Skip to main content
Log in

Unexpected quantum indeterminacy

  • Paper in Philosophy of the Natural Sciences
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent philosophical discussions about metaphysical indeterminacy have been substantiated with the idea that quantum mechanics, one of the most successful physical theories in the history of science, provides explicit instances of worldly indefiniteness. Against this background, several philosophers underline that there are alternative formulations of quantum theory in which such indeterminacy has no room and plays no role. A typical example is Bohmian mechanics in virtue of its clear particle ontology. Contrary to these latter claims, this paper aims at showing that different pilot-wave theories do in fact instantiate diverse forms of metaphysical indeterminacy. Namely, I argue that there are various questions about worldly states of affairs that cannot be determined by looking exclusively at their ontologies and dynamical laws. Moreover, it will be claimed that Bohmian mechanics generates a new form of modal indeterminacy. Finally, it will be concluded that ontological clarity and indeterminacy are not mutually exclusive, i.e., the two can coexist in the same theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the sake of simplicity, in this paper I will use “indeterminacy” and “indefiniteness” as synonyms. Although not technically precise, this will not cause issues for the proposed arguments. For details cf. Torza (2023) p. 1.

  2. PO theories are usually embedded within a spacetime structure which is taken to be a real substance. Relationalist reconstructions of PO theories have been proposed in Vassallo (2015) and Vassallo et al. (2017).

  3. For space reasons, in this essay I will focus exclusively on Bohmian mechanics. For a discussion of MI within GRW theories the reader may refer to Mariani (2022).

  4. Lewis (2022) seems to endorse such conditions. I thank Referee 2 for pointing this out.

  5. Such conditions can be trivially extended to any other property. Indeed, Lewis proposes also an example involving the energy of Bohmian particles, cf. Lewis (2016), p. 103.

  6. The example of classical macroscopic objects is obvious but useful: although we know that they are ontologically reduced to their microscopic constituents, we believe that objects like tables, chairs, mountains etc., do exist in the world. In this case reduction does not amount to elimination, but it is conservative.

  7. Cf. Mariani, 2021, Section 3 for a more detailed argument.

  8. This view about spin has been employed by the present author in Oldofredi (2020a) to show that BM as defined in Dürr et al. (2013) generates a distributive lattice of propositions. Although that essay draws a conclusion valid for the mentioned account of BM, it does not necessarily reflect my current opinion concerning the status and role of spin in pilot-wave theory.

  9. It is worth noting that interpreting spin as a real attribute of the Bohmian particles does not automatically entail indeterminacy as shown in Dewdney et al. (1987). Moreover, Lewis suggests ways to escape indeterminacy in Bohm’s approach, as for instance employing retrocausality. It is outside the scope of the present paper to analyze the latter proposal.

  10. For a recent discussion of Bohmian models with spin and their application to quantum chemistry cf. Lombardi and Fortin (2024).

  11. More on this issue in the next section.

  12. To this specific regard, it should be underlined that Deutsch (1996) and Brown and Wallace (2005) argued that Bohmian hidden parameters are explanatorily irrelevant and thus the casual approach could have been reduced to a many worlds interpretation in denial. However, Lewis (2007) and Valentini (2010) convincingly answered these objections against the pilot-wave theory. I will not consider this discussion in what follows being not strictly relevant to my argument.

  13. In Bohm and Hiley (1993) the authors seem to realize that a full-fledged realist interpretation of \(\psi \) as a physical field may entail the presence of indeterminacy. Indeed, in their joint work they proposed a new interpretation of the wave function as a carrier of information. The selected wave packet then contains what the authors call “active” information—that is actually guiding and determining the motion of the particle—whereas the empty packets represent only inactive or potential information that can be neglected, playing no dynamical role for the particles’ trajectories. In this manner there are no real empty waves spreading and interacting in space.

  14. Repetita iuvant: In this paper my aim is to defend this argument from common objections, not to show that is necessarily valid. Clearly, one may reject one or more assumptions contained in Lewis’ arguments, as for instance the branch-relative fuzzy or the branch-relative vague links.

  15. Contrary to Bohm’s theory, in BM the wave function has a nomological character in the sense specified by Goldstein and Zanghì (2013). Thus, it is not considered physically real as well as the quantum potential, which loses its status of genuine quantum force.

  16. As the authors remark, they do not question the uniqueness of solutions for a given velocity field.

  17. It is worth noting that Deotto and Ghirardi (1998) discuss which formal requirements must be imposed to \(v^{\psi }_{A_k}(Q)\) in order to guarantee the existence of trajectories and the validity of the continuity equation. These technical details, however, are not needed for the purpose of the present discussion.

  18. Cf. Fankhauser and Dürr, 2021, p. 18 for similar views.

  19. One may certainly reply that such indeterminacy is only representational, claiming that it affects how BM represents reality but not reality per se. This criticism, however, would apply to any account of quantum indeterminacy because each of them seems to rest on the following implicit premise: if QM were the correct description of the microphysical world, then from its formalism, theorems, etc., one can derive the presence of various forms of indeterminacy, e.g. indeterminacy of identity and/or indeterminacy of observables. Moreover, it is usually argued, given that QI is neither semantic, nor epistemic, then it must be metaphysical. Trivially, without such an implicit assumption, i.e. rejecting the hypothesis that QM provides an approximately true representation of reality, no account of QI would be metaphysically salient (cf. Skow, 2010). The same reasoning applies in the case of Bohmian mechanics.

  20. This equation has been derived in Nikolić (2006). It is important to mention that Eq. 12 is equivariant if and only if we have probability distributions on \(\mathbb {R}^{4N}\) with density \(|\psi |^2\).

  21. This fact will be analyzed in more detail in Section 4.

  22. For a discussion of Nikolić’s perspective in the context of Bohmian quantum field theory cf. Oldofredi (2020).

  23. Bell’s original model introduces a discrete lattice to model spacetime, the beables of this framework are fermion number densities defined at each node of the lattice.

  24. If one takes into consideration only a single species of particles, e.g. the electrons, the configuration space is

    $$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {Q}=\bigcup _{N=0}^\infty \mathcal {Q}^{[N]}_{e^-}, \end{aligned}$$

    where \(\mathcal {Q}^{[N]}=\mathbb {R}^{3N}/\text {permutations}\). Describing more than a single particle species, the total configuration space is the Cartesian product of the involved particle sectors. The example proposed by the authors is the configuration space of Quantum Electro-Dynamics, which involves three different species of particles: electrons, positions and photons.

  25. Notably, although there are many possible choices in order to describe the jump rates, the authors provide a rigorous proof concerning the existence of a unique “minimal” jump rate, in the sense that at any time t only one between these two jumps \(q_1 \rightarrow q_2\) and \(q_2 \rightarrow q_1\) is allowed.

  26. The results on the global existence, coherence and uniqueness of the jump rates in BTQFT can be found in Dürr et al. (2005) and Tumulka and Georgii (2005). In the former essay it has been shown that if the particle configuration \(Q(t_0)\) is chosen randomly with distribution \(|\Psi (t_0)|^2\), then at any later time t it will be distributed with density \(|\Psi (t)|^2\). This result is the extension of equivariance in the context of regularized QFT.

  27. Here we do not want to conflate indeterminism with indeterminacy, which are logically distinct notions. However, it is our aim to show that there exist connections between the two.

  28. It is outside the scope of the present paper to study whether multiple forms of indeterminacy coexist in the same pilot-wave theory. For instance, we can safely conclude that the indeterminacy of BTQFT cannot be extended to the other Bohmian frameworks analyzed here, as well as one may similarly claim that the sort of indeterminacy present in Nikolić’s QFT is not to be found either. More interesting and complex are the cases involving the reality of spin and modal indeterminacy. To see whether the latter applies to other Bohmian theories and whether spin generates indeterminacy also in BM and its extensions to QFT will be left for future research.

References

  • Allori, V. (2013). Primitive ontology and the structure of fundamental physical theories. In D. Z. Albert & A. Ney (Eds.), The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics, chapter 2 (pp. 58–75). Oxford University Press.

  • Barnes, E., & Cameron, R. (2011). Back to the open future. Philosophical Perspectives, 25, 1–26.

  • Bell, J. S. (1975). The theory of local beables. TH 2053-CERN.

  • Bell, J. S. (1982). On the impossible pilot wave. Foundations of Physics, 12(10), 989–999.

  • Bell, J. S. (1986). Beables for quantum field theory. Physics Reports, 137, 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1987). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952a). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden’’ variables. I. Physical Review, 85(2), 166–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. II. Physical Review, 85(2), 180–193.

  • Bohm, D. (1953). Comments on an article of takabayasi concerning the formulation of quantum mechanics with classical pictures. Progress of Theoretical Physics, 9(3), 273–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D., & Hiley, B. (1993). The undivided universe: An ontological interpretation of quantum theory. Routledge.

  • Bohm, D., & Schiller, R. (1955). A causal interpretation of the Pauli equation (B). Il Nuovo Cimento, 1, 67–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D., Schiller, R., & Tiomno, J. (1955). A causal interpretation of the Pauli equation (A). Il Nuovo Cimento, 1, 48–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2014). Metaphysical indeterminacy, properties, and quantum theory. Res Philosophica, 91(3), 449–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricmont, J. (2016). Making Sense of Quantum Mechanics. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. R., & Wallace, D. (2005). Solving the measurement problem: De Broglie-Bohm loses out to Everett. Foundations of Physics, 35, 517–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C. (2022). Quantum modal indeterminacy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 95, 177–184.

  • Calosi, C., & Mariani, C. (2020). Quantum relational indeterminacy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 71, 158–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C., & Mariani, C. (2021). Quantum indeterminacy. Philosophy Compass, 1–15.

  • Calosi, C., & Wilson, J. (2018). Quantum metaphysical indeerminacy. Philosophical Studies, 176, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C., & Wilson, J. (2022). Metaphysical indeterminacy in the multiverse. In V. Allori (Ed.), Quantum mechanics and fundamentality. Naturalizing quantum theory between scientific realism and ontological indeterminacy (pp. 375–395). Springer, Synthese Library.

  • Chen, E. (2022). Fundamental nomic vagueness. Philosophical Review, 131(1), 1–49.

  • Colijn, C., & Vrscay, E. (2002). Spin-dependent Bohmian trajctories for hydrogen eigenstates. Physics Letters A, 300, 334–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colijn, C., & Vrscay, E. (2003). Spin-dependent Bohm trajectories for Pauli and Dirac eigenstates of hydrogen. Foundations of Physics, 16(4), 303–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Das, S., & Dürr, D. (2019). Arrival time distributions of spin 1/2 particles. Scientific Reports, 9.

  • Deotto, E., & Ghirardi, G. (1998). Bohmian mechanics revisited. Foundations of Physics, 28(1), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, D. (1996). Comment on Lockwood. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 222–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewdney, C., Holland, P., & Kyprianidis, T. (1987). A causal account of non-local Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen spin correlations. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General, 20(14), 4717–4732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewdney, C., Holland, P., Kyprianidis, T., & Vigier, J. (1988). Spin and non-locality in quantum mechanics. Nature, 336, 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1947).The principles of quantum mechanics. Oxford University Press, 3rd edition.

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2004). Bohmian mechanics and quantum field theory. Physical Review Letters, 93, 090402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2005). Bell-type quantum field theories. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General, 38(4), R1–R43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2004). Quantum equilibrium and the role of operators as observables in quantum theory. Journal of Statistical Physics, 116, 959–1055.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Quantum physics without quantum philosophy. Springer.

  • Dürr, D., & Teufel, S. (2009). Bohmian mechanics: The physics and mathematics of quantum theory. Springer.

  • Esfeld, M., & Deckert, D.-A. (2017). A minimalist ontology of the natural world. Routledge.

  • Fankhauser, J., & Dürr, P. (2021). How (not) to understand weak measurements of velocities. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 85, 16–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Krause, D. (2006). Identity in physics: A historical, philosophical, and formal analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., Bradley, S., Du, H., & Smith, L. A. (2014). Laplace’s demon and the adventures of his apprentics. Philosophy of Science, 81(1), 31–59.

  • Glick, D. (2017). Against quantum indeterminacy. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 6(3), 204–213.

  • Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2012). The quantum formalism and the GRW formalism. Journal of Statistical Physics, 149(1), 142–201.

  • Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Reality and the role of the wave function in quantum theory. In D. Z. Albert & A. Ney (Eds.), The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics, chapter 4 (pp. 91–109). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, L. (1992). On the existence of empty waves in quantum theory. Physics Letters A, 167, 11–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. (1993). The quantum theory of motion. An account of the de broglie-bohm causal interpretation of quantum mechanics: Cambridge University Press.

  • Holland, P. (2015). The roads not taken: empty waves, wave function collapse and protective measurement in quantum theory. In S. Gao (Ed.), Protective measurements and quantum reality: Towards a new understanding of quantum mechanics (pp. 145–163). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hossenfelder, S. (2018). Lost in math: How beauty leads physics astray. Basic Books.

  • Hossenfelder, S. (2021). Screams for explanation: Fine-tuning and naturalness in the foundations of physics. Synthese, 198, 3727–3745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P. S. (1814). A philosophical essay on probabilities. Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2022). Explicating quantum indeterminacy. In V. Allori (Ed.), Quantum mechanics and fundamentality. Naturalizing quantum theory between scientific realism and ontological indeterminacy (pp 351–363). Springer, Synthese Library.

  • Lewis, P. J. (2007). Empty waves in bohmian quantum mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 787–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. J. (2016). Quantum ontology. A guide to the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford University Press.

  • Lombardi, O., & Fortin, S. (2024). Bohmian mechanics for quantum chemistry. In A. Oldofredi (Ed.), Guiding waves in quantum mechanics: 100 Years of de broglie-bohm pilot-wave theory. Oxford University Press (Forthcoming).

  • Mariani, C. (2021). Emergent quantum indeterminacy. Ratio, 34, 183–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mariani, C. (2022). Does the primitive ontology of GRW rest on shaky ground? In V. Allori (Ed.), Quantum mechanics and fundamentality. Naturalizing quantum theory between scientific realism and ontological indeterminacy (pp. 127–139). Springer, Synthese Library.

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nikolić, H. (2006). Relativistic bohmian interpretation of quantum mechanics. AIP Conference Proceedings, 844.

  • Nikolić, H. (2010). QFT as pilot-wave theory of particle creation and destruction. International Journal of Modern Physics A, 25(7), 1477–1505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oldofredi, A. (2020a). Classical logic in the quantum context. Quantum Reports, 2(4), 606–616.

  • Oldofredi, A. (2020). Stochasticity and Bell-type quantum field theory. Synthese, 197, 731–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, K. (2023). Derivative indeterminacy. Erkenntnis.

  • Schrödinger, E. (1935). Die gegenwärtige situation in der quantenmechanik. Naturwissenschaften, 23(48), 807–812.

  • Skow, B. (2010). Deep metaphysical indeterminacy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 60(241), 851–858.

  • Timko, J., & Vrscay, E. (2009). Spin-dependent Bohmian electronic trajctories for helium. Foundations of Physics, 39, 1055–1071.

  • Torza, A. (2022). Derivative metaphysical indeterminacy and quantum physics. In V. Allori (Ed.), Quantum mechanics and fundamentality. Naturalizing quantum theory between scientific realism and ontological indeterminacy. Springer, Synthese Library.

  • Torza, A. (2023). Indeterminacy in the world. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tumulka, R., & Georgii, H.-O. (2005). Some jumps processes in quantum field theory. In J. D. Dueschel & A. Greven (Eds.), Interacting Stochastic Systems. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, A. (2010). De Broglie-Bohm pilot-wave theory: Many wordls in denial? In S. Saunders, J. Barrett, A. Kent, & D. Wallace (Eds.), Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory, and reality (pp. 476–509). Oxford University Press.

  • van Riel, R., & Gulick, R. (2019). Reductionism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Vassallo, A. (2015). Can Bohmian mechanics be made background independent? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52, 242–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vassallo, A., Deckert, D.-A., & Esfeld, M. (2017). Relationalism about mechanics based on a minimalist ontology of matter. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7, 299–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2023). Determinable and determinates. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I warmly thank the Editor of this Special Issue Cristian Mariani for the useful conversations about this paper. I have to thank Antonio Vassallo for his valuable remarks on the nature of empty waves in pilot-wave theory and Olga Sarno for helpful comments on previous draft of the paper. Moreover, my gratitude goes to the two anonymous referees, their constructive criticisms and suggestions greatly improved the present essay. Finally, I am grateful to the Fundaç\(\tilde{\textrm{a}}\)o para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (FCT) for financial support (Grant no. 2020.02858.CEECIND).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Oldofredi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Accepted for publication in the European Journal for Philosophy of Science.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Oldofredi, A. Unexpected quantum indeterminacy. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 14, 15 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00574-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00574-9

Keywords

Navigation