Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Aesthetics as a liberating force in mathematics education?

  • Original Article
  • Published:
ZDM Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article investigates different meanings associated with contemporary scholarship on the aesthetic dimension of inquiry and experience, and uses them to suggest possibilities for challenging widely held beliefs about the elitist and/or frivolous nature of aesthetic concerns in mathematics education. By relating aesthetics to emerging areas of interest in mathematics education such as affect, embodiment and enculturation, as well as to issues of power and discourse, this article argues for aesthetic awareness as a liberating, and also connective force in mathematics education.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Higginson (2006) documents some of this in relation to mathematics. Additionally, several books can now be found on the aesthetics of science It Must be Beautiful: Great Equations of Modern Science (Farmelo, 2002), Beauty and the Beast: The Aesthetic Moment in Science (Fischer, 1999) and of computing, Aesthetic Computing Fishwick (2006).

  2. Langer (1957) emphasizes this fact by describing how the merest sense-experience is a process of formulation; human beings have a tendency to organise the sensory field into groups and patterns of sense-data, to perceive forms rather than a flux of light-impressions. They promptly and unconsciously “abstract a form from each sensory experience, and use this form to conceive the experience as a whole, as a thing” p. 90. For Langer, this unconscious appreciation of forms is the primitive root of all abstraction, which in turn is the keynote of rationality; so it appears that the conditions for rationality lie deep in pure animal experience—in the human power of perceiving, in the elementary functions of eyes and ears and fingers.

  3. The physicist Freeman Dyson (1982) also distinguishes between two types of scientists, namely, the ‘unifiers’ and the ‘diversifiers,’ the former finding and cherishing symmetries, the latter enjoying the breaking of them.

  4. In this book, Lakoff and Núñez offer a very stimulating perspective on the genesis of mathematical ideas, based on their theories of embodied cognition. While many scholars (including cognitive science, mathematicians and educators) have expressed reservations about their specific claims (see, for example, Schiralli and Sinclair, 2002), variations of the ideas expressed in this book have motivated many studies in mathematics education that are relevant to an embodied perspective on aesthetics.

  5. It might be argued that journal editors play the role of the art critic in mathematics, but their work is done within a small community of mathematicians, rather than being available or addressed to those outside that community. Textbook authors also play a role similar to that of the art critic, in that they seek to organize, explain and even interpret mathematical products for an outside audience; however, they rarely actually criticize or question these products.

References

  • Albers, D., Alexanderson, G., & Reid, C. (1990). More mathematical people. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanocish, Inc.

  • Aristotle. (2000). Metaphysics. Retrieved October 22, 2000, from http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.1.i.html.

  • Arzarello, F., & Robutti, O. (2001). From body motion to algebra through graphing. In H., Chick, K., Stacey, J., Vincent, & J. Vincent (Eds.), Proceedings of the 12th ICMI study conference (pp. 33–40). Vol. 1, Australia: The University of Melbourne.

  • Bailland, B., & Bourget, H. (Eds.). (1905). Correspondance d’Hermite et de Stieltjer. 2 vols. Paris: Gauthier-Villars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgarten, A. G. (1739, 1758). Texte zur Grundlegung der Ästhetik, trans. H.R. Schweizer, Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1983.

  • Beardsley, M. C. (1982). The aesthetic point of view. Selected essays. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, A. (1991). Mathematics enculturation: a cultural perspective on mathematics education. Dortrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S. (1973). Mathematics and humanistic themes: sum considerations. Educational Theory, 23(3), 191–214. doi:10.1111/j.1741-5446.1973.tb00602.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burton, L. (2004). Mathematicians as enquirers: Learning about learning mathematics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byers, V. (2007). How mathematicians think: Using ambiguity, contradiction, and paradoxes to create mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corfield, D. (2002). Argumentation and the mathematical process. In G. Kampis, L. Kvasz, & M. Stöltzner (Eds.), Appraising lakatos: Mathematics, methodology and the man (pp. 115–138). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, L. (2001). Mathematical structures from Hilbert to Bourbaki: the evolution of an image of mathematics. In U. Bottazzini, & A. Dahan Dalmedico (Eds.), Changing images of mathematics: from the French revolution to the new millennium (pp. 167–185). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crespo, S., & Sinclair, N. (2008) What can it mean to pose a ‘good’ problem? Inviting prospective teachers to pose better problems. Journal of Mathematics Teacher Education, 11, 395–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York: HarperPerennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csiszar, A. (2003). Stylizing rigor; or, why mathematicians write so well. Configurations, 11(2), 239–268. doi:10.1353/con.2004.0018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, P. (1997). Mathematical encounters of the 2nd kind. Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Fénélon, F. (1697/1845). Oeuvres de Fénélon, Vol. 1, Paris, Firmin-Didot frères, fils et cie.

  • Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. New York: Perigree.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dissanakye, E. (1992). Homo aestheticus. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, T., & Eisenberg, T. (1986). On the aesthetics of mathematical thought. For the Learning of Mathematics, 6(1), 2–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farmelo, G. (2002). It must be beautiful: Great equations of modern science. London: Granta Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, E. (1999). Beauty and the beast: the aesthetic moment in science. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishwick, P. (2006). Aesthetic computing. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin, G. A. (2000). Affective pathways and representations in mathematical problem solving. Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 17, 209–219. doi:10.1207/S15327833MTL0203_3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. (1979). The sense of order: A study in the psychology of decorative arts. Oxford: Phaidon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G. H. (1967/1999). A Mathematician’s apology (With a Forward by C. P. Snow). New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hawkins, D. (2000). The roots of literacy. Boulder: University Press of Colorado.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginson, W. (2006). Mathematics, aesthetics and being human. In N. Sinclair, D. Pimm, & W. Higginson (Eds.), Mathematics and the aesthetic: New approaches to an ancient affinity (pp. 105–125). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstatder, D. (1997). From Euler to Ulam: Discovery and dissection of a geometric gem. In J. King & D. Schattschneider (Eds.), Geometry turned on: dynamic software in learning, teaching and research (pp. 3–14). Washington: MAA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, P. (1998). John Dewey and the lessons of art. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, N. (2007). TThe meaning of the body: Aesthetics of human understanding. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krull, W. (1930/1987). The aesthetic viewpoint in mathematics. The mathematical intelligencer, 9(1), 48–52.

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: the logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, S. (1957). Philosophy in a new key 3rd edn. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, R. (2008). Developing a culture of inquiry in an urban sixth grade classroom. Presentation at the American education research association conference. 27 March, 2008, New York.

  • Le Lionnais, F. (1948/1986). Les Grands Courants de la Pensée Mathématique. Marseille: Rivages.

  • Littlewood, J. E. (1986). The mathematician’s art at work. In B. Bollobás (Ed.), Littlewood’s miscellany. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J., Burton L., & Stacey K. 1982: Thinking mathematically. Reading: Addison-Wesley.

  • Nemirovsky, R. (2003). Three Conjectures concerning the relationship between body activity and understanding mathematics. In N. A. Pateman, B. J. Dougherty, & J. T. Zilliox (Eds.), Proceedings of PME 27, Vol. 1, pp. 103–135.

  • Núñez, R. (2004). Do real numbers really move? Language, thought, and gesture: The embodied cognitive foundations of mathematics. In F. Iida, R. Pfeifer, L. Steels, & Y. Kuniyoshi (Eds.), Embodied artificial Iitelligence (pp. 54–73). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papert, S. (1978). The mathematical unconscious. In J. Wechsler (Ed.), On aesthetics and science (pp. 105–120). Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C·S. (1908/1960). A neglected argument for the reality of God. In C. Hartshorne, & P. Weiss (Eds.), Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, (Vol. 6: Scientific metaphysics). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: W·W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1908/1956). Mathematical creation. In J. Newman (Ed.), The world of mathematics Vol. 4, (pp. 2041–2050), New York: Simon and Schuster.

  • Radford, L. (2003). Gestures, speech and the sprouting of signs. Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 5(1), 37–70. doi:10.1207/S15327833MTL0501_02.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rota, G.-C. (1997). Indiscrete thoughts. Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiralli, M. (1999). Constructive postmodernism: Toward renewal in cultural and literary studies. Westport: Bergin & Garvey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silver, E., & Metzger, W. (1989). Aesthetic influences on expert mathematical problem solving. In D. McLeod, & V. Adams (Eds.), Affect and mathematical problem solving (pp. 59–74). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, N. (2001). The aesthetic is relevant. For the Learning of Mathematics, 21(2), 25–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, N. (2002). The kissing triangles: The aesthetics of mathematical discovery. International Journal of Computers for Mathematical Learning, 7(1), 45–63. doi:10.1023/A:1016021912539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, N. (2004). The roles of the aesthetic in mathematical inquiry. Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 6(3), 261–284. doi:10.1207/s15327833mtl0603_1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, N. (2006a). Mathematics and beauty: Aesthetic approaches to teaching children. Teachers College Press.

  • Sinclair, N. (2006b). The aesthetic sensibilities of mathematicians. In N. Sinclair, D. Pimm, & W. Higginson (Eds.), Mathematics and the aesthetic: New approaches to an ancient affinity (pp. 87–104). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, N. (2008). Attending to the aesthetic in the mathematics classroom. For the Learning of Mathematics, 28(1), 29–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, N., & Pimm, D. (forthcoming). The many and the few: Mathematics, Democracy and the Aesthetic. Educational Insights.

  • Singh, S. (1997). Fermat’s enigma: the epic quest to solve the world’s greatest mathematical problem. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sfard, A. (2008). Thinking as communicating: Human development, the growth of discourses, and mathematicizing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, J. (1925/1956). Mathematics as an art. In J. Newman (Ed.), The world of mathematics, Vol. 3 (pp. 2015–2021), New York: Simon and Schuster.

  • Thurston, W. (1994). On proof and progress in mathematics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 30(2), 161–177. doi:10.1090/S0273-0979-1994-00502-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tymoczko, T. (1993). Value judgments in mathematics: can we treat mathematics as an art? In A. White (Ed.), Essays in humanistic mathematics (pp. 62–77). Washington: The Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valero, P. (2005). What has power got to do with mathematics education? In D. Chassapis (Ed.), Proceedings of the 4th dialogue on mathematics teaching issues, Vol. 1, (pp. 25–43). Thessaloniki, University of Thessaloniki.

  • von Glasersfeld, E. (1985). Radical cconstructivism: a way of knowing and learning. London: Falmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. (1947). The mathematician. In R. Heywood (Ed.), The works of the mind (pp. 180–196). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil, A. (1992). The apprenticeship of a mathematician. Trans. J. Gage. Berlin: Birkhauser.

  • Wells, D. (1990). Are these the most beautiful? The Mathematical Intelligencer, 12(3), 37–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiteley, W. (1999). The decline and rise of geometry in 20th century North America. In J. G. McLoughlin (Ed.), Canadian mathematics study group conference proceedings (pp. 7–30). St John’s: Memorial University of Newfoundland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. (1998). Consilience: the unity of knowledge. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yackel, E., & Cobb, P. (1996). Sociomathematical norms, argumentations and autonomy in mathematics. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 27, 458–477. doi:10.2307/749877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathalie Sinclair.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sinclair, N. Aesthetics as a liberating force in mathematics education?. ZDM Mathematics Education 41, 45–60 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11858-008-0132-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11858-008-0132-x

Keywords

Navigation