Skip to main content
Log in

As Thurston says? On using quotations from famous mathematicians to make points about philosophy and education

  • Original Article
  • Published:
ZDM Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is commonplace in the educational literature on mathematical practice to argue for a general conclusion from isolated quotations from famous mathematicians. In this paper, we supply a critique of this mode of inference. We review empirical results that show the diversity and instability of mathematicians’ opinions on mathematical practice. Next, we compare mathematicians’ diverse and conflicting testimony on the nature and purpose of proof. We lay especial emphasis on the diverse responses mathematicians give to the challenges that digital technologies present to older conceptions of mathematical practice. We examine the career of one much cited and anthologised paper, WP Thurston’s ‘On Proof and Progress in Mathematics’ (1994). This paper has been multiply anthologised and cited hundreds of times in educational and philosophical argument. We contrast this paper with the views of other, equally distinguished mathematicians whose use of digital technology in mathematics paints a very different picture of mathematical practice. The interesting question is not whether mathematicians disagree—they are human so of course they do. The question is how homogenous is their mathematical practice. If there are deep differences in practice between mathematicians, then it makes little sense to use isolated quotations as indicators of how mathematics is uniformly or usually done. The paper ends with reflections on the usefulness of quotations from research mathematicians for mathematical education.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As one referee pointed out, here we see philosophers (rather than mathematicians or educationalists) assuming that practice is homogenous. It does not matter for our argument who it was who provoked the psychologists we cite to test the homogeneity hypothesis empirically. All that matters for our purpose are the methods and the results of the experiments.

  2. One computer scientist did say that he suspected that the number of proofs from graph theory in this book was evidence of a campaign by graph theorists to advance their sub-discipline, but even he did not complain that the proofs selected are too ugly to deserve selection (private communication).

  3. The locus classicus is Bolzano 1817. In the twentieth century, the view that diagrams have no place in proofs is associated with Bourbaki (see Brown 1999 p. 172). Littlewood, presenting himself as resisting the trend, complains that his students “will not use pictures” and blames this on “heavy warnings” intended to break students from school mathematics (Littlewood 1953 p.36). Moreover, the rejection of diagrams in proofs is a consequence of the view that the inferences in a mathematical proof should be purely logical, that is, make no reference to specific subject matter. An inference that depends crucially on a diagram obviously violates that rule. This view has its origins in the work of Pasch, Frege and Hilbert. For a recent expression, see Hales 2012 p. x.

  4. Manders used the terms ‘exact’ and ‘co-exact’. ‘Metrical’ and ‘non-metrical’ are the terms used by Zhen et al., and by Weber and Mejia-Ramos. Since we discuss their argument, we use their terms rather than Manders’.

  5. Hume (1888), Book I, PART IV. of the sceptical and other systems of philosophy. Section 1. Of scepticism with regard to reason.

  6. Matthew Inglis has argued that this objection is not as reasonable as it sounds, because in shifting from cognitive science to ethnography, we are changing the object of study. “’Mathematical practice’ can be interpreted from an individualist cognitive perspective or an individualist social psychological perspective, or a sociological perspective (roughly speaking I’d say that the difference between the latter two is that the object of study for a social psychologist is the individual in a social setting, whereas the object of study for the sociologist is the social setting itself)… It is like a sociologist saying, ‘cognitive experiments don’t consider social factors’ or a cognitivist saying ‘ethnographies don’t consider cognitive processing’. Both those statements are true, but they’re not sensible objections.” (private communication, 2018).

  7. One reviewer wondered whether, in this section, we are ourselves guilty of argument by isolated quotation. We do not think so, because we do not take these mathematicians to speak for the whole of mathematics, and besides the argument of this section appeals to a change in mathematical practice. The mathematicians we cite here are doing mathematics differently, and that is what breaks up the homogeneity of current practice.

References

  • Aigner, M., & Ziegler, G. (2000). Proofs from the book (2nd ed.). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atiyah, M., et al. (1994). Responses to “Theoretical Mathematics”: Towards a cultural synthesis of mathematics and theoretical physics, by A. Jaffe and F. Quinn. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 30(2), 178–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avigad, J. (2018). The mechanization of mathematics. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 65(06), 681–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avigad, J., & Harrison, J. (2014). Formally verified mathematics. Communications of the ACM, 57(4), 66–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Awoday, S. (2010). Category theory (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwell, R., & Abtahi, Y. (2017). Mathematics concepts in the news. In E. de Freitas, N. Sinclair, & A. Coles (Eds.), What is a mathematical concept? (pp. 175–188). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, B. (1817). Purely analytic proof of the theorem that between any two values which give results of opposite sign there lies at least one real root of the equation. In W. Ewald (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert. A source book in the foundations of mathematics, vol. 1 (pp. 225–248). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (1999 and 2005). Philosophy of mathematics: The world of proofs and pictures. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bundy, A. (1991). A science of reasoning. In J. L. Lassez & G. Plotkin (Eds.), Computational logic: Essays in honor of Alan Robinson (pp. 178–198). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bundy, A. (2011). Automated theorem provers: A practical tool for the working mathematician? Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 61(1), 3–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bundy, A. (2013). The interaction of representation and reasoning. Proceedings of the Royal Society A Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 469(2157), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci, C. (2015). Mathematical beauty, understanding, and discovery. Foundations of Science, 20(4), 339–355. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9378-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Villiers, M. (1990). The role and function of proof in mathematics. Pythagoras, 24, 17–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ewald, W. (Ed.). (1996). From Kant to Hilbert. A source book in the foundations of mathematics, Volumes 1 and 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganesalingam, M., & Gowers, W. T. (2017). A fully automatic theorem prover with human-style output. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 58, 253–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geist, C., Löwe, B., & Van Kerkhove, B. (2010). Peer review and testimony in mathematics. In B. Löwe & T. Müller (Eds.), Philosophy of mathematics: Sociological aspects and mathematical practice (pp. 155–178). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, L. R. (1981). Language and individual differences: The search for universals in personality lexicons. In B. Wheeler (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology (pp. 141–165). Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hales, T. (2008). Formal proof. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 55(11), 1370–1380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hales, T. (2012). Dense sphere packings: A blueprint for formal proof. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G. (1989). More than formal proof. For the Learning of Mathematics, 9(1), 20–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G. (1995). Challenges to the importance of proof. For the Learning of Mathematics, 15(3), 42–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G., & Winchester, I. (Eds.). (1990). Creativity, thought and mathematical proof. Toronto: Ontario Institute for Studies in Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, J. (2008). Formal proof—theory and practice. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 55(11), 1395–1406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersh, R. (Ed.). (2006). 18 unconventional essays on the nature of mathematics. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1888). In L. A. Selby-Bigge (Ed.), A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Inglis, M., Mejia-Ramos, J. P., Weber, K., & Alcock, L. (2013). On mathematicians' different standards when evaluating elementary proofs. Topics in Cognitive Science, 5(2), 270–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglis, M., & Mejia-Ramos, J. P. (2009). The effect of authority on the persuasiveness of mathematical arguments. Cognition and Instruction, 27(1), 25–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglis, M., & Aberdein, A. (2015). Beauty is not simplicity: An analysis of mathematicians' proof appraisals. Philosophia Mathematica, 23(1), 87–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglis, M., & Aberdein, A. (2016). Diversity in proof appraisal. In B. Larvor (Ed.), Mathematical cultures: The London meetings 2012–2014 (pp. 163–179). Basel: Birkhäuser Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglis, M., & Aberdein, A. (Eds.). (2019). Advances in experimental philosophy of logic and mathematics. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglis, M., & Aberdein, A. (2020) Testing hypotheses about mathematical practice: Are aesthetic judgments in mathematics purely aesthetic? (forthcoming).

  • Jaffe, A., & Quinn, F. (1993). “Theoretical mathematics'': Toward a cultural synthesis of mathematics and theoretical physics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 29(1), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klarreich, E. (2018). Titans of mathematics clash over epic proof of ABC conjecture. Quanta Magazine. https://www.quantamagazine.org/titans-of-mathematics-clash-over-epic-proof-of-abc-conjecture-20180920/. Accessed 28 Mar 2020.

  • Lang, S. (1985). The beauty of doing mathematics: Three public dialogues. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larvor, B. (2012). How to think about informal proofs. Synthese, 187(2), 715–730.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larvor, B. (2019). From Euclidean geometry to knots and nets. Synthese, 196(7), 2715–2736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Littlewood, J. E. (1956). A Mathematician’s miscellany. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manders, K. (2008a). Diagram-based geometric practice. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), The philosophy of mathematical practice (pp. 65–79). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manders, K. (2008b). The Euclidean diagram. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), The philosophy of mathematical practice (pp. 80–133). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manin, Yu. (1998). Truth, rigour, and common sense. In H. G. Dales & G. Oliveri (Eds.), Truth in mathematics (pp. 147–159). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nathanson, M. B. (2008). Desperately seeking mathematical truth. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 55(7), 773.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollatsek, H. (2018). How mathematics research journals select articles. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 65(1), 63–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. D., & Kushner, D. (1987). Explanation, independence and realism in mathematics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38, 141–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rota, G.-C. (1997). The phenomenology of mathematical beauty. Synthese, 111(2), 171–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1978). Mathematical explanation. Philosophical Studies, 34, 135–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, W. (1995). On proof and progress in mathematics. For the Learning of Mathematics, 15(1), 29–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, W. (1994). On proof and progress in mathematics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 30(2), 161–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tymoczko, T. (Ed.). (1998). New directions in the philosophy of mathematics: An anthology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voevodsky, V. (2014). The origins and motivations of univalent foundations. The Institute Letter, 8–9. https://www.ias.edu/sites/default/files/documents/publications/ILsummer14.pdf. Accessed 28 Mar 2020.

  • Weber, K., & Mejía-Ramos, J. P. (2019). An empirical study on the admissibility of graphical inferences in mathematical proofs. In M. Inglis & A. Aberdein (Eds.), Advances in experimental philosophy of logic and mathematics (pp. 123–144). London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiedijk, F. (2008). Formal proof—getting started. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 55(11), 1408–1414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhen, B., Weber, K., & Mejia-Ramos, J. P. (2016). Mathematics majors’ perceptions of the admissibility of graphical inferences in proofs. International Journal of Research in Undergraduate Mathematics Education, 2(1), 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brendan Larvor.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We are grateful to Paul Dawkins and three anonymous referees for extensive comments on drafts of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hanna, G., Larvor, B. As Thurston says? On using quotations from famous mathematicians to make points about philosophy and education. ZDM Mathematics Education 52, 1137–1147 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11858-020-01154-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11858-020-01154-w

Navigation