Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Buck-passing dumping in a garbage-dumping game

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study stable strategy profiles in a pure exchange game of bads, where each player dumps his or her bads such as garbage onto someone else. Hirai et al. (Mathematical Social Sciences 51(2):162–170, 2006) show that cycle dumping, in which each player follows an ordering and dumps his or her bads onto the next player, is a strong Nash equilibrium and that self-disposal is \(\alpha \)-stable for some initial distributions of bads. In this paper, we show that a strategy profile of bullying, in which all players dump their bads onto a single player, becomes \(\alpha \)-stable for every exchange game of bads. We also provide a necessary and sufficient condition for a strategy profile to be \(\alpha \)-stable in an exchange game of bads. In addition, we show that repeating an exchange after the first exchange makes self-disposal stationary.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In general, the \(\alpha \)-core is a superset of the \(\beta \)-core. The opposite inclusion holds for every pure exchange game of bads. To be more specific, the coincidence holds if every coalition S has a coalitionally dominant strategy \(x^S\): for every strategy profile \(z\in X^N\), \(u_i (x^S,z^(N\setminus S) )\ge u_i (z)\ \forall i\in S\). As long as all players in S dump all bads outside S, the strategy is a coalitionally dominant strategy of S. Therefore, both core notions coincide with each other. See Hirai et al. (2006) for details. In addition, the \(\gamma \)-core is a superset of the \(\delta \)-core. If the number of types of bads is one and there are three or more players, then the \(\gamma \)-core becomes empty, which immediately implies that the \(\delta \)-core is also empty. For further details, see Nakayama (2012). For the coincidence between SNE and CPNE, see Proposition 5 in Hirai et al. (2006).

  2. For more details on the other notions, see, for example, Peleg and Sudhölter (2007, Section 11). Kóczy (2018, Chapter 5) also elaborates the definitions and backgrounds of these core notions.

  3. The last assumption means that players have, for example, bad apples and that bad oranges are not considered in the model. The homogeneity assumption means that we do not distinguish between very bad apples between a little bad ones: they have homogeneously bad apples.

  4. Note that the condition also implies \(b^1=b^2\).

  5. Formally, assuming that player i is the kth player in ordering \(\sigma _{\mathcal {P}(i)}\) of coalition \(\mathcal {P}(i)\), let \(\lambda ^{\sigma _{\mathcal {P}}}(i):=\sigma _{\mathcal {P}(i)}(k-1)\) and \(\eta ^{\sigma _{\mathcal {P}}}(i):=\sigma _{\mathcal {P}(i)}(k+1)\). Note that if i belongs to that player’s one-person coalition \(\mathcal {P}(i)=\{i\}\), then \(\lambda ^{\sigma _{\mathcal {P}}}(i)=\eta ^{\sigma _{\mathcal {P}}}(i)=i\).

  6. Note that we do not assume that their coalition must split up in the second stage: we can simply admit the case in which their coalition may split up, because if the coalition remains in the second stage, their joint strategy should give them payoffs that are greater than or equal to the payoffs they obtain if their coalition collapses.

References

  • Aumann, R. J. (1959). Acceptable points in general cooperative n-person games. In A. Tucker & R. Luce (Eds.), Contributions to the theory of games IV.. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R. J., & Peleg, B. (1960). Von Neumann-Morgenstern solutions to cooperative games without side payments. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 66(3), 173–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chander, P., & Tulkens, H. (1997). The core of an economy with multilateral environmental externalities. International Journal of Game Theory, 26(3), 379–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cramton, P., Gibbons, R., & Klemperer, P. (1987). Dissolving a partnership efficiently. Econometrica, 55(3), 615–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currarini, S., & Marini, M. (2004). A conjectural cooperative equilibrium for strategic form games. In C. Carraro & V. Fragnelli (Eds.), Game practice and the environment. Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirai, T., Masuzawa, T., & Nakayama, M. (2006). Coalition-proof Nash equilibria and cores in a strategic pure exchange game of bads. Mathematical Social Sciences, 51(2), 162–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kóczy, Á. L. (2018). Partition function form games (theory and decision library C). Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Konishi, H., Quint, T., & Wako, J. (2001). On the Shapley-Scarf economy: the case of multiple types of indivisible goods. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 35(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nakayama, M. (2012). Foundations and applications of cooperative games. Keiso Shobo Publishing. In Japanese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, B., & Sudhölter, P. (2007). Introduction to the theory of cooperative games. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarf, H. E. (1971). On the existence of a cooperative solution for a general class of N-person games. Journal of Economic Theory, 3(2), 169–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L. S., & Shubik, M. (1969). On the core of an economic system with externalities. American Economic Review, 59(4), 678–684.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Takaaki Abe.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The author is grateful to Yukihiko Funaki, Yukio Koriyama, and the participants of CREST Workshop 2019 at Ecole Polytechnique for their helpful comments. The author gratefully acknowledges financial support from JSPS Grant-in-Aid for Research Activity Start-up (No. 19K23206) and Waseda University Grant-in-Aid for Research Base Creation (2019C-486).

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Proposition 2

Proposition 2. Let \(b\in B^N\). A strategy profile \(x\in X^N_b\) is \(\alpha \)-stable if and only if for any \(S\subseteq N\) there is \(i\in S\), such that \(\sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\ge r^i_x\).

Proof

Let \(x\in X^N_b\) be \(\alpha \)-stable. By the definition of \(\alpha \)-stability, for any \(S\subseteq N\) and any \(y^S\in X^S_b\), there is \(z^{N\setminus S}\in X^{N\setminus S}_b\), such that

$$\begin{aligned} v^i(y^S,z^{N\setminus S})\le v^i(x) \text { for some}{i\in S}. \end{aligned}$$

Since \(v^i\) is represented by \(u^i\), the inequality is equivalent to \(u^i(r^i_{(y^S,z^{N\setminus S})})\le u^i(r^i_x)\). Moreover, since \(u^i\) is a strictly decreasing function, this is equivalent to \(r^i_{(y^S,z^{N\setminus S})}\ge r^i_x\). Hence, x is \(\alpha \)-stable if and only if for any \(S\subseteq N\) and any \(y^S\in X^S_b\), there is \(z^{N\setminus S}\in X^{N\setminus S}_b\), such that

$$\begin{aligned} r^i_{(y^S,z^{N\setminus S})}\ge r^i_x \text { for some}{i\in S}. \end{aligned}$$

Below, fixing \(S\subseteq N\), we show that the following two statements are equivalent:

  1. (i)

    For any \(y^S\in X^S_b\), there is \(z^{N\setminus S}\in X^{N\setminus S}_b\), such that \(r^i_{(y^S,z^{N\setminus S})}\ge r^i_x\) for some \(i\in S\).

  2. (ii)

    There is \(i\in S\), such that \(\sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\ge r^i_x\).

We first show (ii) \(\Rightarrow \) (i). Let i be the player satisfying the condition of (ii). Set \({\bar{z}}^{ji}=b^j\) for all \(j\in N\setminus S\). It readily follows that \(\sum _{j\in N\setminus S}{\bar{z}}^{ji}= \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). Hence, for any \(y^S\in X^S_b\),

$$\begin{aligned} r^i_{(y^S,z^{N\setminus S})}=\sum _{j\in S}y^{ji}+\sum _{j\in N\setminus S}{\bar{z}}^{ji}\ge \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j \overset{\text {(ii)}}{\ge } r^i_x \end{aligned}$$

We now show (i) \(\Rightarrow \) (ii). Assume that for any \(i\in S\),

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j< r^i_x. \end{aligned}$$
(1)

Let \({\bar{y}}^S\) be a profile satisfying \({\bar{y}}^{ji}=0\) for all \(j,i \in S\). It holds that for any \(z^{N\setminus S}\in X^{N\setminus S}_b\) and any \(i\in S\),

$$\begin{aligned} r^i_{({\bar{y}}^S,z^{N\setminus S})}=\sum _{j\in S}{\bar{y}}^{ji}+\sum _{j\in N\setminus S}z^{ji} \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\overset{{(1)}}{<}r^i_x. \end{aligned}$$

This contradicts (i). \(\square \)

1.2 Proof of Lemma 1

Lemma 1. Let \(n\ge 4\). For any \(b\in B^N\) and any \(\sigma \in \Psi ^N\), no strategy profile of the following \(2n-1\) profiles can be defined as a nonnegative convex combination of the other \(2n-2\) profiles:

$$\begin{aligned} x^\sigma (b),\ {\hat{x}}^i(b) \text { for all}{i\in N\setminus \{1\}},\ x^{\sigma i}(b) \text { for all}{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}. \end{aligned}$$

If \(n=3\), then the same holds for the following four profiles:

$$\begin{aligned} x^\sigma (b),\ {\hat{x}}^2 (b),\ {\hat{x}}^3 (b),\ x^{\sigma 1}(b). \end{aligned}$$

Proof

We prove the statement for \(n\ge 4\). Let \(b\in B^N\) and \(\sigma \in \Psi ^N\).

We begin with \(x^\sigma (b)\). We assume that there is a collection of non-negative real numbers that sum to 1, \({\hat{c}}^i\) with \(i\in N\setminus \{1\}\) and \(c^{\sigma i}\) with \(i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}\), such that

$$\begin{aligned} x^\sigma (b) = \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i {\hat{x}}^i(b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} x^{\sigma i}(b). \end{aligned}$$

If there is \(i\in N\setminus \{1\}\), such that \({\hat{c}}^{i}>0\), then for any player \(j\in N\setminus \{1\}\), we have \(x^\sigma (b)^{j1} \ge {\hat{c}}^{i} {\hat{x}}^{i}(b)^{j1} = {\hat{c}}^{i} b^j > 0\). However, in the \(\sigma \)-cycle profile \(x^\sigma (b)\), there is a player \(j^*\) in \(N\setminus \{1\}\) who dumps no bads to player 1, namely, \(x^\sigma (b)^{j^*1}=0\). This is a contradiction. If there is \(i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}\) such that \(c^{\sigma i}>0\), then \(x^\sigma (b)^{i1} \ge c^{\sigma i} x^{\sigma i}(b)^{i1} = c^{\sigma i} b^{i} > 0\). However, since \(\lambda (1)\) is the only player who dumps bads to player 1 in \(x^\sigma (b)\), we have \(x^\sigma (b)^{i'1}=0\) for every \(i'\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}\). This is a contradiction. Hence all the coefficients above are zero, while \(x^\sigma (b)\) contains positive entries, which implies that \(x^\sigma (b)\) can not be written as a non-negative convex combination of the other profiles.

Now, let \(i^*\in N\setminus \{1\}\). We suppose that

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{x}}^{i^*}(b) = c^\sigma x^\sigma (b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,i^*\}} {\hat{c}}^i {\hat{x}}^i(b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} x^{\sigma i}(b) \end{aligned}$$

holds for some collection of non-negative coefficients that sum to 1. Assume \(c^\sigma >0\). For any \(i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}\), \({\hat{x}}^{i^*}(b)^{i \eta (i)}=0\). However, \(x^\sigma (b)^{h \eta (h)}=b^{h}>0\) for some \(h\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}\). This is a contradiction. If there is \(i\in N\setminus \{1,i^*\}\) such that \({\hat{c}}^{i}>0\), then \({\hat{x}}^{i^*}(b)^{1i}=0< b^1= {\hat{x}}^{i}(b)^{1i}\), which is a contradiction. If there is \(i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}\), such that \(c^{\sigma i}>0\), then since \(n\ge 4\) we obtain a contradiction in the same manner as the case \(c^\sigma >0\) by replacing \(x^\sigma (b)\) with \(x^{\sigma i}(b)\). Thus, \({\hat{x}}^{i^*}(b)\) can not be written as a non-negative convex combination of the other profiles.

Let \(i^*\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}\). We assume that

$$\begin{aligned} x^{\sigma i^*}(b) = c^\sigma x^\sigma (b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i {\hat{x}}^i(b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),i^*\}} c^{\sigma i} x^{\sigma i}(b) \end{aligned}$$

holds for some collection of non-negative coefficients that sum to 1. If \(c^\sigma >0\) then we have \(x^{\sigma i^*}(b)^{i^* \eta (i^*)}=0<b^{i^*}=x^\sigma (b)^{i^* \eta (i^*)}\), which is a contradiction. If there is \(i\in N\setminus \{1\}\), such that \({\hat{c}}^{i}>0\), then at least one player \(j^*\in N\setminus \{1,i^*,\lambda (1)\}\) satisfies \(x^{\sigma i^*}(b)^{j^*1}=0\), while \({\hat{x}}^i(b)^{j1}=1\) for every \(j\in N\setminus \{1\}\). This is a contradiction. If there is \(i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),i^*\}\) such that \(c^{\sigma i}>0\), then \(x^{\sigma i^*}(b)^{i^* \eta (i^*)}=0<b^{i^*}=x^{\sigma i}(b)^{i^* \eta (i^*)}\), which is a contradiction. Thus, \(x^{\sigma i^*}(b)\) can not be written as a non-negative convex combination of the other profiles. \(\square \)

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3

Proposition 3. For any \(n\ge 3\), any \(b\in B^N\), and any \(\sigma \in \Psi ^N\), all nonnegative convex combinations of \(E(n,b,\sigma )\) are \(\alpha \)-stable.

Proof

In view of Lemma 1, the statement for \(n=3\) is straightforward to show, since the number of the profiles is four. Below, we prove the statement for \(n\ge 4\). Let \(b\in B^N\) and \(\sigma \in \Psi ^N\). Let y(b) be a non-negative convex combination of the profiles in \(E(n,b,\sigma )\):

$$\begin{aligned} y(b) =c^\sigma x^\sigma (b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i {\hat{x}}^i(b) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} x^{\sigma i}(b). \end{aligned}$$

In view of Proposition 2, we show that for every coalition \(S\subseteq N\), there is \(i\in N\), such that \(\sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\ge r^i_{y}\).

We have

$$\begin{aligned} r_y =c^\sigma r_{x^\sigma } + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i r_{{\hat{x}}^i} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} r_{x^{\sigma i}}. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(h\in N\setminus \{1\}\). We have

$$\begin{aligned} r^{h}_y= & {} c^\sigma r^{h}_{x^\sigma } + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i r^{h}_{{\hat{x}}^i} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} r^{h}_{x^{\sigma i}}\nonumber \\= & {} c^\sigma r^{h}_{x^\sigma } + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i r^{h}_{{\hat{x}}^i} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),\lambda (h)\}} c^{\sigma i} r^{h}_{x^{\sigma i}} + c^{\sigma \lambda (h)} r^{h}_{x^{\sigma \lambda (h)}}\nonumber \\= & {} c^\sigma b^{\lambda (h)} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i r^{h}_{{\hat{x}}^i} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),\lambda (h)\}} c^{\sigma i} b^{\lambda (h)} + c^{\sigma \lambda (h)} 0\nonumber \\= & {} \left( c^\sigma + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),\lambda (h)\}} c^{\sigma i} \right) b^{\lambda (h)} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i r^{h}_{{\hat{x}}^i}. \end{aligned}$$
(2)

The third equality holds, because (i) in the profiles \(x^\sigma \) and \(x^{\sigma i}\), the bads player h receives are equal to the initial endowment of player \(\lambda (h)\), and (ii) in the profile \(x^{\sigma \lambda (h)}\), player h receives no bads as player \(\lambda (h)\) dumps his bads all to player 1. Moreover, we have

$$\begin{aligned} (2)= & {} \left( c^\sigma + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),\lambda (h)\}} c^{\sigma i} \right) b^{\lambda (h)} + {\hat{c}}^h b^1\nonumber \\\le & {} \left( c^\sigma + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1),\lambda (h)\}} c^{\sigma i} \right) b^{\lambda (h)} + {\hat{c}}^h b^{\lambda (h)}\nonumber \\\le & {} b^{\lambda (h)}. \end{aligned}$$
(3)

The first equality holds, because \(r^{h}_{{\hat{x}}^i}=b^1\) holds only for \(i=h\). The second inequality holds as \(b^1\le ... \le b^n\). Since the coefficients sum to 1, we obtain the third inequality. Thus, (3) shows that \(r^{h}_y \le b^{\lambda (h)}\) for every \(h\in N\setminus \{1\}\), which implies that if a coalition S contains a player \(h\in N\setminus \{1\}\) but not \(\lambda (h)\), then, in view of Proposition 2, the coalition does not \(\alpha \)-improve. Therefore, below, we focus on a coalition defined as \(\{\sigma (1),\ldots ,\sigma (s)\}\) for some \(1\le s\le n-1\).

For any \(s\ge 2\), coalition \(S:=\{\sigma (1),\ldots ,\sigma (s)\}\) contains player \(\sigma (2)\). From (3), it follows that \(r^{\sigma (2)}_y\le b^{\sigma (1)}=b^{1}= \min _{\emptyset \ne T\subseteq N} \sum _{j\in T}b^j \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). Hence, for any \(s\ge 2\), coalition \(S=\{\sigma (1),\ldots ,\sigma (s)\}\) does not \(\alpha \)-improve. We now consider the coalition \(S=\{1\}\). We have

$$\begin{aligned} r^{1}_y= & {} c^\sigma r^{1}_{x^\sigma } + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i r^{1}_{{\hat{x}}^i} +\sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} r^{1}_{x^{\sigma i}}\nonumber \\= & {} c^\sigma b^{\lambda (1)} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i \left( \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{1\}}b^j \right) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} \left( b^{\lambda (1)}+b^{i} \right) \nonumber \\= & {} c^\sigma b^{\lambda (1)} + \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{1\}}b^j\left( \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i \right) + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} b^{\lambda (1)}+\sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} b^{i}. \end{aligned}$$
(4)

For simplicity, let \(\Sigma {\hat{c}}:= \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} {\hat{c}}^i\). We have

$$\begin{aligned}&(4) =c^\sigma b^{\lambda (1)} + \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{1\}}b^j \Sigma {\hat{c}} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} b^{\lambda (1)}+\sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} b^{i}\\&=c^\sigma b^{\lambda (1)} + \left[ b^{\lambda (1)} \Sigma {\hat{c}} +\sum _{j\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}}b^j \Sigma {\hat{c}} \right] \\&\quad + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} b^{\lambda (1)}+ \left[ c^{\sigma 1} b^{1} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}}c^{\sigma i} b^{i} \right] \\&= \left[ \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}} (c^{\sigma i} + \Sigma {\hat{c}}) b^{i} \right] + \left[ c^\sigma + \Sigma {\hat{c}} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma i} \right] b^{\lambda (1)} + c^{\sigma 1} b^{1}\\&= \left[ \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}} (c^{\sigma i} + \Sigma {\hat{c}}) b^{i} \right] + b^{\lambda (1)} + c^{\sigma 1} b^{1}\\&\le \left[ \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}} (c^{\sigma i} + \Sigma {\hat{c}}) b^{i} \right] + b^{\lambda (1)} + \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}} c^{\sigma 1}b^{i} \\&= \left[ \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}} (c^{\sigma 1}+c^{\sigma i} + \Sigma {\hat{c}}) b^{i} \right] + b^{\lambda (1)}\\&\le \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1,\lambda (1)\}} b^{i} + b^{\lambda (1)}\\&= \sum _{i\in N\setminus \{1\}} b^{i}. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, coalition \(\{1\}\) does not \(\alpha \)-improve. Thus, no coalition \(\alpha \)-improves, and y(b) is \(\alpha \)-stable. \(\square \)

1.4 Proof of Lemma 2

Lemma 2. Let \(\mathcal {P}\in \Pi ^*(N)\), \(\sigma _\mathcal {P}\in \Psi ^{\mathcal {P}}\), and \(b\in B^N\). If for any \(\mathcal {Q}\subsetneq \mathcal {P}\) with \(\mathcal {P}(n)\in \mathcal {Q}\) there is \(j\in \cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}} T\), such that \(b^j\le \sum _{i\in N\setminus (\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}} T)}b^i\), then strategy profile \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}(b)\) is \(\alpha \)-stable.

Proof

We consider coalition S that satisfies \(\emptyset \ne S\subsetneq N\). If there is a coalition \(T\in \mathcal {P}\), such that \(T\cap S\ne \emptyset \) and \(T\setminus S \ne \emptyset \), then for some \(h\in S\), \(\lambda (h)\in T\setminus S\) and \(h\in T\cap S\). From the definition of \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} r^h_{x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}}=b^{\lambda (h)} \overset{\lambda (h)\not \in S}{\le } \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j, \end{aligned}$$

and S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. Therefore, for coalition S to \(\alpha \)-improve, S needs to satisfy \(S=\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}}T\) for some \(\mathcal {Q}\subsetneq \mathcal {P}\). If \(\mathcal {P}(n)\not \in \mathcal {Q}\), then \(n\in N\setminus S\). Hence, for some \(h\in S\), \(r^h_{x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}}=b^{\lambda (h)}\le b^n \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\), which means that S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. If \(\mathcal {P}(n)\in \mathcal {Q}\), then in view of the assumption of the claim, there is \(j\in \cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}} T\), such that \(b^j\le \sum _{i\in N\setminus (\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}} T)}b^i\). We fix this player j and consider \(\eta (j)\). It holds that \(r^{\eta (j)}_{x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}}=b^{j}\le \sum _{i\in N\setminus S}b^i\), which means that S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. Therefore, no coalition \(\alpha \)-improves \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}(b)\). \(\square \)

1.5 Proof of Lemma 3

Lemma 3. Let \(\mathcal {P}\in \Pi ^*(N)\) with \(\mathcal {P}(n)=\mathcal {P}(1)\). For any \(b\in B^N\) and any \(\sigma _\mathcal {P}\in \Psi ^\mathcal {P}\), strategy profile \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}(b)\) is \(\alpha \)-stable.

Proof

If there is a coalition \(T\in \mathcal {P}\), such that \(T\cap S\ne \emptyset \) and \(T\setminus S \ne \emptyset \), then S does not \(\alpha \)-improve in the same manner as Lemma 2. Hence, to \(\alpha \)-improve, S must satisfy \(S=\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}}T\) for some \(\mathcal {Q}\subsetneq \mathcal {P}\). If \(\mathcal {P}(n)\not \in \mathcal {Q}\), then player n is in \(N\setminus S\), and for some \(h\in S\), \(b^{h}\le b^n \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). If \(\mathcal {P}(n)\in \mathcal {Q}\), then player 1 is in S, and for some \(h\in N\setminus S\), \(b^1\le b^h \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). \(\square \)

1.6 Proof of Proposition 4

Proposition 4. Let \(\mathcal {P}\in \Pi ^*(N)\) with \(\mathcal {P}(n)=\mathcal {P}(1)\), \(\sigma _\mathcal {P}\in \Psi ^\mathcal {P}\), \(t\in \mathbb {R}_+\), and \(i\in N\setminus T_\mathcal {P}\). For any \(b\in B^N\), the following two statements are equivalent:

  1. i.

    \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}_{ti}(b)\) is \(\alpha \)-stable,

  2. ii.

    \(t\le \sum _{j\in N}b^j - (b^i + b^{\lambda (i)})\).

Proof

In this proof, we fix \(\mathcal {P}\), \(\sigma _\mathcal {P}\), t, i, and b as mentioned in the proposition and write \(r_{**}:=r_{x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}_{ti}}\) and \(r_{*}:=r_{x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}}\) for simplicity. We begin with [(ii)\(\Rightarrow \)(i)]. Below, we consider that a coalition S satisfies \(\emptyset \ne S\subsetneq N\). Claim 1 is used for Claims 25. Claims 25 are used for the \(\alpha \)-improvement of coalition S. \(\square \)

Claim 1

For any \(j\in N\setminus \{i\}\), \(r^j_{**}\le r^j_{*}\). For the player i, \(r^i_{**}\ge r^i_{*}\).

Proof of Claim 1. For every player \(j\in N\setminus \{i\}\), \(r^j_{**} = b^{\lambda (j)}- x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}_{ti}(b)^{\lambda (j) i} \le b^{\lambda (j)} = r^j_{*}\). For the fixed player i, \(r^i_{**} = b^{\lambda (i)}+ t \ge b^{\lambda (i)} = r^i_{*}\). //

Claim 2

For any S with \(\emptyset \ne S\subsetneq N\), if \(i\in N\setminus S\), then S does not \(\alpha \)-improve.

Proof of Claim 2. In view of lemma 3, \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}\) is \(\alpha \)-stable. Hence, for the coalition S, there is \(h\in S\), such that \(r^h_{*}\le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). Since \(h\ne i\), it follows from Claim 1 that

$$\begin{aligned} r^h_{**} \overset{{Claim 1}}{\le } r^h_* \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j, \end{aligned}$$

which means that S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. //

Claim 3

For any S with \(\emptyset \ne S\subsetneq N\), if \(T_\mathcal {P}\subseteq S\), then S does not \(\alpha \)-improve.

Proof of Claim 3. Since \(\{1,n\}\subseteq T_\mathcal {P}\), \(\sigma _{T_\mathcal {P}}(1)=1\). We write \(h:=\sigma _{T_\mathcal {P}}(2)\). Since \(i\in N\setminus T_\mathcal {P}\), \(h\ne i\). We have

$$\begin{aligned} r^h_{**} \overset{{Claim 1}}{\le } r^h_* = b^{\lambda (h)} =b^1 \le \min _{j\in N}b^j. \end{aligned}$$

Since S is a proper subset of N, for some \(h'\in N\setminus S\), \(\min _{j\in N}b^j \le b^{h'} \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). Hence, S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. //

Claim 4

For any S with \(\emptyset \ne S\subsetneq N\), if S satisfies the following condition, then S does not \(\alpha \)-improve:

$$\begin{aligned} \text {there is }T\in \mathcal {P}\setminus \{\mathcal {P}(i)\} \text { such that }T\cap S\ne \emptyset \text { and }T\setminus S\ne \emptyset . \end{aligned}$$

Proof of Claim 4. Since \(T\cap S\ne \emptyset \) and \(T\setminus S\ne \emptyset \), there is a player \(h\in T\cap S\), such that \(\lambda (h)\in T\setminus S\). Considering that \(h\in T\ne \mathcal {P}(i)\) implies \(h\ne i\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} r^h_{**} \overset{{Claim 1}}{\le } r^h_* = b^{\lambda (h)} \overset{\lambda (h)\not \in S}{\le } \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. //

Claim 5

For any S with \(\emptyset \ne S\subsetneq N\) and \(S\cap T_\mathcal {P}=\emptyset \), if S satisfies the following condition, then S does not \(\alpha \)-improve:

$$\begin{aligned} \text {there is }T\in \mathcal {P}\setminus \{\mathcal {P}(i)\} \text { such that }T\cap S\ne \emptyset . \end{aligned}$$

Proof of Claim 5. Since \(T\cap S\ne \emptyset \), we consider a player \(h\in T\cap S\). Moreover, since \(h\in T\ne \mathcal {P}(i)\), we obtain \(h\ne i\). We have

$$\begin{aligned} r^h_{**} \overset{{Claim 1}}{\le } r^h_* = b^{\lambda (h)} \le b^{n} \end{aligned}$$

Since \(n\in T_\mathcal {P}\) and \(S\cap T_\mathcal {P}=\emptyset \), we have \(n\in N\setminus S\), which implies

$$\begin{aligned} b^{n} \le \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. //

In view of Claim 4, for a coalition S to \(\alpha \)-improve, it must obey the following condition: for some partition \(\mathcal {Q}\subseteq \mathcal {P}\setminus \{\mathcal {P}(i)\}\), \(S= (\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}}T) \cup (S\cap \mathcal {P}(i))\), where \(\mathcal {Q}\) may be \(\emptyset \). Moreover, by Claim 3 and the fact that \(T_\mathcal {P}\) is an element of \(\mathcal {P}\), the previous condition must become the following form: for some partition \(\mathcal {Q}\subseteq \mathcal {P}\setminus \{\mathcal {P}(i), T_\mathcal {P}\}\), \(S= (\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}}T) \cup (S\cap \mathcal {P}(i))\). Hence, \(S\cap T_\mathcal {P}=\emptyset \). By Claim 5, \((\cup _{T\in \mathcal {Q}}T)\) must be empty. Hence, \(S=S\cap \mathcal {P}(i)\), which is equivalent to the condition \(S\subseteq \mathcal {P}(i)\). By Claim 2, S satisfies \(i\in S\subseteq \mathcal {P}(i)\).

If there is \(h\in S\), such that \(h\ne i\), then we have \(r^h_{**} \overset{{Claim 1}}{\le } r^h_* = b^{\lambda (h)} \le b^{n} \overset{n\in N\setminus S}{\le } \sum _{j\in N\setminus S}b^j\). Hence, S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. Therefore, it suffices to show \(S=\{i\}\) does not \(\alpha \)-improve. By the condition of t, we obtain \(r^i_{**} = b^{\lambda (i)}+t \le b^{\lambda (i)} + \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i, \lambda (i) \}}b^j = \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}b^j\), which means that S does not \(\alpha \)-improve. Thus, for every \(S\subseteq N\), S does not \(\alpha \)-improve \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}_{ti}(b)\): \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}_{ti}(b)\) is \(\alpha \)-stable.

Now, we assume that the opposite inequality holds for the condition of t, \(t> \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i, \lambda (i) \}}b^j\). Then, in the same manner as above, \(r^i_{**} > \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}b^j\). Given Proposition 2 and the fact that i is the only member of S, \(S=\{i\}\) \(\alpha \)-improves. Hence, \(x^{\sigma _\mathcal {P}}_{ti}(b)\) is not \(\alpha \)-stable. This establishes [not (ii) \(\Rightarrow \) not (i)].

1.7 Proof of Proposition 5

Proposition 5. For any \(b\in B^N\), the self-disposal profile \(x^*(b)\) is the only m-stable profile in \(X^N_b\).

Proof

Let \(b\in b^N\). We first show that if profile \(x\in X^N_b\) is not the self-disposal profile \(x^*(b)\), then x is not m-stable. Assume that there is a player \(i\in N\), such that \(x^{ih}>0\) for some \(h\in N\setminus \{i\}\). We define \(y^i\in X_b^i\) as follows: \(y^{ii}=b^i\) and \(y^{ij}=0\) for every \(j\in N\setminus \{i\}\). We have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_x - \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_{y^i,x^{-i}}= & {} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}} \sum _{l\in N} x^{lj} - \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}\left( y^{ij} + \sum _{l\in N\setminus \{i\}} x^{lj} \right) \\= & {} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}} ( x^{ij} - y^{ij} )\\= & {} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}} x^{ij}\\> & {} 0. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, \(\{i\}\) m-deviates from x, and profile x is not m-stable.

Now, we show that \(x^*(b)\) is m-stable. We write \(x^*:=x^*(b)\) for simplicity. Assume that a coalition S m-deviates from \(x^*\). By the definition of m-deviation, there is \(y^S\in X_{b}^S\), such that for every \(i\in S\):

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_{y^S,x^{* N\setminus S}} < \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_{x^*}. \end{aligned}$$
(5)

Let \(T:=\{i\in S | y^{ij}>0 \text { for some }j\in N\setminus \{i\}\}\). Note that T is nonempty, because if \(y^{ij}=0\) for every \(j\in N\setminus \{i\}\) and every \(i\in S\), then \(y^S=x^{*S}\), which contradicts (5). For every \(i\in T\), define

$$\begin{aligned} I^i(y^S):= \sum _{h\in S\setminus \{i\}}y^{hi} \text { and }O^i(y^S):= \sum _{h\in N\setminus \{i\}}y^{ih}. \end{aligned}$$

For every \(i\in T\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_{y^S,x^{* N\setminus S}} = \left( \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}b^j \right) + O^i(y^S) - I^i(y^S). \end{aligned}$$
(6)

Since \(\sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_{x^*} = \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}b^j\), (5) implies

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}r^j_{y^S,x^{* N\setminus S}} < \sum _{j\in N\setminus \{i\}}b^j. \end{aligned}$$
(7)

It follows from (6) and (7) that for every \(i\in T\),

$$\begin{aligned} O^i(y^S) < I^i(y^S). \end{aligned}$$
(8)

In view of the definition of T, \(y^{ii}=b^i\) for every \(i\in S\setminus T\). Hence, we have \(I^i(y^S) \overset{\text {def}}{=} \sum _{h\in S\setminus \{i\}}y^{hi}=\sum _{h\in T\setminus \{i\}}y^{hi}\) and \(O^i(y^S) \overset{\text {def}}{=} \sum _{h\in N\setminus \{i\}}y^{ih}=\sum _{h\in T\setminus \{i\}}y^{ih}+\sum _{h\in N\setminus T}y^{ih}\). We obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i\in T}I^i(y^S)= & {} \sum _{i\in T} \sum _{h\in T\setminus \{i\}}y^{hi}\\= & {} \sum _{i\in T} \sum _{h\in T\setminus \{i\}}y^{ih}\\\le & {} \sum _{i\in T} \left( \sum _{h\in T\setminus \{i\}}y^{ih} + \sum _{h\in N\setminus T}y^{ih} \right) \\= & {} \sum _{i\in T}O^i(y^S). \end{aligned}$$

This contradicts (8). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abe, T. Buck-passing dumping in a garbage-dumping game. Theory Decis 93, 509–533 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-021-09858-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-021-09858-5

Keywords

Navigation