Skip to main content
Log in

Repeating, Not Simply Recollecting, Repetition: On Kierkegaard’s Ethical Exercises

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This essay argues for a formative, and not simply abstract, aspect to the philosophy of religion by attending to the practices of writing employed in Søren Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous work Repetition. By locating this text within an ethical tradition that focuses upon the practices that form subjects, rather than simply the formulation of a theory, its seemingly literary performances can be viewed as exercises. In particular, this text deploys and transforms the Stoic practices of self writing, in the form of keeping notebooks and letter writing, so as to cultivate capabilities. This indirect ethical instruction does not, however, lead to the formation of autonomous ethical subjects, but to the cultivation of capabilities that are only possible in the relational space of vulnerability, service and dependence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Pierre Hadot (1995) and Michel Foucault (2005) have both given voice to the manner in which ancient philosophical traditions understood philosophy as a way of life or as practices directed to the care of the self. Furthermore, both have highlighted the manner in which post-Hegelian (Foucault 2005, 28) and post-Nietzschean (Hadot 1995, 108) strands of philosophy have revived this understanding of the task of thinking. For a wide ranging review of recent studies that are oriented toward the interconnections between philosophy and everyday life, see Van Hooft (2002).

  2. Kevin Hart has highlighted the varied and active senses of theōria and its contemporary English translation, contemplation in his episodic account of the development, alienation, and return of ‘contemplation’ in European philosophical and theological thought (2009).

  3. In this and all subsequent citations of Kierkegaard’s works I will follow the standard abbreviations adopted in the International Kierkegaard Commentary and provide the page numbers from the Hong and Hong translation. The initial citation of each text will provide the year of publication.

  4. On reading as an ethical task, see Cox and Feldman (2005).

  5. Mark Dooley’s (2001) treatment of repetition in relation to responsibility is a notable exception. Jon Stewart (2003, 288–92) and George J. Stack (1977, 133–37) have also briefly considered repetition in relation to ethics. These examinations have, however, followed the aforementioned conceptual itinerary, paying little attention to medium and performance. Edward Mooney’s interpretation of Repetition stays closer to the text, but remains focused upon repetition as a concept—viewing it as a term that illuminates the limits of ethics (1998, 296–299). Daniel Greenspan, emphasizing the psychological and theatrical aspects of the pseudonymous works, suggestively locates Repetition within the ancient ‘moral-psychological tradition’ of educating the passions (2008, 242).

  6. Roberts takes two steps in this direction, while taking one step back. He both questions an overly rationalistic approach to ethics and reframes Kierkegaard’s work in terms of wisdom, while maintaining an essential divide between thought and action. Though he notes that Kierkegaard’s texts demand virtue, virtue is fostered largely on the basis of applying the correct propositions or concepts to one’s life (1998, 192, 195; 2008, 78, 92). As Greenspan observes, a number of the connections that have been drawn by recent interpreters between Kierkegaard and ancient thought (particularly Aristotelian virtue ethics) have been at the expense of the dynamic and critical character of his relationship to both conceptual thinking and antiquity (2008, 6).

  7. The connection between Kierkegaard and Foucault has rarely been explored. The primary exceptions, of which I am aware, are two essays by Paul Bové and William McDonald. The former primarily considers different texts and periods from those that are currently under examination (focusing upon Kierkegaard’s Two Ages and Foucault’s Discipline and Punish). Bové’s work is helpful, in that he notes that Kierkegaard’s work is not simply directed toward a criticism of the present order, but that ‘the maieutic functions of [Kierkegaard’s indirect communication] help to form a style…to form a “counter-ideology” or “counter-practice”’ (1992, 29). McDonald’s essay serves to situate Kierkegaard’s work within a larger trajectory of traditions that Foucault terms ‘Technologies of the Self,’ particularly as they are concerned with ‘self writing.’ Though McDonald deploys these connections to read Either/Or (1843), his essay is largely preoccupied with formulating Kierkegaard’s theory of writing and comparing it to others (McDonald 1996).

    Foucault scarcely mentioned Kierkegaard in his writings. To my knowledge he only does so twice; once contrasting his work to Hegel’s ‘with the problem of repetition and truth’ (1972, 237), and the other considering Kierkegaard’s relationship to his pseudonyms, among whom he lists ‘Constantine Constantius’ (1984, 107). The editors of the 1981–1982 Lecture course, The Hermeneutics of the Self, claim that ‘Foucault was a great reader of Kierkegaard, although he hardly ever mentions this author, who nonetheless had for him an importance as secret as it was decisive’ (2005, 32 no. 46).

  8. Arnold Davidson characterizes subjectivation as the manner in which ‘we constitute ourselves as moral subjects of our own actions’ (1994, 118).

  9. The importance of this distinction does not lie in its exhaustive description of the impossibly diverse fields of ‘contemporary ethical theory’ but in providing a heuristic opening for the ethical importance of Kierkegaard’s work.

  10. Gouwens notes that Kierkegaard’s critiques of modern social structures and philosophy are not so much theoretical disputes, as critiques of ‘reflection,’ which he defines in terms similar to Foucault’s characterization of subjectivation. Reflection indicates ‘the character or tone of one’s imaginative and affective life. It includes the ways in which people dream and project images of themselves, how they think—with or without hope—about their prospects and possibilities….It includes too how a person exercises his or her intellective capacities’ (1996, 27). See also Kierkegaard’s Two Ages (1978b, TA, 78–84).

  11. It is not until 17 pages into the book that one receives much that resembles a theoretical or conceptual account of ‘repetition.’ Even here ‘repetition’ is not so much explained as it is positioned in relation to other thinkers. Expanding the philosophical stage beyond the ancient debate between the Eleatics and Heraclitus over motion, Constantius contrasts repetition with Hegelian ‘mediation’ (R, 148, 149). This slightly conceptual aside does not last for long however, as he describes repetition with anecdotes of speakers repeating themselves (R, 150). The remainder of the ‘Report’ stages repetition in relation to Constantius’s farcical attempt to prove it through a return trip to Berlin. In the section of part two entitled ‘Repetition,’ Constantius does not write about repetition, but of his return home and turns his attention back to the story of the young man. The only mention of ‘repetition’ as such is in the concluding paragraphs of this section in which he disavows his former ‘theory’ noting that ‘repetition is too transcendent for me’ and that it should not be sought in professorial philosophical manners (R, 186). Repetition does not return until near the end, when the young man claims to have achieved it by regaining himself from the love of the girl that had kept him captive (R, 220, 221). Yet even this affirmative declaration of repetition is challenged as Constantius declares in his concluding letter to the reader, that the young man’s ‘repetition’ transformed him back into a poet, and thereby allowed him to sneak out the back door and out of life (R, 229).

  12. His account of repetition here, however, does not seem to be offered without a touch of irony as he eschews the speculative reading that would reduce his book to 1, 2, 3 (like an accounting scheme, or three moments of a dialect), but the three part explanation he offers in that very paragraph is accompanied with the letters A, B, C (R 302–03).

  13. Drawing attention back to Kierkegaard certainly does not undermine the importance of the love affair. As so many interpreters have pointed out, this text was written within the context of Kierkegaard’s own struggles with his failed engagement with Regine Olsen. Without understating the importance of Kierkegaard’s biography for this text, I would hope to avoid its reductive deployment. The emphasis upon theory (repetition) or biography (his failed engagement) has sometimes led interpreters to reinstate the ancient division between philosophy and literature and thought and life. By focusing upon the text as an exercise I hope to bring these domains closer together.

  14. By shifting attention from the young man, to Constantius, Kierkegaard and writing, the emphasis of the text is also shifted from a critique of Romanticism to ‘Stoicism.’

  15. McDonald notes a number of parallels between Stoic writing practices and elements of the first volume of Either/Or (1996, 60).

  16. This is how Arrian, the compiler of Epictetus’s Discourses, described the texts he was putting together in a prefatory letter to Lucius Gellius and the term that Plutarch used to describe his On the Tranquility of the Soul. Pierre Hadot observes that Marcus Aurelius’s Meditations should be read as hupomnemata as well (1995, 199, 178; 1998, 30–34).

  17. In a later text, The Sickness Unto Death (1849), he makes a similar reference to ‘stoicism, but understood as not referring only to the sect,’ in which it represents the subject formation of despair in defiance (1980, SUD, 86).

  18. Rick Anthony Furtak argues for the simultaneous resonance and dissonance between Kierkegaard and the Stoics, as both have an integrated understanding of thought and the emotions. He notes, however, that Kierkegaard departs from the Stoics in that he does not give a dispassionate disposition pride of place (2005, 49).

  19. Gouwens notes that virtue is ‘dethroned’ but ‘not eliminated’ for Kierkegaard, (1996, 106) as it exceeds the traditional focus upon habit and places a greater emphasis upon active resolution and receptive dependence in faith (1996, 101, 138). Furthermore, he notes that Kierkegaard’s use of virtue is not simply limited to those that are substantive, but also on a relational understanding of virtue (1996, 117). I want to take Gouwens’s reading a step further and argue that the capabilities that Repetition cultivates are fundamentally relational and dynamic. In this manner it is not so much that readers come to possess abilities, but it is only in fragile space of response and relationship—in service and dependence—that these capabilities are even possible.

  20. The difference being highlighted here between Kierkegaard’s exercises and the Stoics is not unlike that drawn by Matthew Jacoby (1999) between a post-liberal emphasis upon Christian doctrine as being directed toward right moral action and communal formation, and Kierkegaard’s emphasis upon relationship, passion and vulnerability.

  21. The upbuilding discourse on Job published two months after Repetition (December 1843) does not seem to settle this ambiguity (1990b, EUD 109–124). It too is fraught with the difficulties of indirect communication, as Jacob Bøggild has persuasively argued (112–118, 2004).

  22. The moral or ethical judgment that emerges from the ordeal does not, as John D. Caputo notes, follow the traditional model in which judgment is dictated by the application of principles (1993, 97, 106). Far from ensuring autonomy or certainty, such an ethical exercise opens out in heteronomy and difficulty.

  23. George Pattison notes the interpersonal orientation of Repetition, observing that its ‘sustaining heartbeat’ is a ‘genuine openness to the future that is at one and the same time a genuine openness to the other’ (1993, 359).

  24. Kangas notes that Repetition ‘opens a possibility; it does not explain.’ Therefore, he characterizes repetition as ‘an enablement, a power, not identical to the spontaneity of the will,’ but one which demands patience and which is less of a return than a departure (2007, 122, 124).

References

  • Bøggild, J. (2004). Revocated trials: on the indirect communication in two of Kierkegaard’s early religious discourses. In E. Jegstrup (Ed.), The New Kierkegaard (pp. 112–127). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bové, P. A. (1992). The penitentiary of reflection: Søren Kierkegaard and critical activity. In mastering discourse: The politics of intellectual culture (pp. 19–46). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, J. D. (1987). Radical hermeneutics: Repetition, deconstruction, and the hermeneutic project. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, J. D. (1993). Against ethics: Contributions to a poetics of obligation with constant reference to deconstruction. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, E., & Feldman, K. (2005). Reading by example. In G. Bertram & S. Blank (Eds.), Intersubjecktivität und Praxis (pp. 237–246). Paris: L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, A. I. (1994). Ethics as ascetics: Foucault, the history of ethics, and ancient thought. In G. Gutting (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Foucault (pp. 115–140). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dooley, M. (2001). The politics of exodus: Søren Kierkegaard’s ethics of responsibility. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1972). The Discourse on Language. In The Archeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language (pp. 215–237). New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1984). What is an author? In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault reader (pp. 101–120). New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1990). The use of pleasure. Volume 2 of the history of sexuality. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1997). Self writing. In P. Rabinow (Ed.), Ethics: Subjectivity and truth (pp. 207–222). New York: New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2005). The hermeneutics of the subject: Lectures at the college de France 1981–1982. New York: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furtak, R. A. (2005). Wisdom in Love: Kierkegaard and the Ancient Quest for Emotional Integrity. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gouwens, D. J. (1996). Kierkegaard as religious thinker. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, D. (2008). The passion of infinity: Kierkegaard, Aristotle and the rebirth of tragedy. New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1995). Philosophy as a Way of life: Spiritual exercises from Socrates to Foucault. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1998). The inner citadel: The meditations of Marcus Aurelius. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, K. (2009). Contemplation: Beyond and behind. Sophia, 48(4), 435–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacoby, M. (1999). Kierkegaard and the nature of truth. Sophia, 38(1), 74–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, M. D. (2005). Cicero, Ambrose, and Aquinas ‘on Duties’ or the limits of genre in morals. Journal of Religious Ethics, 33(3), 485–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kangas, D. J. (2007). Kierkegaard’s Instant: On beginnings. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1967). In H. V. Hong, E. H. Hong, & G. Malantschuk (Eds.), Søren Kierkegaard’s journals and papers (Vol. 1st ed.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1978a). Letters and documents. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1978b). In H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong (Eds.), Two ages: The Age of revolution and the present Age, a literary review. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1980). In H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong (Eds.), The sickness unto death. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1983). In H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong (Eds.), Fear and trembling and repetition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1990a). In J. Watkin (Ed.), Early polemical writings. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1990b). In H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong (Eds.), Eighteen upbuilding discourses. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirmmse, B. H. (Ed.) (1996). Encounters with Kierkegaard: A life as seen by his contemporaries. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Lobkowicz, N. (1967). Theory and practice: History of a concept from Aristotle to Marx. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDonald, W. (1996). Writing as a technology of the self in Kierkegaard and Foucault. Enrahonar, 25, 55–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mooney, E. (1998). Repetition: Getting the world back. In A. Hannay & G. Marino (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Kierkegaard (pp. 282–307). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nightingale, A. W. (2004). Spectacles of truth in classical Greek philosophy: Theoria in its cultural context. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pattison, G. (1993). The magic of theatre: Drama of existence in Kierkegaard’s repetition and Hesse’s Steppenwolf. In R. Perkins (Ed.), International Kierkegaard commentary, fear and trembling and repetition (pp. 359–378). Macon: Mercer University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattison, G. (2005). The philosophy of Kierkegaard. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. C. (1998). Existence, emotion, and virtue: Classical themes in Kierkegaard. In A. Hannay & G. Marino (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Kierkegaard (pp. 177–206). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. C. (2008). Kierkegaard and ethical theory. In E. Mooney (Ed.), Ethics, love, and faith in Kierkegaard (pp. 72–92). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, J. A. (2007). What about Isaac?: rereading fear and trembling and rethinking ethics. Journal of Religious Ethics, 35(2), 319–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stack, G. J. (1977). Kierkegaard’s existential ethics. University: The University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2003). Kierkegaard’s Relations to Hegel reconsidered. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Hooft, S. (2002). Philosophy and the care of the self: a literature survey. Sophia, 41(1), 89–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, S. (2004). Theatricality as medium. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank John D. Caputo, Marcia Robinson and J. Aaron Simmons for their comments on an earlier draft of this essay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to T. Wilson Dickinson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dickinson, T.W. Repeating, Not Simply Recollecting, Repetition: On Kierkegaard’s Ethical Exercises. SOPHIA 50, 657–675 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-011-0259-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-011-0259-z

Keywords

Navigation