Skip to main content
Log in

The fundamental reason for reasons fundamentalism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Reasons, it is often said, are king in contemporary normative theory. Some philosophers say not only that the vocabulary of reasons is useful, but that reasons play a fundamental explanatory role in normative theory—that many, most, or even all, other normative facts are grounded in facts about reasons. Even if reasons fundamentalism, the strongest version of this view, has only been wholeheartedly endorsed by a few philosophers, it has a kind of prominence in contemporary normative theory that suits it to be described as orthodoxy by its critics. It is the purpose of this paper to make progress toward understanding what appeal Reasons Fundamentalism should have, and whether that appeal is deserved. I will do so by exploring and comparing two central motivations for Reasons Fundamentalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Jonathan Adler (2002, 9) describes the thesis of evidentialism in epistemology as the view that “to (fully) believe that p one needs adequate reasons”. Similarly, according to Derek Parfit (1997, 209), one important form of egalitarianism is the view that “we always have a reason to prevent or reduce inequality, if we can”.

  2. Prominent proponents of something like this view have included Derek Parfit (2011), Jonathan Dancy (2004), and Mark Schroeder (2007).

  3. Here I follow Schroeder (2008). Many philosophers talk in terms of possessed reasons or reasons you ‘have’, but this talk is contentious and naturally interpreted as incorporating substantive commitments about the relationship between objective and subjective reasons, so it is best avoided.

  4. Dancy (2000) is naturally interpreted as accepting this view. See the discussion in Schroeder (2018a, 294–295).

  5. See, for example, Prior (1960).

  6. This example comes from Schroeder (2010).

  7. Sidgwick (1907) famously tries to use a monistic consequentialist theory, in order to explain many of the same things as Ross, but Ross has the advantage that he can offer the very same diagnosis of intuitive counterexamples to utilitarianism that he and Sidgwick both offer to intuitive counterexamples to absolute deontological principles. The advantage of pluralist consequentialism is that it can agree with Ross that it is not always best to maximize happiness.

  8. This argument comes from Schroeder (2011).

  9. They can’t be made alike in this respect, without the first person’s killing resulting in more killings, by preventing the preventions of killings, which undermines the force of the example.

  10. Many agent-relative teleologists arrive at their view more quickly, assuming that it is the only way to capture these cases of constraints. But as Oddie and Milne (1991) have shown, that is not exactly right. What is true, is that the assumptions required in order to reconcile constraints with traditional, agent-neutral consequentialism become increasingly implausible as assumptions about a notion of goodness about which we have some independent grasp. See Nair (2014) for a particularly good discussion of this point, and Setiya for a defense of the view that killings that prevent killings really are much worse than killings that do not.

  11. On Agent-Relative Teleology, see especially Sen (1983), Dreier (1993), Smith (2003), Louise (2004), and Portmore (2014).

  12. Compare especially Samuel Scheffler’s reasoning in The Rejection of Consequentialism, particularly at (1982, **-**).

  13. Dreier (2011), Oddie (2018), Milona and Schroeder (2019).

  14. Compare Wedgwood (2015).

  15. This is Setiya’s (2014) informal gloss on his account, which he goes on to spell out more precisely in other terms, but the idea of sound inferences forms the backbone of Silverstein’s (2016) account. This difference makes it likely that Silverstein’s account has better prospects to avoid the objection from elusive reasons explained below.

  16. Schroeder (2007, chapter 2).

  17. Sliwa (2012, 2016).

  18. King (2020).

  19. Sliwa (2016), King (2020).

  20. Compare Smith (2003, chapter 3), Arpaly (2002b).

  21. See especially Schroeder (2007, chapter 2) and (2009).

  22. Compare Schroeder (2018b).

  23. Markovits (2010, 2012), Arpaly (2002a, b), Arpaly and Schroeder (2013). An important fellow traveler is Stratton-Lake’s (2000) symmetry thesis, though Stratton-Lake follows what he takes to be Kant’s view in imposing a further condition on moral worth that is inspired by Barbara Herman and Marcia Baron’s distinction between primary and secondary motives.

  24. See especially Lehrer and Paxson (1969), Lehrer (1970), Klein (1971), Annis (1973), Ackerman (1974), Johnsen (1974), Swain (1974), Olin (1976), and Barker (1976). For a fairly comprehensive discussion of the problems confronted in this attempt to answer the problems posed by Gettier (1963), see Shope (1983), and for discussion of how defeasibility analyses of knowledge are a kind of right reasons account and diagnosis of where implementations of this idea in the 1970’s went wrong, see Schroeder (2015).

  25. Alston (1985).

  26. This is a familiar issue from the Gettier literature—see, for example, Swain (1981, chapter 4).

  27. Again, though not explored in recent literature on moral worth, similar issues have long been part of similar discussions in epistemology. See especially Lehrer (1974, chapter 6).

  28. Schroeder (2018b).

  29. Compare Markovits’ (2010, 227) case of the altruist and the reward-seeker, who both rush into a burning building for the reason that there is a child who needs to be saved. Arpaly’s (2002a, 240) case of Steve plays a similar role, though she uses it to make more points.

  30. Markovits: “We should understand the Coincident Reasons Thesis as pronouncing an action morally worthy whenever the noninstrumental reasons for which it is per- formed coincide with the noninstrumental reasons that morally justify its performance” (2010, 230). A similar feature comes out in Arpaly and Schroeder’s (2013) view that moral worth is exhibited by agents who act on intrinsic desires whose objects correspond to the reasons as articulated by the true moral theory.

  31. Broome (2004, 2013).

  32. Markovits (2010, 205).

  33. Compare Daniel Star (2011, 84): “Suppose, for the sake of a simple example, that the correct moral theory is hedonistic utilitarianism (needless to say, I do not actually think this is the correct moral theory). This theory would have it that the only ultimate reasons are facts about pain and pleasure. If an act would increase pleasure in the world then the fact that this act would increase pleasure is an ultimate reason to do it, while if an act would increase pain in the world then the fact that this act would increase pain is an ultimate reason not to do it. Furthermore, one ought to do those acts that increase the balance of pleasure over pain (according to the theory). Now consider the fact that a particular act is a lie. This normative theory says nothing about facts that are lies. However, the fact that this act is a lie is evidence that one ought not do it, and is thus also a derivative reason not to do it.”.

  34. Daniel Star (2011, 75): “Philosophers engaged in the project of normative ethics are not wasting their time when they search after highly general moral principles which could not be discovered or justifiably accepted through non-philosophical thinking, and which specify the good reasons on which virtuous people act, as well as provide a criterion or criteria for determining what it is that people ought to do.”.

  35. For Star (2011, 2015), reasons strictly speaking are evidence of what you ought to do—and as such they can play a role in an account of moral worth, because the right motive will always involve being sensitive to evidence of what you ought to do. Whereas the explainers of what you ought to do are more properly called ‘right-making features’, and are the proper objects of inquiry in explanatory moral theory, but bear no essential connection to worthy motivation.

  36. Wedgwood (2015) is also prominently skeptical that anything plays the dual roles of reasons.

  37. Reasons fundamentalism therefore denies what I have elsewhere called the ‘no background conditions’ view of reasons, whereas the cleanup view implies it. See Schroeder (2007, chapter 2).

References

  • Ackerman, T. (1974). Defeasibility modified. Philosophical Studies, 26(5–6), 431–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adler, J. (2002). Belief’s own ethics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (1985). Concepts of epistemic justification. Monist, 68(1), 57–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annis, D. (1973). Knowledge and defeasibility. Philosophical Studies, 24(3), 199–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (2002a). Moral worth. Journal of Philosophy, 99(5), 223–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (2002b). Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N., & Schroeder, T. (2013). In praise of desire. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, J. A. (1976). What you don’t know won’t hurt you? American Philosophical Quarterly, 13(4), 303–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2004). Reasons. In R. J. Wallace, et al. (Eds.), Reason and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz (pp. 204–228). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2000). Practical reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (1993). The structure of normative theories. Monist, 76, 22–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (2011). In defense of consequentializing. Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, 1, 97–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 1963, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, A. (2016). Normative reasons as good bases. Philosophical Studies, 173(9), 2291–2310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, N. R. (2019). One desire too many. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnsen, B. (1974). Knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 25(4), 273–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1971). A proposed definition of propositional knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 68(16), 471–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, Z. J. (2020). Accidentally doing the right thing. Philosophy and Phenomenlogical Research, 100(1), 186–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1986). Skepticism about practical reason. Journal of Philosophy, 83(1), 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1996). Kant’s analysis of obligation. In her Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 43–76.

  • Lehrer, K. (1970). The fourth condition of knowledge: A defense. Review of Metaphysics, 24(1), 122–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1974). Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Paxson, T. (1969). Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 225–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louise, J. (2004). Relativity of value and the consequentialist umbrella. Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 518–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markovits, J. (2010). Acting for the right reasons. Philosophical Review, 119(2), 201–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markovits, J. (2012). Saints, heroes, sages, and villains. Philosophical Studies, 158(2), 289–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milona, M., & Schroeder, M. (2019). Desiring under the proper guise. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 14, pp. 121–143).

  • Nair, S. (2014). A fault line in ethical theory. Philosophical Perspectives, 28 (Ethics), 173–200.

  • Oddie, G. (2018). Value perception, properties and the primary bearers of value. In A. Bergqvist & R. Cowan (Eds.), Evaluative perception: Aesthetic, ethical, and normative (pp. 239–257). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G., & Milne, P. (1991). Act and value: Expectation and the representability of moral theories. Theoria, 57(1–2), 42–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olin, D. (1976). Knowledge and defeasible justification. Philosophical Studies, 30(2), 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1997). Equality and priority. Ratio, 10(3), 202–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters, volumes 1 and 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore, D. (2014). Commonsense consequentialism: Wherein morality meets rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1960). The autonomy of ethics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 38(3), 199–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (1982). The rejection of consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2008). Having reasons. Philosophical Studies, 139(1), 57–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2009). ‘Buck-passers’ negative thesis’. Philosophical Explorations, 12(3), 341–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2010). Value and the right kind of reasons. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 5, 25–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2011). Holism, weight, and undercutting. Noûs, 454(2), 328–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2015). Knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason. Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 5, 226–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2018a). Getting perspective on objective reasons. Ethics, 128(2), 289–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2018b). Believing Well. In C. McHugh, J. Way, & D. Whiting (Eds.), Metaepistemology (pp. 196–212). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1983). Evaluator relativity and consequential evaluation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 12(1), 113–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2014). What is a reason to act? Philosophical Studies, 167(2), 221–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shope, R. (1983). The analysis of knowing: A decade of research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics (7th ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverstein, M. (2016). Reducing reasons. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 10(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sliwa, P. (2012). In defense of moral testimony. Philosophical Studies, 158(2), 175–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sliwa, P. (2016). Moral worth and moral knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(2), 393–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2003). Neutral and relative value after moore. Ethics, 113(3), 576–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Star, D. (2011). Two levels of moral thinking. Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, 1, 75–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stratton-Lake, P. (2000). Kant, duty, and moral worth. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swain, M. (1974). Epistemic defeasibility. American Philosophical Quarterly, 11(1), 15–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swain, M. (1981). Reasons and Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Way, Jonathan. (2017). Reasons as premises of good reasoning. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 98(2), 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2015). The pitfalls of ‘Reasons’. Philosophical Issues, 25(1), 123–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1979). Internal and external reasons. In H. Ross (Ed.), Rational action (pp. 101–113). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Special thanks to Nathan Howard, Stephen Finlay, and Ralph Wedgwood.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Schroeder.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schroeder, M. The fundamental reason for reasons fundamentalism. Philos Stud 178, 3107–3127 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01572-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01572-2

Keywords

Navigation