Of course, Scots law does not distinguish between public and private law in the same way as English law, which may account for the different result, but it nonetheless sits uncomfortably given the geographical proximity of the jurisdictions. Indeed, in some sporting contexts, athletes from the two jurisdictions compete together, under a single SGB.Footnote 155 It was held in Lennox v British Show Jumping AssociationFootnote 156 that such bodies would be reviewable in Scotland. This results in “forum shopping”,Footnote 157 whereby a party will simply seek to claim in the most favourable jurisdiction. Such inconsistencies are unsatisfactory and, for example, could lead to the situation whereby athletes of the same nationality, in the same sport, might have differing legal remedies available to them simply because of the team/SGB of which they are a member.

The fact that so many other jurisdictions have recognised the public flavour of SGBs certainly makes Aga Khan appear anomalous. However, Hoffman LJ was not drawn by comparative arguments:

different countries draw the line between public and private regulation in different places. The fact that certain functions of the Jockey Club could be exercised by a statutory body and that they are so exercised in some other countries does not make them governmental functions in England.Footnote 158

While it is certainly true that different jurisdictions approach the public/private divide differently, comparative analysis in this field has particular value. The sports industry is truly international: athletes from England and Wales regularly compete against athletes from other jurisdictions and the fact that foreign athletes can access JR might give them an advantage—as explained in Part 4—which adds to the case for JR. It is surely desirable to enhance consistency in international sports law generally, especially when there are good, principled reasons for doing so. To do so is in the interests of both the administrators and participants of sport globally.

The court’s approach in Aga Khan is out of date, and it is time to follow our Commonwealth counterparts.

3.1.5 To what extent?

Having argued that SGBs should be amenable to JR, it is important to consider to what extent they would be so. For an application for JR to succeed, not only must the body be susceptible to JR, but so must the specific decision in question.Footnote 159 A public body in the modern day exercises many functions, some of which will not be “public”—such as entering employment contracts—and these will not be judicially reviewable.Footnote 160

SGBs similarly perform a multitude of functions. Many operate their national team and, as such, undertake an array of commercial tasks such as negotiating sponsorship and paying players. Such purely commercial functions would be outside the scope of JR. It is only the regulatory function of SGBs which should be reviewable—only in this regard can their function be described as “public”.

4 Private law remedies

The final issue which must be considered is the availability of private law remedies. In Aga Khan, Hoffman LJ stated that the existence of “entirely adequate” remedies in private law meant that no injustice would be caused by the denial of a public law remedy.Footnote 161 This appears to allow the argument that private law remedies in the sporting context are, in fact, inadequate and, as such, JR should be allowed. However, he also stated that JR should not be used “to patch up” remedies available against bodies which would otherwise not be amenable to JR.Footnote 162 Indeed, this seems to be the approach adopted consistently by English courts.Footnote 163 As Lord Oliver explained in Leech v Deputy Governor of Parkhurst Prison,Footnote 164 alternative remedies are relevant to the court’s decision to permit JR, but not to the prior question of amenability.Footnote 165

Therefore, the inadequacy of private law remedies cannot by itself make the case for amenability, but is relevant to the broader question of whether SGBs should be subject to JR. As such, this Part will highlight the limitations of the private law causes of action used to challenge SGBs, both substantive and procedural, and will argue that they should not preclude a claim for JR. This will demonstrate that the debate in Part 3 is not purely academicFootnote 166: there are practical reasons why an aggrieved sports participant would want to pursue JR as opposed to a private law cause of action.

On this view, sporting claimants have rights in both public and private law. This might be thought odd in the light of the procedural exclusivity rule,Footnote 167 but, though a claim cannot be brought in public and private law simultaneously, the harshness of this rule has been mitigatedFootnote 168 such that a claim is unlikely to be struck out simply for using the “less appropriate” procedure.Footnote 169 Indeed, in Clark v University of Lincolnshire and Humberside,Footnote 170 Sedley LJ considered that, though JR could have been sought, a claim in private law was just as appropriate as there was simply “a contractual relationship which happens to possess a public law dimension”.Footnote 171 The same can be said of the participant–SGB relationship. It is argued that rights against SGBs may arise in public and private lawFootnote 172 and, as such, that litigants should be able to mount their claim depending on which jurisdiction would provide the better remedy in the circumstances. Indeed, this is the approach taken in New Zealand.Footnote 173

4.1 Private law causes of action

Claims for breach of contract, restraint of trade and in the so-called private law “supervisory jurisdiction” have proved to be the primary mechanisms for challenging SGBs in English law and, as such, will be considered here. However, challenges could also be mounted to varying degrees in the contractual “public policy” jurisdiction,Footnote 174 competition lawFootnote 175 and EU law—though the latter would also be possible in JR.

4.1.1 Breach of contract

As explained above, SGB regulations are readily interpreted as contracts.Footnote 176 Though this is somewhat artificial, it is a fiction the law has adopted consistently, out of necessity. Without an express or implied contract between the SGB and the participants, SGBs would have no legal basis for the exercise of its powersFootnote 177—participants could simply choose not to accept SGB regulatory decisions, and sport would descend into chaos. As merely de facto public bodies, SGBs must rely on private law.

As such, courts can perform a degree of review via claims for breach of contract. Some SGBs today explicitly prescribe the principles of natural justice and procedural fairness in their regulations.Footnote 178 Thus, a decision might be challenged as a breach of an express contractual term. A court could then make a declaration as to the validity of the decision and remedy any ill-effects by awarding an injunction and/or damages.Footnote 179

Equally, the courts have shown themselves willing to imply the principles of natural justice into SGB regulations.Footnote 180 Indeed, “public law principles” were implied into contracts at the highest level in Braganza v BP Shipping,Footnote 181 to conduct a review “almost indistinguishable from the general approach to review of public powers”.Footnote 182 This mirrors the view of Lord Woolf MR in Modahl v British Athletics Federation (No. 1)Footnote 183 that there is:

no reason why there should be any difference as to what constitutes unfairness or why the standard of fairness required by an implied term should differ from that required of the same tribunal under public lawFootnote 184

It can thus be said with confidence that the substance of the obligations owed by SGBs as a matter of private law is broadly the same as those they would owe if their decisions were amenable to JR.Footnote 185

However, this may undermine one of the principal arguments in favour of precluding JR: that it would illegitimately cut across the intentions of the parties to the contract.Footnote 186 After all, if contract law itself recognises that party autonomy is limited by principles equivalent to those of JR, how can the argument against the applicability of these principles in JR be maintained? One might argue that the court in Braganza was merely giving effect to the presumed intentions of the parties, but the reality is that the court went much further than that.Footnote 187 These standards will invariably be applied “in the absence of very clear language”Footnote 188 to the contrary. In private law terms, it appears that these are terms implied “in law” into certain types of contract, rather than “in fact”. Therefore, the argument in support of Aga Khan becomes difficult to sustain.

It is also a limit of the implied terms approach that parties could exclude their application through express terms.Footnote 189 One might argue that the same “exclusion” could be achieved in JR via an ouster clause. However, given the restrictive interpretative approach taken by the courts to such clauses,Footnote 190 it is suggested that an effective exclusion of the courts’ jurisdiction would be less likely in public law.Footnote 191

Of course, an action for breach of contract will only be available where a contract exists. Though the courts have been willing to imply contracts readily in the sports context,Footnote 192 participants without a contract, such as those prevented from entering the sport in the first place, will have no remedy here. This action will also be of limited use to participants looking to challenge regulations themselves: only new regulations which the SGB makes ultra vires could be challenged. When an action for breach of contract is unavailable, JR would provide a remedy.

4.1.2 Restraint of trade

An associated mechanism for challenging SGBs is the doctrine of restraint of trade. According to the leading case, Nordenfelt v Maxim Nordenfelt Guns and Ammunition Co,Footnote 193 a contractual term which places a restraint on the exercise of an individual’s trade will be void unless it can be justified as reasonable by reference to the interests of the parties and the interests of the public.Footnote 194 It has evolved as a public policy tool to protect individual autonomy and has been extended to non-contractual cases.Footnote 195 It can be used to challenge not only SGB decisions,Footnote 196 but also regulations themselves.Footnote 197 Though it does not give rise to an action for damages, courts can make declarations as to validityFootnote 198 and may be able to award an injunction.Footnote 199

However, the doctrine is not without its limitations. Firstly, it is not always clear where the burden of proof lies in sports cases, nor how the standard of reasonableness should be formulated.Footnote 200 In Stevenage Borough FC v The Football League,Footnote 201 Carnwath J suggested that the burden was on the individual seeking to challenge the provision, adopting a reasonableness standard influenced by JR,Footnote 202 but in Newport AFC v Football Association of WalesFootnote 203 the court treated the issue using orthodox contractual principles, with the onus on the SGB to justify the rule. There is still no “universal and immutable standard of review”.Footnote 204 Such uncertainty makes the doctrine unappealing.

Its greatest limitation, though, is that it is confined to cases concerning “trade”.Footnote 205 In Ray v PGA Ltd.,Footnote 206 the court held that the doctrine did not apply because the claimant’s contract was a “training” contract, not a “trading” contract.Footnote 207 More famously, British sprinter Dwain Chambers was refused an interim injunction to enable him to compete at the 2008 Olympics, in part, because the Olympic Games is an amateur event.Footnote 208 The court held that, even if it could be argued that his Olympic participation could give rise to an “indirect financial benefit”, Chambers’ “prospects of success” at the Olympics were “at best, speculative”, such that it would be difficult to argue that there was any restraint of trade.Footnote 209 As Mackay J put it, “his prospects of arguing…that this is a right to work case are not good”.Footnote 210

This was built on the decision of Gasser v Stinson,Footnote 211 where it was held that the restraint of trade doctrine could not apply where an athlete was merely deprived of a “chance of building up a reputation and to later exploit it for commercial gain” but that it would apply where an athlete was prevented from participating in a competition from which they otherwise would have been able to make a financial gain as a “direct consequence”. Therefore, amateur athletes, or athletes competing at such a level that they are unable to be sure of obtaining any direct financial gain from their participation, may be left without a remedy under restraint of trade. In such circumstances, JR could provide a meaningful alternative.

4.1.3 The supervisory jurisdiction

Given the possible vacuum in the law where those affected by SGB regulations are not in a contractual relationship with the SGB,Footnote 212 English private law appears to have developed a residual “supervisory jurisdiction”. In Bradley v Jockey Club,Footnote 213 affirmed on appeal,Footnote 214 it was held that, even in the absence of a contractual relationship, an SGB decision “is subject to the supervisory jurisdiction of the court in accordance with the principles stated in Nagle v Feilden”.Footnote 215

In Nagle, Lord Denning MR stated that courts may have a jurisdiction to see that exercise of “predominant power over…a trade or profession…is not abused”Footnote 216 as a matter of public policy. Indeed, in Bradley, Richards J noted that this area has assumed “even greater importance” given the attitude of the courts towards the JR of SGBs.Footnote 217 He stated:

given the difficulties that sometimes arise in drawing the precise boundary between the two, I would consider it surprising and unsatisfactory if a private law claim in relation to the decision of a domestic body required the court to adopt a materially different approach from a judicial review claimFootnote 218

As such, under this supervisory jurisdiction, the court may review both procedural and substantive fairness and make a declaration as to the “lawfulness of the decision taken”Footnote 219 regardless of the existence of a contract.

Nonetheless, the scope and basis of this jurisdiction were not entirely clear following Bradley, with particular uncertainty over whether it was limited to cases concerning the claimant’s right to work. However, in Mullins v McFarlane and The Jockey Club,Footnote 220 it was held that there was “no jurisdictional…boundary to the power of the Court to grant declaratory relief in this context”Footnote 221—it was not so restricted. It thus appears incredibly broad, and it may be that the matter need only be of “importance”.Footnote 222 It was exercised in both Fallon v Horseracing Regulatory AuthorityFootnote 223 and McKeown v British Horseracing Authority,Footnote 224 but remains a relatively unexplored area, raising a plethora of questions.

Primarily, its basis remains uncertain. Bradley placed great reliance on Nagle, which itself was a “restraint of trade” case,Footnote 225 but the jurisdiction has been construed far more broadly. Bradley may have elided restraint of trade with the court’s general jurisdiction to grant a declaration (now under CPR 40.20),Footnote 226 a point of confusion evident throughout the case law. In McInnes v Onslow-FaneFootnote 227 “public law principles” were seemingly applied under the court’s general jurisdiction, but the court drew heavily on Nagle and restraint of trade.Footnote 228 Likewise, JR principles were injected into restraint of trade in Nagle and Stevenage Borough FC. It may be that in Nagle and Onslow-Fane, the courts were seeking a basis for the grounds of review necessary to do justice and so resorted to the doctrine of restraint of trade, as opposed to relying specifically on the court’s general jurisdiction.Footnote 229 Indeed, Hoffman LJ thought there was “an improvisatory air”Footnote 230 about the solution in Nagle.

The result is that there is a significant lack of clarity over the true basis of the jurisdiction expounded in Bradley and Mullins. This is unsatisfactory and may be practically significant in determining whether amateurs can claim, whether regulations as well as decisions can be challenged, and where the burden of proof lies. Indeed, in Bradley, Richards J deliberately left the question of the burden open.Footnote 231 Yet, as he noted, such difficulties would evaporate if JR applied.Footnote 232 At the time of Nagle and Onslow-Fane, the scope of JR was more limited than it is now—had the functional approach to amenability existed, it would surely have provided the more natural solution.Footnote 233

Moreover, if it is based on restraint of trade, a broad jurisdiction as suggested in Mullins would seem to extend a field of public policy; something which, on orthodox private law principles, is controversialFootnote 234—particularly without proper consideration of the reasons for doing so. Recognising that SGBs are exercising a de facto public function would give a principled justification for review.

There are thus many question marks hanging over the supervisory jurisdiction. There is a confused body of law which has the effect of providing JR “by the back door”; an intellectually unsatisfactory approach and one likely to cause difficulties in practice. Accepting JR of SGBs, it is submitted, would be preferable.

4.1.4 Substantive assessment

Each of the private law causes of action discussed has its merits, but also limitations. Particular uncertainty lies over restraint of trade and the supervisory jurisdiction, largely owing to attempts to infuse the private law with public law principles. Allowing JR of SGBs would obviate the need to perform contortions in private law: it has a body of rules which could readily be applied to SGBs in a transparent and principled way, with no need for adjustment, regardless of the applicant’s status (professional or contractual), and by judges skilled in their application.Footnote 235

Furthermore, mounting a challenge to the regulations themselves would be more straightforward in JR. Indeed, in Aga Khan, Farquharson LJ suggested that:

If for example the JC failed to fulfil its obligations under the charter by making discriminatory rules, it may be that those affected would have a remedy in public lawFootnote 236

In JR, SGB regulations could be substantively challenged on the well-recognised grounds of fundamental rights,Footnote 237 Wednesbury reasonablenessFootnote 238 or proportionality,Footnote 239 though discrimination claims could today be brought under Part 7 of the Equality Act 2010. Successful challenges to SGB regulations have been scarce in the contractual and supervisory jurisdictions,Footnote 240 while restraint of trade is limited. JR would provide a reliable means of challenge, including for amateur athletes.

The remedial differences are also salient. In contract, the available remedies are comprehensive: damages, injunctions or a declaration. In the supervisory jurisdiction, however, applicants can only obtain a declaration. Though a declaration can be a “highly effective weapon”,Footnote 241 its effect may be limited in a non-contractual context. One cannot be in contempt of court for ignoring a declarationFootnote 242 and, if there is no contract, there remains no basis upon which to claim an injunction. It is therefore unclear just how effective a remedy this would be, albeit that there would be public pressure on SGBs to comply.

By contrast, in JR, declarations and injunctions,Footnote 243 as well as mandatory, prohibiting and quashing orders,Footnote 244 are available. The latter would be particularly powerful in undoing the effects of sanctions, though would largely have the same effect in practice as an injunction. Remedies in JR are certainly more powerful than those under the supervisory jurisdiction, though both are discretionary, while the principal difference with the contractual jurisdiction is compensation—in JR, damages are rarely available.Footnote 245 However, they are not usually the most important remedy for sporting claimantsFootnote 246 and, in any event, if cases must be brought within the short time limit of JR and are disposed of quickly, the potential for significant losses to accrue is less likely.

4.2 Procedural matters

The JR procedure is often conceived as providing protection to defendant public bodies, which are politically accountable and whose effectiveness would be hindered by the threat of ordinary litigation.Footnote 247 Oliver has argued that there is no reason why SGBs should benefit from such protectionFootnote 248 but, given the softening of the procedural exclusivity rule, this protective function has diminished in importance for de facto SGBs, as appropriate claims outside of the JR time limit may nonetheless be brought in private law.

It must also be recognised that JR procedure may bring advantages for claimants, especially in the sporting context. Three procedural points of difference add force to the argument that private law remedies are not necessarily adequate, and JR more suitable.

4.2.1 Hearing procedure

Firstly, the JR hearing procedure is far better suited to sports disputes than that of private law, as recognised by Carnwath J in Stevenage Borough FC:

in spite of the efforts of the parties, and the economy of presentation, the writ procedure, with pleadings, discovery and oral evidence, inevitably is more elaborate, time consuming and expensive than judicial review…[where] the case for each party can generally be set out in one main affidavit…supported only by relevant documents; rather than, as in this case, in some 16 witness statements, 15 files of documents and transcripts of 5 days of oral evidenceFootnote 249

JR is a far more expedient and inexpensive process, factors which may be of great pertinence for athletes, clubs and even SGBs themselves. The speed at which the sports industry moves makes swift dispute resolution vital for both participants and SGBs,Footnote 250 so the availability of JR would be of real significance.

Of course, there are ways to expedite private law proceedings. CPR changes have permanently established Shorter and Flexible Trials schemes,Footnote 251 allowing for a “simplified” procedure which can offer dispute resolution “on a commercial timescale”.Footnote 252 These might well be appealing to sporting claimants, but importantly only apply if the parties mutually agree. Thus, procedure could be used as a negotiating tool by defendant SGBs in order to draw out proceedings and deter litigation. There is no such opportunity for manipulation in JR. Part 8 CPR proceedings might be more appealing, as they allow for a procedure similar to JR where there is no dispute of fact. However, a defendant can still object to its use,Footnote 253 and the starting point remains that evidence will be heard orally and that any preliminary ruling on written evidence will be temporary.Footnote 254

Of course, interim injunctions and declarations can be obtained in private law under Part 25 CPR, which offers swift protection where appropriate. However, such interim determinations tend to favour claimants, while SGBs typically fare better at trial.Footnote 255 It is also unclear whether interim measures are available in the supervisory jurisdiction.Footnote 256 A streamlined process of JR would avoid any such inconsistencies, allowing for swift and, most importantly, final dispute resolution.

4.2.2 Standing

Secondly, JR’s broad test of standingFootnote 257 may be of importance in the sports context. In private law, the only person entitled to sue is the person whose right has been infringed.Footnote 258 In public law, by contrast, a court will likely allow any applicant to proceed where they have a strong prospect of succeeding on the merits.Footnote 259

As noted in Part 3, there is a huge public interest in sport. Thus, there is a strong argument for allowing challenges to SGBs to be made not only by the participants whose rights have been affected, but also interested parties more generally. Clubs are backed by passionate fans, athletes are represented by unions,Footnote 260 and both are often supported commercially. In cases where athletes or clubs cannot afford, or choose not to mount a legal challenge, such groups may wish to. This was the central issue in Finnigan v NZRFU where individuals not in a contractual relationship with the SGB were held to have standing, paving the way for JR of SGBs in New Zealand. These groups can be considered to have an interest in SGB decisions and would be best placed to vindicate that through JR.

4.2.3 Time limits

Finally, it is worth commenting on the 3-month limitation period in JR.Footnote 261 This short time limit would be no object in the sports context, as urgency is invariably essentialFootnote 262 due to the fast-moving nature of the industry. Indeed, where it is a sporting suspension being challenged, claims will need to be made almost immediately.

4.2.4 Procedural assessment

Given the foregoing, it is submitted that private law remedies will not always be adequate for challenging SGBs. The more straightforward procedural requirements of JR are particularly well suited to the sports sector, where disputes “arise at short notice…[and] where the swiftness of the court’s ruling is as important as the result itself”Footnote 263 and where interested parties might not have private law standing. JR can provide a final ruling within weeks or even days of the challenged decision.Footnote 264 JR is arguably the “preferable vehicle” for sports dispute resolution.Footnote 265

However, it must be acknowledged that it is a scarce resource. Unlike claims in private law, which can in theory be presented in any county court, there are only five administrative courts to handle JR claims nation-wide. As such, delays are common, somewhat offsetting the procedural advantages. Nonetheless, the lower-cost and conclusive nature of JR remains significant, and applications can be heard more swiftly in urgent cases.Footnote 266 In the situation where an SGB makes an unlawful decision late one evening prohibiting an individual from competing the following morning, JR could provide an effective remedy.

4.3 Arbitration

The role of private law in sport cannot be adequately considered without mention of arbitration. The past two decades have seen arbitration emerge as the primary means of dispute resolution for many SGBs and, certainly, for doping disputes. As such, it might be thought that the role JR would play would be merely residual and that arbitration clauses will pose an insurmountable hurdle to any challenge in the ordinary courts, in private or public law.Footnote 267 This may be true in some cases, but it does not preclude the need for JR.

Firstly, not all SGBs use arbitration. For example, the RFU and, indeed, World Rugby (rugby union’s international governing body, which is governed by English lawFootnote 268) make no provision for arbitration outside of anti-doping, while British Cycling provides for it on a purely voluntary basis. As such, there will remain circumstances in which arbitration is irrelevant, and the ordinary courts’ jurisdiction will be the only forum for challenges to SGBs.

Secondly, the validity of “forced arbitration” clauses contained in SGB regulations has been cast into doubt by the ECtHR decision in Mutu and Pechstein,Footnote 269 which recognised the lack of genuine consent by participants to SGB regulations. This reinforces the analysis in Part 3.1.1 with regard to the artificiality of the contract deemed to exist between participants and SGBs and may lay the foundation for a future challenge to the validity of SGB arbitration clauses in English law. Moreover, it is suggested that, if JR of SGBs is accepted, the administrative courts might be more willing to find arbitration clauses invalid, owing to their approach to ouster clauses.Footnote 270

Arbitration has and will continue to have a significant role to play in sports dispute resolution, and there are many good reasons for that. However, it is argued that it does not do away with the need for, nor does it preclude, JR.

4.4 Overall assessment

In sum, it is argued that the availability of private law remedies should not preclude claims for JR, as they are not necessarily adequate, substantively or procedurally. Allowing JR of SGBs would bring the advantages of both coherence and speed.Footnote 271 The choice of remedy should be at the discretion of the claimant whose rights have been infringed.

5 Conclusion

On the basis of the foregoing analysis, it is argued that regulatory decisions of SGBs should be subject to JR. The reasoning of the decision in Aga Khan suffers from a number of fatal flaws undermining its authority. Its reasoning on the consensual relationship between participants and SGBs is highly unsatisfactory, and its emphasis on the source of the power is inappropriate. The exclusion of SGBs from the scope of JR is also out of line with other jurisdictions as well as English authorities on other self-regulatory organisations. Most significantly, since the early 1990s, government involvement in sport has grown inexorably such that SGBs’ public function can now be straightforwardly established. In 1991, Rose J considered that allowing JR of SGBs would be “a quantum leap”.Footnote 272 In 2019, continuing to deny JR of SGBs would be a categorical mistake.

Of course, there will still be sports cases that can be dealt with in private law, and it is not suggested that JR be used exclusively. However, the availability of private law remedies should not preclude JR, particularly as it will often offer a more appealing remedy, and, if an application is brought properly, there is no reason for it to be denied. New Zealand’s approach should be followed.

Finally, the analysis in Part 4.1 demonstrates the substantive overlap between the traditionally conceived fields of public and private law. The position of SGBs, and their more recent treatment by English courts, supports the viewFootnote 273 that any substantive divide between the two spheres is not strict. The principal divide appears procedural. Though this, too, has been softened, significant procedural distinctions do exist and, for as long as that remains the case, sporting claimants should be able to challenge SGBs in both jurisdictions.