Skip to main content
Log in

Does the counterfactual theory of explanation apply to non-causal explanations in metaphysics?

  • Original Paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the recent philosophy of explanation, a growing attention to and discussion of non-causal explanations has emerged, as there seem to be compelling examples of non-causal explanations in the sciences, in pure mathematics, and in metaphysics. I defend the claim that the counterfactual theory of explanation (CTE) captures the explanatory character of both non-causal scientific and metaphysical explanations. According to the CTE, scientific and metaphysical explanations are explanatory by virtue of revealing counterfactual dependencies between the explanandum and the explanans. I support this claim by illustrating that CTE is applicable to Euler’s explanation (an example of a non-causal scientific explanation) and Loewer’s explanation (an example of a non-causal metaphysical explanation).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This attention to non-causal explanations sometimes takes a critical tone – see, for instance, Bueno and French (2012); Skow (2014), and Strevens (forthcoming). However, it is not the goal of this paper to discuss the critics of (certain kinds of) non-causal explanations.

  2. Explanations based on network models are promising, though controversial, candidates for non-causal explanations in the life and social sciences (Strogatz 1994; Barabasi et al. 2006; Huneman 2010).

  3. Note that grounding need not be restricted to facts. It can be extended to other kinds of entities (see Fine 2001, 2012; Schaffer 2009).

  4. See Lange (2009b) for a related account.

  5. One alternative option to monism is causal reductionism, i.e. the view that seemingly non-causal explanations can ultimately be understood as causal explanations. Lewis (1986) and Skow (2014) have presented the most compelling attempt to spell out this strategy. Lewis and Skow rely on the notion of providing information about the causal history of the explanandum. Their notion of ‘causal information’ is significantly broader, and weaker, than the notion of ‘identifying the causes of the explanandum’ figuring in the causal accounts I have referred to earlier. For instance, Lewis and Skow hold that one explains causally by merely excluding a possible causal history of some explanandum E, or by stating that E has no cause at all – while other causal accounts would not classify this sort of information as causally explanatory. I cannot enter an in-depth discussion of the merits of causal reductionism here. I take it as premise – against causal reductionism – that there actually are non-causal explanations including the examples listed above and the two examples I will discuss in Sections 3 and 4.

  6. See Kim (1974) and Ruben (2012) for related suggestions.

  7. I adopt Woodward’s (2003) terminology in calling it a counterfactual theory.

  8. It is interesting that Woodward (1979: 45–46) takes the CTE to be a charitable revision of the covering law account.

  9. I assume that a generalization supports counterfactuals only if the generalization is non-accidentally true or lawful. I use a broad notion of laws that includes non-strict ceteris paribus laws, such as Woodward and Hitckcock’s own invariance account. However, my aim here is not to defend a particular view of laws. I want to suggest instead that the CTE is neutral with respect to alternative theories of non-accidental truth or lawhood. I take this to be a strength of the CTE.

  10. One may, of course, also ask whether the proof for Euler’s theorem is an explanatory proof. However, this question changes the topic and, hence, the explanandum, because it concerns an explanation in pure mathematics (as opposed to an applied mathematical explanation). As mentioned in Section 1, I will not address this topic.

  11. Although the veridicality condition is met in the case of Euler’s explanation, one might worry that it does not hold for all scientific explanation, because (a) many scientific explanations involve idealized assumption, and (b) how-possibly explanations play an important epistemic role in the sciences. Both idealized and how-possibly explanations do not meet the veridicality condition. Regarding idealized explanations, it is, however, often possible to (re)interpret the idealizations in a way that is compatible with the veridicality condition by adopting, for instance, dispositionalist and minimalist accounts of idealizations (see Cartwright 1989; Hüttemann 2004; Strevens 2008). Regarding how-possibly explanations, I ultimately agree that the veridicality condition has to be rejected, if the CTE is supposed to be an account of both how-possibly and how-actually explanations. However, many prominent accounts of explanations (including Woodward’s version of the CTE) are (at least, implicitly) presented as accounts of how-actually explanations. In this vein, I also introduce the CTE as an account of how-actually explanations; this account can, of course, be weakened in the case of how-possibly explanations (see Reutlinger, A., Hangleiter, D., Hartmann, S., “Understanding (with) Toy Models”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, “forthcoming” for my approach to how-possibly explanations and toy models).

  12. It is a controversial issue whether the Humean grounding generalization (or a Humean supervenience claim) holds in all possible worlds, or only in a restricted class of worlds (see Hall 2012 for an overview).

  13. See Cohen and Callender (2009) for a version of the BSA that is not committed to fundamental (or natural) predicates.

  14. While Loewer seems to accept the grounding generalization as a key part of the explanans, there might be an alternative version of the Humean metaphysical explanation of laws that does not rely on grounding. This version is inspired by the Canberra plan. According to the Canberra plan version, the explanans consists of the following assumptions: (1) Conceptual analysis: A general statement l is a law in world w iff l is a theorem or axiom of the best system of w. (2) Empirical fact: The mosaic of a world w is such that l is an axiom or theorem of the best system of w. Assumptions (1) and (2) entail the explanandum: (3) Statement l is a law in w. The crucial point here is that the CTE also captures the Canberra plan version of the Humean explanation of laws. Most importantly, the decisive counterfactual is true in Loewer’s version and in the Canberra plan version; see below.

  15. See footnote 11 regarding two qualifications with respect to the veridicality condition in the context of scientific explanations.

  16. At first glance, the same problem appears to arise in the context of dispositional essentialism about laws. According to dispositional essentialism, the nomic essence of some property P grounds the regularities involving instantiation of P in a world (see, for instance, Bird 2007). A proponent of the CTE might be tempted to cash out the explanatory content of this grounding claim in terms of the counterfactual “if P had a non-actual nomic essence, then regularities would be different than they actually are”. According to dispositional essentialism, this antecedent is metaphysically impossible. However, a dispositional essentialist is certainly not committed to this prima facie problematic counterfactual within the CTE framework. A much more plausible and more useful counterfactual is this one: ‘if some non-actual ‘alien’ property P* with a different nomic essence than P’s nomic essence were instantiated (rather than P) in a world w, then the regularities in w would be different than the actual regularities'. The antecedent of this conditional is not impossible and suffices to spell out the explanatory content of the grounding claim that the dispositional essentialist makes.

  17. I believe the very same problem arises in the context of explanations in pure mathematics, where the assumptions in the explanans seem to include necessary truths. It is an open research questions for me whether the CTE applies to explanations in pure mathematics or whether the CTE needs to be supplemented by an alternative theory of explanations in pure mathematics.

  18. One reason for choosing a non-interventionist counterfactual account of causation is that Woodward’s critics have recently argued that interventionist counterfactuals are inherently problematic and ultimately dispensable for understanding causation and causal explanation (see Strevens 2008; Reutlinger 2013).

  19. In Reutlinger 2013, I provide an in-depth discussion of non-interventionist counterfactuals and their semantics.

  20. I would like to thank a referee for urging me to address this point.

  21. This claim is not necessarily at odds with recent attempts to justify the claim that some non-causal explanations do in fact display an asymmetry (see Lange 2011; Jansson forthcoming).

References

  • Achinstein, P. (1983). The nature of explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barabasi, A., Newman, M., & Watts, D. (2006). The structure and dynamics of networks. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2000). Multiple Realizability and universality. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 51, 115–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2002). The devil in the details. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (1993). Discovering complexity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2008). Can classical structures explain quantum phenomena? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(2), 217–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & French, S. (2012). Can mathematics explain physical phenomena? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 85–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correira, F., & Schnieder, B. (Eds.) (2012a). Metaphysical grounding: understanding the structure of reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correira, F. and B. Schnieder (2012b): Grounding: An Opinionated Introduction, In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the structure of reality, Correira, F. and B. Schnieder (eds.), pp. 1–36, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Earman, J., & Roberts, J. (2005). Contact with the nomic. A challenge for deniers of Humean supervenience about Laws of nature part II: the epistemological argument for Humean supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXI, 253–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (1998): Theories, models, and explanation, Dissertation, UC Berkeley.

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2007) “Bounded Rationality”, Philosophy Compass 2: 534–563.

  • Hall, N. (2012): David Lewis’s Metaphysics, In Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2012 Edition), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/lewis-metaphysics/>.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2010). Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese, 177, 213–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A. (2004). What’s wrong with Microphysicalism? London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansson, L. (forthcoming): Explanatory Asymmetries: Laws of Nature Rehabilitated, Journal of Philosophy.

  • Kim, J. (1974). Noncausal connections. Noûs, 8(1), 41–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kistler, M. (2013). The interventionist account of causation and non-causal association Laws. Erkenntnis, 78, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). The nature of mathematical knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 13, Scientific Explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009a). Dimensional explanations. Noûs, 43, 742–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009b): Why do the Laws Explain Why?, In T. Handfield (ed.) Dispositions and Causes, pp. 286–321, New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Lange, M. (2011). Conservation Laws in scientific explanations: constraints or coincidences? Philosophy of Science, 78, 333–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2013a). What makes a scientific explanation distinctively mathematical? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 485–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2013b). Really statistical explanations and genetic drift. Philosophy of Science, 80, 169–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2014). Aspects of Mathematical Explanation: Symmetry, Unity, and Salience. Philosophical Review, 123.4(2014), 485–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Causal Explanation. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers Vol. II (pp. 214–240). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology (pp. 224–247). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2004). Causation as influence. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 75–106). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (Second ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2001). Determinism and chance. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32, 609–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2008). Why there is anything except physics. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being Reduced. New essays on reduction, explanation, and causation (pp. 149–163). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of Laws and Time. Philosophical Studies, 160, 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about Mechamisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2008). Mathematical explanation: why it matters. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), The philosophy of mathematical practice (pp. 134–150). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2011): Explanation in Mathematics, In Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/mathematics-explanation/>

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P., & Price, H. (1993). Causation as a secondary quality. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 44, 187–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pexton, M. (2014). How dimensional analysis can explain. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0401-x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2015). Abstract explanations in science. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 66, 857–882.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger, A. (2013). A Theory of Causation in the Biological and Social Sciences. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 109–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D., Ladyman, J., & Kincaid, H. (2013). Scientific metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruben, D.-H. (2012). Explaining explanation. Boulder: Paradigm Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912/13). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26.

  • Saatsi, J. (2016). The Geometry of Motion. British Journal for Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axw007.

  • Saatsi, J., & Pexton, M. (2013). Reassessing Woodward’s account of explanation: regularities, counterfactuals, and non-causal explanations. Philosophy of Science, 80, 613–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2015). Grounding in the image of causation. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-014-0438-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2011). A logic for ‘because’. Review of Symbolic Logic, 4(3), 445–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (forthcoming): The Asymmetry of ‘Because’, Grazer Philosophische Studien.

  • Skow, B. (2014). Are there non-causal explanations (of particular events)? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 445–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1978). Mathematical explanation. Philosophical Studies, 34, 135–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2007). Review of Woodward, making things happen. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(1), 233–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008): Depth. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Strevens, M. (forthcoming). The Mathematical Route to Causal Understanding. In A. Reutlinger & J. Saatsi (Eds.), Explanation Beyond Causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Strogatz, S. (1994). Nonlinear dynamics and chaos. Cambridge: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and Symmetries. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright, G. H. (1971). Explanation and understanding. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherall, J. (2011). On (some) explanations in physics. Philosophy of Science, 78, 421–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013): Simulation and Similarity , New York: Oxford University Press

  • Wilson, A. (manuscript): Metaphysical Causation.

  • Woodward, J. (1979). Scientific explanation. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 30, 41–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part I: a counterfactual account. Noûs, 37, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Hanoch Ben-Yami, Philip Goff, Siegfried Jaag, Lina Jansson, Maria Kronfeldner, Marc Lange, John T. Roberts, Juha Saatsi, and Wolfgang Schwarz as well as audiences in Budapest, Leeds, and Luxemburg for constructive comments. I am particularly grateful to Barry Loewer for many stimulating conversations (about many topics) over the past several years.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Reutlinger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Reutlinger, A. Does the counterfactual theory of explanation apply to non-causal explanations in metaphysics?. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 7, 239–256 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-016-0155-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-016-0155-z

Keywords

Navigation