Skip to main content
Log in

Good reasons are apparent to the knowing subject

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Reasons rationalize beliefs. Reasons, when all goes well, turn true beliefs into knowledge. I am interested in the relationship between these aspects of reasons. Without a proper understanding of their relationship, the theory of knowledge will be less illuminating than it ought to be. I hope to show that previous accounts have failed to account for this relationship. This has resulted in a tendency to focus on justification rather than knowledge. It has also resulted in many becoming skeptical about the prospects for an analysis of knowledge. The skepticism is misplaced and the tendency can be fixed without sacrificing any insights. The solution is to see how good reasons (in a sense to be articulated) are apparent (in a sense to be articulated) to the knowing subject. Once this claim is unpacked, we see that it is an illuminating analysis of knowledge in terms of distinct but intimately related aspects of epistemic assessment. It helps us see the value of knowledge (over and above true belief) and it affords us a unified, “reasons-first” metaepistemology. The resulting picture is neither a familiar kind of internalism or externalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Before getting started I should mention that I like to put my point in terms of reasons, though for my purposes it would also be ok to put the points I make in terms of evidence.

  2. Non-foundationalists say that reasonableness always requires having further reasons. Foundationalists deny this. I will remain neutral until later in the paper.

  3. As opposed to the facts, in which case we would be considering its sufficiency as an objective normative reason. More on objective normative reasons and their relation to subjective normative reasons below.

  4. For various takes on this idea see Sellars (1956/1997), BonJour (1985, p. 7), Korsgard (1996, Lecture 3), Scanlon (1998, Introduction), Moran (2001, Chapter 2), Boyle (2012), Smithies (2016). For a dissenting view, see Kornblith (2011).

  5. Some readers may worry that this is inconsistent with out tendency to attribute knowledge to small children and animals. I disagree, although the point will have to be made in a different paper.

  6. Perhaps better, a (rather than the) connection between justification and truth. Justification is already connected to truth in the minimal sense that your justification is something that makes it rational for you to regard something as true. The problem is that your justification needs another connection to truth for you to have knowledge; this is the upshot of the Gettier problem. Another way of voicing the concern is that we have two different truth-connections and they seem to both be interesting but not like two different aspects of a single interesting thing.

  7. Cf. Putnam (1975).

  8. Kirkham (1984) embraces the consequence.

  9. One might object that the anti-Gettier condition is meant to be the connection between justification and truth, so it isn’t a mere aggregate. My concern is that the connection just seems like another dimension of assessment entirely. I take it this is the worry that the comments about JTB + analyses being ad hoc and unilluminating are gesturing toward.

  10. See Lehrer (1965, 1970), Lehrer and Paxson (1968), Hilpinen (1971), Johnsen (1974), Swain (1974), Barker (1976), Klein (1971, 1976, 1980), Pollock (1986), Moser (1989), Audi (1993), de Almeida and Fett (2016). See Shope (1983) for a useful overview.

  11. It is sometimes argued that knowledge is more explanatorily powerful than mere rational true belief because it is more robust in the fact of new evidence and hence less likely to be lost after one learns more (Williamson 2000: Chapters 2,3). However, rational beliefs with no factual defeaters are even more robust to new evidence, but knowledge is still more interesting.

  12. See fn. 12.

  13. Putting it this way runs afoul of the reasons-first order of explanation. There is a more cumbersome way of making the same point that does not: if the world were as the subject rationally takes it to be (where rationality is determined by the balance of subjective normative reasons), then her subjective normative reason would be an objective normative reason.

  14. Though see (Schroeder 2021, p. 69) for a possible lapse into his earlier view.

  15. Strictly speaking, these are her justifiable beliefs. I ignore the subtlety here to streamline exposition.

  16. Thanks to an anonymous referee for making clear the importance of driving this point home.

  17. Ballantyne (2015) makes much of this point.

  18. Rosenberg (2002) has a proposal that is similar in this respect, although relativist in a way mine isn’t.

References

  • Audi, R. (1993). The structure of justification. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ballantyne, N. (2015). The significance of unpossessed evidence. The Philosophical Quarterly, 65(260), 315–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, J. (1976). What you don’t know won’t hurt you? American Philosophical Quarterly, 13, 303–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (2003). In L. BonJour, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Epistemic justification. Blackwell Publishing.

  • BonJour, L. (2010). Epistemology: Classic problems and contemporary responses (2nd ed.). Rowman & Littlefield Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, M. (2012). Essentially rational animals. In G. Abel & J. Conant (Eds.), Rethinking epistemology. Walter de Gruyter Verlag. DeGruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Almeida, C., & Fett, J. R. (2016). Defeasibility and Gettierization: A reminder. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(1), 152–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). In J. McDowell (Ed.), The varieties of reference. Clarendon Press.

  • Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Rowman & Littlefield Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified, true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R. (1971). Knowledge & justification. Ajatus, 33(7), 39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. (2007). Reasons as defaults. Philosophers’ Imprint, 7, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. (2012). Reasons as defaults. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnsen, B. (1974). Knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 25(4), 273–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1985). It’s not what you know that counts. Journal of Philosophy, 82(7), 350–363.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkham, R. (1984). Does the Gettier problem rest on a mistake? Mind, 93(372), 501–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1971). A proposed definition of propositional knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 68(16), 471–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1976). Knowledge, causality, indefeasibility. Journal of Philosophy, 73(20), 792–812.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1980). Misleading evidence and the restoration of justification. Philosophical Studies, 37(1), 81–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2017). The nature of knowledge. In R. Borges, C. de Almeida, & P. Klein (Eds.), Explaining knowledge: New essays on the Gettier problem (pp. 35–57). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2011). On reflection. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgard, C. (1996). The sources of normativity. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2017). Lessons from Gettier. In R. Borges, C. de Almeida, & P. Klein (Eds.), Explaining knowledge: New essays on the Gettier problem (pp. 152–169). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1965). Knowledge, truth and evidence. Analysis, 25(5), 168–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1970). The fourth condition for knowledge: A defense. Review of Metaphysics, 24(1), 122–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Paxson, T. (1968). Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief. Journal of Philosophy, 66(8), 225–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the truth-connection. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J., & Chihara, C. (1985). The surprise examination paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4(1), 71–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority & estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. K. (1988). Review of John Pollock’s Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39(1), 131–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. K. (1989). Knowledge & evidence. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. (2015). Gettier and the method of explication: A 60 year old solution to a 50 year old problem. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 57–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge (1st ed.). Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J., & Cruz, J. (1999). Contemporary theories of knowledge (2nd ed.). Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning.’ Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, J. (2002). Thinking about knowing. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2015). Knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason. In Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 5, pp. 226–252).

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2008). Having reasons. Philosophical Studies, 139(1), 57–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2021). Reasons first. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956/1997). Empiricism & the philosophy of mind. Harvard University Press.

  • Shope, R. (1983). The analysis of knowing: A decade of research. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2012). Moore’s paradox and the accessibility of justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(2), 273–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2015). Why justification matters. In D. Henderson & J. Greco (Eds.), Epistemic evaluation: Purposeful epistmeology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2016). Reflection on: On reflection. Analysis, 76(1), 55–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M. (1996). An introduction to contemporary epistemology. Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swain, M. (1974). Epistemic defeasibility. American Philosophical Quarterly, 11(1), 15–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2010). On the relationship between propositional and doxastic justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(2), 312–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2003). What good are counterexamples? Philosophical Studies, 115(1), 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. (2017). Knowledge, noise and curve-fitting: A methodological argument for justified true belief? In R. Borges, C. de Almeida, & P. Klein (Eds.), Explaining knowledge: New essays on the Gettier problem (pp. 253–272). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. Philosophical Quarterly, 44(174), 65–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2017). The Lesson of Gettier. In R. Borges, C. de Almeida, & P. Klein (Eds.), Explaining knowledge: New essays on the Gettier problem (pp. 179–191). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’d like to thank Beth Barker, Regina Hurley, Jennifer Lackey, Nate Lauffer, Kathryn Pogin, Baron Reed, Tamler Sommers, Justin Zacek and two (incredibly helpful) anonymous referees for comments and helpful conversations. Most of all, thanks to Sandy Goldberg, for reading what must have been a dozen drafts over several years, and (somehow) getting contagiously excited each time he read a new one.

Funding

I have received no external funding for this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Spencer Paulson.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I have no conflicting interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Paulson, S. Good reasons are apparent to the knowing subject. Synthese 202, 15 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04242-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04242-y

Keywords

Navigation