Skip to main content
Log in

Expected return—expected loss approach to optimal portfolio investment

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Standard models of portfolio investment rely on various statistical measures of dispersion. Such measures favor returns smoothed over all states of the world and penalize abnormally low as well as abnormally high returns. A model of portfolio investment based on the tradeoff between expected return and expected loss considers only abnormally low returns as undesirable. Such a model has a comparative advantage over other existing models in that a first-order stochastically dominant portfolio always has a higher expected return and a lower expected loss. Expected return—expected loss model of portfolio investment can rationalize the equity premium puzzle. Two random variables are not comoving if there is at least one state of the world in which one random variable yields a positive return and the other—a negative return. Such random variables provide hedging benefits from diversification in portfolio investment according to the expected return—expected loss model. A special case of this model, when an investor linearly trade-offs expected returns and expected losses, is also a special case of the prospect theory when a decision-maker has a piece-wise linear value function without any probability weighting.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These are monthly changes in close prices (adjusted for dividends and splits) on the first day of the month between June 2019 and May 2020 for Tesla, Inc. (TSLA) and NVIDIA Corporation (NVDA). Data downloaded from https://finance.yahoo.com/

  2. In any state of the world si in which there is comovement (i.e. R1(si)R2(si) ≥ 0) the ratio (5) is not a well-defined share (being either negative or greater than one).

  3. The case with comoving securities that we discussed first is just a special case of this algorithm when there are no “break even” shares.

  4. These are monthly changes in close prices (adjusted for dividends and splits) on the first day of the month between June 2019 and May 2020 for Walmart Inc. (WMT) and Apple Inc. (AAPL). Data downloaded from https://finance.yahoo.com/

  5. The dashed-dotted curve on Fig. 3 has only one kink corresponding to the “break even” share of AAPL α1 = 0.187 because AAPL and TSLA are comoving in all but one state (s4).

  6. These are monthly changes in adjusted close prices between June 2019 and May 2020 for Regeneron Pharmaceuticals, Inc. (REGN). Data downloaded from https://finance.yahoo.com/.

  7. In our example, system (6) has nine other solutions that are located inside the convex hull of feasible binary portfolios and hence they cannot be fully diversified boundary portfolios.

  8. Mean-Gini approach is equivalent to Yaari (1987) dual model with a quadratic probability weighting function (Blavatskyy, 2016).

  9. This is similar to Gul (1991) theory of disappointment aversion where outcomes are disappointing if they are below a lottery’s certainty equivalent.

  10. Data (^IRX and ^IXIC) downloaded from https://finance.yahoo.com/.

References

  • Ang, A., Chen, J., & Xing, Y. (2006). Downside risk. The Review of Financial Studies, 19(1), 1191–1239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, N., Huang, M., & Santos, T. (2001). Prospect theory and asset prices. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(1), 1–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benartzi, S., & Thaler, R. (1995). Myopic loss aversion and the equity premium puzzle. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 110, 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M., & Navarrete, J. (1998). Testing descriptive utility theories: Violations of stochastic dominance and cumulative independence. Journal of Risk Uncertainty, 17, 49–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2010). Modifying the mean-variance approach to avoid violations of stochastic dominance. Management Science, 56(11), 2050–2057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2016). Probability weighting and L-moments. European Journal of Operational Research, 255(1), 103–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P., & Pogrebna, G. (2010). Models of stochastic choice and decision theories: why both are important for analyzing decisions. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 25(6), 963–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borch, K. (1969). A note on uncertainty and indifference curves. The Review of Economic Studies., 36(1), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbone, E., & Hey, J. (1995). A comparison of the estimates of EU and non-EU preference functionals using data from pairwise choice and complete ranking experiments. Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 20, 111–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coval, J. D., & Shumway, T. (2005). Do behavioral biases affect prices? The Journal of Finance, 60(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Roos, N., & Sarafidis, Y. (2010). Decision making under risk in Deal or No Deal. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 25, 987–1027.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gini, C. (1912). Variabilità e Mutabilità. contributo allo studio delle distribuzioni e delle relazione statistiche. Studi Economici-Giuridici Dela Regia Università Di Cagliari, 3, 3–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gul, F. (1991). A theory of disappointment aversion. Econometrica, 59(3), 667–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. (2001). Does repetition improve consistency? Experimental Economics, 4, 5–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J., & Richard, T. (1990). Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the coarse theorem. Journal of Political Economy, 98, 1325–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J. L. (1989). The endowment effect and evidence of nonreversible indifference curves. American Economic Review, 79, 1277–1284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konno, H., & Yamazaki, H. (1991). Mean absolute deviation portfolio optimization model and its application to Tokyo stock market. Management Science, 37, 519–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1998). Testing different stochastic specifications of risky choice. Economica, 65, 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markowitz, H. (1952). Portfolio selection. The Journal of Finance, 7, 77–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehra, R., & Prescott, E. (1985). The equity premium: A puzzle. Journal of Monetary Economics, 15, 145–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odean, T. (1998). Are investors reluctant to realize their losses? The Journal of Finance, 53(5), 1775–1798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1981). Risk perception and risk aversion among Australian farmers. Australian Journal of Agricultural Resource Economics, 25(2), 160–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3(4), 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roy, A. D. (1952). Safety first and the holding of assets. Econometrica, 20, 431–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, W., & Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Status quo bias in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 7–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shalit, H., & Yitzhaki, S. (1984). Mean-Gini. Portfolio theory. And the pricing of risky assets. The Journal of Finance, 39(5), 1449–1468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shefrin, H., & Statman, M. (1985). The disposition to sell winners too early and ride losers too long: Theory and evidence. Journal of Finance, 40, 777–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1, 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59(4), 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior (2nd ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P., Erev, I., & Weber, E. (1994). Comonotonic independence: The critical test between classical and rank-dependent utility theories. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9, 195–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaari, M. (1987). The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica, 55, 95–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yitzhaki, S. (1982). Stochastic dominance. Mean variance. And Gini’s mean difference. The American Economic Review, 72(1), 178–185.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Pavlo Blavatskyy is a member of the Entrepreneurship and Innovation Chair, which is part of LabEx Entrepreneurship (University of Montpellier, France) and funded by the French government (Labex Entreprendre, ANR-10-Labex-11-01).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pavlo Blavatskyy.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of proposition 1

For any portfolio α we denote the return of this portfolio in state of the world si as

$$ R_{i} \left( {\varvec{\alpha}} \right)\mathop = \limits^{{{\text{def}}}} \mathop \sum \limits_{j = 1}^{m} \alpha_{j} R_{j} \left( {s_{i} } \right) $$

For any two portfolios α and β let X denote the set of their possible returns:

$$ X\mathop = \limits^{{{\text{def}}}} \bigcup\limits_{i = 1}^{n} {\left\{ {R_{i} \left( {\varvec{\alpha}} \right) , R_{i} \left( {\varvec{\beta}} \right)} \right\}} $$

Let N be the number of elements in set X and let us number those elements by subscript k in the ascending order so that x1 is the minimum element and xN is the maximum element in X. Finally. We denote the cumulative distribution function of portfolio α as

$$ F_{k} \left( \alpha \right)\mathop = \limits^{{{\text{def}}}} \mathop \sum \limits_{{\begin{array}{*{20}c} {i = 1} \\ {R_{i} \left( \alpha \right) \le x_{k} } \\ \end{array} }}^{n} p\left( {s_{i} } \right) $$

If portfolio α first-order stochastically dominates portfolio β then \(F_{k} \left( {\varvec{\alpha}} \right) \le F_{k} \left( {\varvec{\beta}} \right)\) for all \(x_{k} \in X\).

Expected return (3) of portfolio α can be then written as

$$ \begin{aligned} ER\left( {\varvec{\alpha}} \right) & = \mathop \sum \limits_{j = 1}^{m} \alpha_{j} ER_{j} = \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{n} R_{i} \left( {\varvec{\alpha}} \right)p\left( {s_{i} } \right) \hfill \\ \;\;\;\;\;\;\;\;\;\;\; & = x_{N} + \mathop \sum \limits_{k = 1}^{N - 1} F_{k} \left( {\varvec{\alpha}} \right)\left[ {x_{k} - x_{k + 1} } \right] \ge x_{N} \hfill \\ \;\;\;\;\;\;\;\;\;\;\; & + \mathop \sum \limits_{k = 1}^{N - 1} F_{k} \left( {\varvec{\beta}} \right)\left[ {x_{k} - x_{k + 1} } \right] = ER\left( {\varvec{\beta}} \right) \hfill \\ \end{aligned} $$

Let X- denote the set of all losses (negative returns) in X and zero:

$$ X_{ - } \mathop = \limits^{{{\text{def}}}} \left\{ {x \in X{|}x < 0} \right\} \cup \left\{ 0 \right\} $$

Let L be the number of elements in set X-. As before. We keep the numbering in the ascending order so that x1 is the minimum element (the biggest loss) in X- and xL = 0. Expected loss of portfolio α can be then written as

$$ EL\left( \alpha \right) = - \sum _{{\mathop {i{\text{ }} = {\text{ }}1}\limits_{{R_{i} \left( \alpha \right) < 0}} }}^{n} R_{i} \left( \alpha \right)p\left( {s_{i} } \right) = \sum\limits_{{k = 1}}^{{L - 1}} {F_{k} } \left( \alpha \right)\left[ {x_{{k + 1}} - x_{k} } \right] \le \sum\limits_{{k = 1}}^{{L - 1}} {F_{k} } \left( \beta \right)\left[ {x_{{k + 1}} - x_{k} } \right] = ER\left( \beta \right) $$

Q.E.D.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blavatskyy, P. Expected return—expected loss approach to optimal portfolio investment. Theory Decis 94, 63–81 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09870-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09870-3

Keywords

Navigation