1 The standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy

Ordinary language philosophy is an approach to philosophical problems motivated by the thought that paying attention to the way that language is used in ordinary (that is, non-philosophical) talk can transform our understanding of traditional philosophical problems and reveal previously unasked questions that deserve philosophical attention.Footnote 1 There is a standard story told in histories of analytic philosophy about the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy: it was a widespread, if not dominant, approach to philosophy in Great Britain in the aftermath of World War II up until the early 1960s, but with the development of systematic approaches to the study of language—formal semantic theories on one hand and Gricean pragmatics on the other—ordinary language philosophy more or less disappeared (Chapman, 2005; Forguson, 2001; Mulhall, 1994, 2017; Parker-Ryan, 2012; Soames, 2003; Stanley, 2008; Travis, 1985; von Wright, 1993; Warnock, 1998):

[The label ‘ordinary language philosophy’] was supposed to identify a certain kind of philosophy that flourished…for twenty years or so, roughly after 1945. (Warnock, 1998)

Ordinary language philosophy flourished in Oxford from the late 1940’s to the early 1960’s. (von Wright, 1993, p. 40)

By the mid-1960s… [ordinary language philosophy] was already in decline…Ordinary language philosophy is now a historical movement, rather than an active force in contemporary philosophical discussion. (Forguson, 2001, p. 326)

How do we know whether the standard story about the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy is true? There are tens of thousands of articles in philosophy journals published since what is considered the heyday of ordinary language philosophy, and no one has examined them all for signs of life. Is it possible that ordinary language philosophy wasn’t killed off in the late 1960s, but survives into the present in the pages of those journals in a way overlooked in the standard story?

Working with the topic model of 32,183 philosophy articles in Weatherson (2022), we evaluate the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy. We build on Weatherson’s large dataset and carefully documented methodology by combining computational methods with a familiar kind of archival research—qualitative classifications, data organization, and reading. We find evidence that supports part of the standard story, but we argue there is also evidence of a “new wave” of ordinary language philosophy since the early 2000s, appearing in the guise of contextualist theories in epistemology and ethics and certain versions of experimental philosophy. The standard story needs to be rewritten: Ordinary language philosophy was not killed off in the 1960s; it went into hibernation for 30 years and has woken up in the twenty-first century.

2 Quantitative evidence and the standard story

Weatherson (2022) models the discourse in more than 30,000 philosophy articles drawn from 12 leading journals over the period 1876–2013.Footnote 2 In technical terms, he uses a Latent Dirichlet Allocation (LDA) to build a model of 90 topics using filtered lists of word frequencies for each article. The topics essentially represent the best guess of an algorithmic process that sorts articles based on the words they use. The results can be understood from the standpoint of the articles (which are assigned a probability of being “in” each topic), the words (which are assigned a probability of appearing in an idealized article from each topic), or the topics (which comprise these article and word weights). For example, Jessica Brown’s “Knowledge and Assertion” (2010) is assigned a 66% likelihood of being in the 74th topic, and the words most likely to appear in this topic include “knowing”, “skepticism”, and “epistemology.” On the basis of articles and words like these, Weatherson calls Topic 74 “Knowledge”.

Topic models depend on a mix of quantitative computational analysis and subjective judgment calls. The experimenter decides the number of topics that the model will find, as well as the subset of words from the corpus that will be included in the process. The method also involves randomization, which means similar parameters can produce substantially different results. Finally, the “topics” are statistically rather than conceptually derived; Topic 74 is really just a relationship between articles and words, and Weatherson’s decision to call it “Knowledge” depends on his own expertise and interpretation of the results. Weatherson is candid about the tradeoffs involved in making his decisions about which words to exclude, how many topics to include, and other adjustments needed to make a meaningful model (see Weatherson, 2022, Sect. 1), but for our purposes the important lesson to keep in mind is that the topic model data he has created depends on a combination of subjective and objective factors.Footnote 3

We build on Weatherson’s work, using his topic model classifications in part to take advantage of the substantial intellectual labor he has already expended and explained. Instead of creating our own topic model, our primary intervention will be the refinement of the way his model represents the history of ordinary language philosophy, which includes a lot of false positives (articles that are not really about or examples of ordinary language philosophy) and some false negatives (missing articles, especially toward the end of the period he covers, that are examples of, or are about, ordinary language philosophy). Ordinary language philosophy is only one of 90 areas of philosophical inquiry that Weatherson examines, so it makes sense that his model doesn’t track its trajectory with complete accuracy. Since we are focused just on this narrow field instead of trying to represent more than a century of philosophy in general, we can dig into the limitations of the generalized topic model approach. When we understand those limitations, we can work toward getting as accurate a picture of the historical trajectory of ordinary language philosophy as possible (in terms of articles in Weatherson’s corpus), giving us a more focused—narrower, but clearer—view of the history of this particular approach to philosophical problems.

Rather than automating the detection of ordinary language philosophy papers to arrive at something like a probabilistic prediction of the frequency of their publication, we wanted instead to surface as many examples as we could without leaving the specific articles behind—in other words, we wanted to base our identification of articles as ordinary language philosophy on their content, which required actually reading them. We chose this approach for three reasons. First, we wanted to build on the work Weatherson has already done. Second, our method is relatively easy to implement and understand, making it a useful site of simplicity in a complex inquiry. Finally, we were guided by the literary digital humanities scholar Lauren Klein’s observation that:

A topic model is, after all, a model. And for the model to be truly meaningful, domain experts—that’s us—must be able to probe the semantic associations that the model proposes, and seek out additional perspectives on the model, as well as on the archive itself.

Topic modeling, Klein says, is “a technique that stirs the archive”. In what follows, we use Weatherson’s topic model to stir the archive in search of ordinary language philosophy.Footnote 4

2.1 Weatherson’s Topic 24: “Ordinary Language Philosophy”

One of the most prominent topics in Weatherson’s model he labels “Ordinary Language Philosophy” (topic 24). Weatherson says that ordinary language philosophy has such a large presence in the journals he surveys that it “almost breaks the model” (Weatherson, 2022, Sect. 0).Footnote 5 And in the chart of weighted proportion of all articles (Weatherson, 2022, Fig. 3.2), “Ordinary Language Philosophy” (topic 24) displays a pattern that defies the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy: it does peak in the early 1960s, followed by a drop, but then it levels off and remains one of the largest topics through 2013 (the end of the period surveyed in Weatherson’s model).Footnote 6 It also appears that many articles in topic 24 appear before ordinary language philosophy becomes popular on the standard story, roughly the mid 1940s (see Fig. 1).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Weatherson (2022, Sect. 2.24) Topic 24, “Ordinary Language”, Weighted Proportion of Articles Over Time

Some commentators on Weatherson (2022) have taken the shape of Topic 24 to be a challenge for the standard story:

Ordinary language is a topic on the top five list for every decade, and is the most popular topic from the 1950s through the present. And yet “ordinary language philosophy” would generally be thought to have arisen in the 1940s and declined permanently in the 1960s.Footnote 7

What explains the conflict between Weatherson’s “Ordinary Language Philosophy” topic and the standard story?

While the results of the topic model frequently align with recognizable philosophical concepts, the model itself does not have a human-like grasp of word meanings or concepts. It simply tracks word frequencies and their variations in articles. As a result, it may capture linguistic phenomena that are not ultimately attributable to the discussion of particular philosophical content. Weatherson observes at several points in his book that what topic 24 is tracking is “as much a style as a topic” (Sects. 2; 2.47; 9.1):

The big assumption that drives the kind of model I’m building is that there is a one-one mapping between classes of articles with a distinctive vocabulary, and classes of articles with a distinctive subject matter. That often holds true, but it breaks quite spectacularly in 1950s Britain. A new language, shorn of pomp and circumstance, takes over. And my poor model thinks that all the philosophers have moved on to a wholly new subject matter. But they largely have not—they are just discussing the old subjects using new words. (Weatherson, 2022, Sect. 0)Footnote 8

That the topic that Weatherson labels “Ordinary Language Philosophy” is not really tracking the philosophical ideas that make something a work of ordinary language philosophy is evident from the 10 articles that the model assigns the highest probability to be in topic 24 (Table 1).

Table 1 Top 10 Articles in Weatherson (2022) Topic 24, “Ordinary Language Philosophy”

Out of these 10 articles classified as the most probable to belong to Weatherson’s Topic 24, the Broadie article “Trying and Doing”, Wisdom’s Inaugural Address to the Aristotelian Society, and Woozley’s “Knowing and Not Knowing” are examples of ordinary language philosophy, or criticisms of it: Broadie undertakes an analysis of the complexity of the expression “trying” in order to “[throw] a subtler light on the concept of action”, and Wisdom aims to disambiguate different ordinary interpretations of the question “Can one ever really know the mind of another?” as a way of dissolving the philosophical perplexity and feeling of difficulty that the question generates among philosophers. Both of these are paradigmatic ordinary language approaches to philosophical problems. A.D. Woozley’s article, “Knowing and Not Knowing”, is a clear example of an article criticizing ordinary language philosophy: it challenges the idea that we can draw conclusions about knowledge on the basis of how we ordinarily use the word “know” in assertions.

The other articles in the top 10 of topic 24 are a very mixed bag: The top two articles are both satirical: Lafleur’s “The R-Being” is an attempted reductio of the ontological argument by showing the absurdities that arise from imagining a being that has every property that begins with the letter “R”; Storer’s “Miniac: World’s Smallest Electronic Brain” gives “do-it-yourself plans for constructing a computer that will answer questions not resolvable by any other present machine”, where the instructions consist of gluing pieces of paper with “YES” and “NO” written on them to both sides of a coin. The Markosian and Sider articles concern a puzzle about what the best question would be to ask an omniscient angel if philosophers were given that opportunity. The “Reply to First and Second Thoughts in Moral Philosophy” by Ewing accuses his critic Warner of conflating epistemic and metaphysical senses of “might”. Williams’s “Reply to Professor Garnett” is a response to a comically uncharitable misconstrual of Williams’s utilitarian ethical theory.Footnote 9 Finally, Hughes’s “Report on Analysis ‘Problem’ No. 17” poses the question “Can I ever, by my subsequent actions, bring it about that something I did on a previous occasion was done from a certain motive rather than from some other one?”, which the author chose on the ground that in his experience it had provoked interesting discussion. But Hughes laments that in spite of how interesting he found the question, Analysis did not receive any attempts to answer it!Footnote 10

Weatherson points out that another measure of how topic 24 is not really picking out a substantial topic is that many of the list of highly cited articles that appear in topic 24 are “only loosely connected” to what would be considered ordinary language philosophy (Weatherson, 2022, Sect. 2.82). By our count, only 6 out of the top 30 most cited articles in topic 24 are examples of ordinary language philosophy, and the top 5 most cited articles in topic 24 include Frege’s “The Thought”, Michael Walzer’s “Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands”, and Frank Jackson’s “Epiphenomenal Qualia”, none of which are examples of ordinary language philosophy.

A further measure of the diffuseness of topic 24 is its high probability for articles across the board. On average, the model assigns each article about a 1% chance of being in a given topic, but this varies widely from one topic to the next. At the low end, articles are assigned to topic 79 (“Races and DNA”) just 0.4% of the time, or one out of every 250 articles. For topic 24, the average probability is 5.4%, the highest of any topic by a wide margin: If we draw an article at random, we have a better than one in twenty chance that it’s in topic 24.Footnote 11

Importantly, articles are assigned a likelihood for every topic. The prevalence of topic 24 doesn’t just mean that there are many articles in topic 24; it means that even articles assigned to some other topic are apt to have relatively high “topic 24 scores”. And in fact, “lots of topics are such that articles in them look a lot like Ordinary Language Philosophy [topic 24]”—that is, lots of topics display high “cross-topic probability” with topic 24:

For a pair of topics ⟨x,y⟩, look at the articles that are more likely in topic x than any other topic, and find the average probability that these articles are in y. (Weatherson, 2022, Sect. 8.5)

Of the 25 highest cross-topic probabilities that Weatherson charts with this method, ten involve topic 24. This is precisely what we would expect given the prevalence of the topic overall, but it underscores the notion that topic 24 reflects some kind of broader linguistic phenomenon than the “Ordinary Language Philosophy” name captures. It’s theoretically possible that ordinary language philosophy has had an unmatched, overwhelming presence in the entire field of philosophy over the past 130 years, but it seems more likely that topic 24 is charting something else.

These features of topic 24 mean that its continuing prevalence in Weatherson’s model up through 2013 does not pose a challenge to the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy, though Weatherson suggests that it may be tracking one important legacy of ordinary language philosophy, namely its lasting effect on the linguistic style in which analytic philosophy is written.

If the trajectory of topic 24 does not contribute to confirming or disconfirming the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy, is there any other evidence from the topic model that does? We think topic 22 (“Meaning and Use”) is the next best place to start to look for such evidence.

2.2 Topic 22: “Meaning and Use”/ “Wittgensteinian Philosophy of Language”

Topic 22, which Weatherson calls “Meaning and Use” or “Wittgensteinian philosophy of language”, is a better measure of ordinary language philosophy, rather than the ordinary style of writing philosophical prose that topic 24 appears to be tracking.Footnote 12 The weighted proportion of articles in topic 22 over time mirrors the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy, peaking in the early 1960s and then rapidly declining (see Fig. 2).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Weatherson (2022, Sect. 2.22) Topic 22 “Meaning and Use”, Weighted Proportion of Articles over Time

The top 10 most likely articles to appear in topic 22 contain four articles that are clear examples of ordinary language philosophy, or criticisms of ordinary language philosophy:

Author

Title

Year

Journal

Alan R. White

The Use of Sentences

1956

Analysis

John Passmore

Professor Ryle’s Use of “Use” and “Usage”

1954

Philosophical Review

Manley Thompson

When Is Ordinary Language Reformed?

1961

Journal of Philosophy

Norman Malcolm

Moore’s Use of “Know”

1953

Mind

Three of the top 10 articles are examples of Wittgenstein exegesis:

Author

Title

Year

Journal

Cora Diamond

Logical Syntax in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus

2005

The Philosophical Quarterly

Carolyn Black

Philosophical Investigations Remark 43 Revisited

1974

Mind

Leonard Linsky

Wittgenstein on Language and Some Problems of Philosophy

1957

The Journal of Philosophy

Wittgenstein’s relationship to paradigmatic ordinary language philosophy is contested.Footnote 13 For example, Dummett (1978, p. 433) claims that “Wittgenstein’s later philosophy is totally distinct both from logical positivism and from the ordinary language movement”, while Cavell (1962) makes the case for some significant overlap between ordinary language philosophers like Ryle and Austin and Wittgenstein in the way that ordinary language is appealed to in approaching philosophical problems.

Some of the articles that concern Wittgenstein clearly should be counted as examples of ordinary language philosophy, like those articles that relate Wittgenstein to the methodology of ordinary language philosophy (paradigmatically Cavell, 1962), and work inspired by Wittgenstein that concerns aspects of ordinary language (Wisdom, 1936, Waismann, 1951, for example). Some of the articles that concern Wittgenstein are not as obviously examples of ordinary language philosophy, like articles that are primarily interpretations of the private language argument. We decided to include work about Wittgenstein’s middle period and late philosophy in our count of articles about ordinary language philosophy, but we also tagged these articles as being about Wittgenstein, so it would be easy to exclude them from the overall count if someone wanted to see what the overall trajectory of ordinary language philosophy looks like without Wittgenstein exegesis (see Fig. 4 for the count of articles tagged as being about later Wittgenstein over time).

The remaining three articles in the top 10 of Weatherson’s topic 24 concern Saussure’s comparison of language with the game of chess, Carnap’s “formal mode of speech”, and “heterological” and “homological” predicates—that is, predicates that refer to properties that either do or do not apply to the predicate itself.

Author

Title

Year

Journal

Maurice Mandelbaum

Language and Chess: De Saussure’s Analogy

1968

The Philosophical Review

C.D. Hardie

The Formal Mode of Speech

1936

Analysis

Joshua C. Gregory

Heterological and Homological

1952

Mind

Weatherson’s topic 22 is collecting several distinct philosophical debates, so we can’t draw conclusions about the accuracy of the standard story just from the rise and fall of this topic in Weatherson’s model. Moreover, topic 22 is the fifth most common topic overall. So while it is not as common as topic 24, it is still relatively likely to appear as a significant topic for articles across the board. Again, this points to the possibility that it doesn’t reflect the kind of narrow conceptual focus that other topics seem to display. What unity there is in topic 22 seems to be a focus on metalinguistic facts: facts about words, about use (and “usage”), and about word meaning.

So what use are these automatically assembled topics for understanding the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy if they collect what philosophers would consider distinct philosophical debates together? We think the best use of LDA in understanding the history of philosophy is as a method of directing attention to overlooked parts of the history of philosophy, a “tool for reading”Footnote 14:

Effective use of topic models depends on validation by human coders to avoid ‘reading the tea leaves’—finding spurious, meaningless patterns—that can be created by unsupervised models. The results produced by an algorithm should never be the end game of research: instead, these results should provoke further interpretive analysis. (Mohr et al., 2020, p. 171)

Using Weatherson’s topics 22 and 24 as tools for reading, for “stirring the archive”, we can sift through thousands of articles ordered in terms of their likelihood of belonging to those topics and “hand code” articles that are clearly examples of ordinary language philosophy. The resulting list of articles that are clear examples of ordinary language philosophy will begin to give us a way of verifying the standard story within the corpus of articles collected in Weatherson (2022).

3 Hand-coding examples of ordinary language philosophy using Weatherson’s Topics 22 and 24

To get a sense of how far down the list of articles in Weatherson’s topics we need to look to find examples of ordinary language philosophy, we can begin by picking out some canonical examples in Weatherson’s corpus and seeing where they are located in topics 22 and 24. Table 2, below, is a list of canonical articles in ordinary language philosophy or criticisms of ordinary language philosophy, assembled from articles included in Weatherson (2022) that are cited in either the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on ordinary language philosophy (Parker-Ryan, 2012) or in the chapters on ordinary language philosophy in Soames’s history of analytic philosophy (Soames, 2003). Articles are presented together with their ranking in Weatherson’s topic 22 and 24.

Table 2 Canonical ordinary language philosophy articles in Weatherson (2022)

If anything counts as practicing ordinary language philosophy or as critically discussing it, these articles do. Weatherson’s models do a reasonably good job capturing these canonical articles, placing most of them in the top 3% of articles in one or both of topics 22 and 24. But finding relevant articles even in the top 1% of articles in a topic still requires a large amount of human effort—it means reading between 300 and 900 articles. The rankings of these canonical examples of ordinary language philosophy in topics 22 and 24 reveal that we will need to look beyond the top few hundred articles in each topic to get a survey of articles that are clearly examples of, or criticisms of, ordinary language philosophy.

But we also want to identify articles that fall outside the canon, because only then will we begin to get an accurate sense of the trajectory of articles in ordinary language philosophy that were published in the 20th and early twenty-first centuries. And looking systematically at the top articles in both Weatherson’s category 22 and 24 is indeed an effective tool for reading, a way of stirring the archive to uncover some non-canonical works in ordinary language philosophy.

For example, consider the first article outside the top 10 in topic 22, C.H. Whiteley’s “Mr. Warnock on Ordinary Language”. This is not a canonical article on ordinary language philosophy by any measure—it has only been cited twice in 61 years.Footnote 15 But it is an impressively concise (3 pages!) survey of problems with the methodology of ordinary language philosophy as it is standardly understood. It begins by quoting a passage from Warnock’s English Philosophy Since 1900, which is a less cautious restatement of a more famous passage from Austin’s “A Plea for Excuses”, setting out one of the important assumptions behind the ordinary language method:

It [ordinary language] is to be used for a vast number of highly important purposes; and it is at the very least unlikely that it should contain either much more, or much less, than those purposes require. If so, the existence of a number of different ways of speaking is very likely indeed to be an indication that there is a number of different things to be said…Where the topic at issue really is one that does constantly concern most people in some practical way—as for example perception, the ascription of responsibility, or the assessment of human character and conduct—then it is certain that everyday language is as it is for some extremely good reasons; its verbal variety is certain to provide clues to important distinctions. (Warnock, 1958, p. 151)

Whiteley criticizes the assumption that the existence of a rich vocabulary describing some area of practical concern is evidence that there is an equally rich variety of different features to be described by that vocabulary; for example, a rich vocabulary can be due to historical linguistic influences or non-semantic considerations like sociolinguistic register or politeness. English, for instance, possesses both Romance and Germanic versions of many expressions, and the distinction marked between, e.g., “napkin” and “serviette” is not a matter of the objects being referred to but of register. Austin’s (1956) famous distinction between “mistake” and “accident” also identifies expressions on either side of this etymological divide.

Consider another non-canonical (5 citations in 59 years) example of ordinary language philosophy that turns up when looking at the top articles in Weatherson’s topic 22: Philip P. Hallie’s “The Privacy of Experience”. This article begins with what we consider to be a perfectly generic statement of a project in ordinary language philosophy (in the sense of expressing features of the genre): it claims that (a) philosophers use a key expression (“private”) differently from the ways it is ordinarily used, (b) confusions arise as a result of departing from ordinary use, and (c) those confusions can be resolved by pointing out the difference between philosophers’ use and ordinary use:

Current controversies over the privacy of experience use the crucial term “private” in queer ways, in ways radically different from the ways it is used in plain talk. Words like “occult,” “inner,” “unverifiable” are assumed by the controversialists to be synonymous with that term; but as a matter of fact this synonymy does not hold in ordinary speech. In fact, the meaning of the term is being quietly but radically transformed when it is taken as synonymous with such words. What I should like to point out here is first of all the nature of this transformation, that is, the difference between privacy and what our controversialists are arguing about. Then I should like to show how confusions arise in the arguments when this difference is ignored. And finally, I should like to indicate how these confusions can be cleared up by our becoming aware both of this difference and of the everyday meaning of the word “private.” (Hallie, 1961, p. 337)

This generic structure appears in other non-canonical articles in the Weatherson corpus, like A.N. Flew’s “Selves” (1949)Footnote 16:

I want to do two things: first, to draw attention to the oddness of the words which philosophers, apparently without any realisation of their peculiarity, habitually use in discussing problems about “selves”; and, second, to show the dangers of using such a perverse and perplexing vocabulary, and by doing this to hint that many of the difficulties of problems of “the self” might dissolve, if only philosophers would “express themselves in the clearest, plainest and most familiar manner, abstaining from all hard or unusual terms”. (p. 355)

Discussions of ordinary language philosophy often include a disclaimer about it not being a philosophical “school” with doctrines shared among all its practitioners (see Dummett, 1978, p. 431, for example). When we identify an article as a work of (or criticism of) ordinary language philosophy, we are not claiming its membership in a philosophical “school”, but rather identifying it as a member of a philosophical genre, within which individual variation takes place:

Think of a Western movie, or a musical, or a gangster film. Probably you won’t think of any individual Western or musical or gangster film, but rather of a vaguely defined amalgam of actions and attitudes, of characters or locales. For as one sees more genre films, one tends to negotiate the genre less by its individual films than by its deep structure, those rules and conventions which render this film a Western and that film a musical. (Schatz, 1981, p. 18)

The shared structure that qualifies something as an example of ordinary language philosophy is a commitment to the idea that attention to the details of ordinary, non-philosophical use of language has substantial philosophical payoffs.

There are many more forgotten examples of ordinary language philosophy in the Weatherson corpus. Using topics 22 and 24 as tools for reading, we uncovered scores of noncanonical articles that start to fill out the standard story about the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy. But even though we found many articles by reading through the lists for topics 22 and 24, the process was slow enough that we wanted to develop a more targeted method, one that could find examples of ordinary language philosophy by building on the resources of Weatherson's entire 90-topic model.

4 Hand coding ordinary language philosophy articles using a 90-topic similarity measure

As we saw with the cross-topic probabilities of topic 24, articles are assigned a probability of belonging to every topic, and although it is often useful to think of a given article as being in a single topic (whichever one the model considers maximally probable), in reality the picture is more complex. Weatherson makes this point in relation to the model’s classification of an article on Kantian aesthetics:

Even for articles that you or I would say are unambiguously articles about Kant, the model is rarely more than 40% confident that that’s what they are about. And this is for a good reason. Most articles about Kant in philosophy journals are, naturally enough, about Kantian philosophy. And any part of Kantian philosophy is, well, philosophy. So the model has a topic on Beauty, and when it sees an article on Kantian aesthetics, it gives some probability the correct classification of that article is in the topic on Beauty. (Sect. 1)

In other words, single topics may be useful for a summary view, but we can arrive at a more detailed understanding of a specific paper by looking at its distinctive mixture of all of the topics. We know, for example, that Ryle’s “Use, Usage, and Meaning” (1961) is an article that concerns ordinary language philosophy. Articles similar to it seem likely to have something to do with ordinary language philosophy as well. We can check topic 24 to see which articles have the most similar scores to Ryle’s, but this will only take us so far. In fact, the closest paper by that metric is Ernest Gellner’s “Time And Theory In Social Anthropology” (1958). While Gellner was an acerbic critic of ordinary language philosophy, this article is a critique of the philosophical assumptions operative in E.R. Leach’s Political Systems of Highland Burma (1954), in particular Leach’s belief that the precise concepts employed by anthropologists necessarily distort the messy social realities they are used to describe.Footnote 17

The fact that the most similar article to Ryle’s “Use, Usage, and Meaning” in topic 24 does not concern ordinary language philosophy is not surprising given what we know about the multivalence of topic 24. Yet even if topic 24 had a laser-like focus on a single philosophical issue, writing like Ryle does not just mean using the language of ordinary language philosophy exactly as much as he does. For instance, “Use, Usage, and Meaning” also has a fairly high score on topic 6 (“Definitions”), so any other philosopher who uses topic 6 language at a similar rate may come across as more Rylean (or at least, more similar to the “Usage” article) than a philosopher who does not. To be closest of all to Ryle, it would help to use both topics at a Rylean rate, even if neither is quite an exact match, in the same way that a point at (3,15) on an ordinary Cartesian plane will be closer to a point at (2,12) than it is to points at (3,0) or (100,15). This will hold true if we add another topic with a high score in this paper—say, topic 78 (“Concepts”)—which is equivalent in our Cartesian example to adding a z-axis. And the most precise picture of proximity would take into account the score on every one of Weatherson’s 90 topics.

In short, we can consider the probability of being assigned to each topic to be a dimension, treat our universe of papers as a 90-dimensional space, and calculate the distance between articles on that basis.Footnote 18 It’s impossible to picture a 90-dimensional space, but calculating distance within it is straightforward given the right tools.Footnote 19 For example, the ten closest articles to “Use, Usage and Meaning” according to this method appear in Table 3.

Table 3 Most Similar Articles to Ryle, “Use, Usage, and Meaning”, comparing probabilities of being assigned to all 90 topics in Weatherson (2022)

This is a strikingly focused group of articles concerning the role of different understandings of linguistic “use” or “usage” as it bears on the practice of ordinary language philosophy.

In “Ordinary Language” (1953), Ryle spells out what his concern with “ordinary” language amounts to, namely the “standard” or “stock” uses of expressions, as opposed to “non-standard”, “non-stock” uses of those expressions. He distinguishes between the “use” and the “usage” of an expression, where “use” is a normative notion that contrasts with misuse, while “a usage” is:

a custom, practice, fashion or vogue. It can be local or widespread, obsolete or current, rural or urban, vulgar or academic. There cannot be a misusage any more than there can be a miscustom or a misvogue. The methods of discovering linguistic usages are the methods of philologists (pp. 174–175).

(That is, philologists and not philosophers.)

In contrast, P.L. Heath’s “The Appeal to Ordinary Language” (1952), which doesn’t distinguish between “use” and “usage”, criticizes some ordinary language philosophers’ reliance on “standard” or “correct” usage on the grounds that expressions of ordinary language are frequently vague and ambiguous, and so attempting to identify a single, clear “standard” use is misguided: “For whatever usages be laid down as correct, it is nearly always possible to produce counter-examples of an unimpeachable ordinariness and legitimacy” (p. 7). Heath’s “Wittgenstein Investigated” (1956) is a critical review of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations that, among a long list of objections, argues that the expressions “use” and “meaning” are “highly ambiguous”, which he argues leads to problems for Wittgenstein’s famous claim in the Philosophical Investigations that “for a large class of cases…the meaning of a word is its use in the language [Sect. 43]” (p. 69).

Both C.D. Rollins’s “Ordinary Language and Procrustean Beds” (1951) and A.D. Woozley’s “Ordinary Language and Common Sense” are responses to Norman Malcolm’s (1949) argument that when G.E. Moore (1939) offered a refutation of skepticism by holding up each of his hands and then saying “I do know that I held up two hands above this desk not very long ago” (as an example of something that he knows), Moore was guilty of “a radical departure from ordinary and correct usage”, a “misuse of language”, and asserting something “without sense”.

Bertrand Russell’s “The Cult of ‘Common Usage’” (1953) presents a caricature of ordinary language philosophy, as follows:

The doctrine, as I understand it, consists in maintaining that the language of daily life, with words used in their ordinary meanings, suffices for philosophy, which has no need of technical terms or of changes in the signification of common terms. (p. 303)

By way of criticism of this doctrine, Russell tells a “fable” involving a dialogue between an ordinary speaker (a “bedmaker”), who has observed a Professor going into a “dangerous frenzy” and being taken away in an ambulance:

[I]t happened that I, who live on the professor’s staircase, overheard the following dialogue between the bedmaker and the policeman:

Policeman: ’Ere, I want a word with yer.

Bedmaker: What do you mean? ‘A word’? I ain’t done nothing.

Policeman: Ah, that's just it—Yer ought to ’ave done something. Couldn’t yer see the pore gentleman was mental?

Bedmaker: That I could. For an ’ole hour ’e went on something chronic. But when they're mental you can’t make them understand.

In this little dialogue, ‘word’, ‘mean’, ‘mental’, and ‘chronic’ are all used in accordance with common usage. They are not so used in the pages of Mind by those who pretend that common usage is what they believe in. What in fact they believe in is not common usage, as determined by mass observation, statistics, medians, standard deviations, and the rest of the apparatus. What they believe in is the usage of persons who have their amount of education, neither more nor less—less is illiteracy, more is pedantry—so we are given to understand. (p. 304)

O.P. Wood’s little-known essay (2 citations in 70 years), “The Force of Linguistic Rules” (1951), maintains that questions about “what we would say” “or what we do say” are only philosophically interesting insofar as they are questions about “what is the correct use of the word”, and not as contributions to a scientific theory of semantics (pp. 325–326). This claim seems to anticipate Ryle’s distinction between “use” (standard or correct use) and “usage” (which is only of interest to philologists, not philosophers).

C.W.K. Mundle’s “‘Private Language’ And Wittgenstein’s Kind of Behaviourism” (1966) argues that Wittgenstein’s private language argument conflates different senses of “private”, and that Rush Rhees’s (1954) defense of the private language argument against Ayer’s criticisms ignores the way that expressions like “remembering that” and “doubting whether” are actually used in ordinary speech. According to Mundle, “Rhees is denying facts about English usage because these are inconsistent with Wittgenstein's theory of meaning!” (p. 43).Footnote 20

C.G. New’s “A Plea for Linguistics” (1966) criticizes J.L. Austin’s armchair methods of collecting evidence of ordinary usage in “A Plea for Excuses” (1956) as being insufficiently empirically-informed and “frequently prescriptive” (p. 371), and advocates adopting the methods of corpus linguistics. The armchair method used by Austin only tells us “what we think we do with words” and not “what we actually do with them” (p. 375). New illustrates the limitations of the armchair method by pointing out that Austin’s own use of the term “mistake” is not in accord with the account he gives of its meaning in “A Plea for Excuses” (p. 382).

Finally, D.M. Taylor’s “Meaning and the Use of Words” (1967), which appears to have never been cited, attempts to specify a precise sense in which a word may be said to have a “use”, and then describe conditions under which two words have the same “use” on the precisified sense of “use”.

Given the impressive focus of these results, we used the 90-dimensional similarity scores to develop a dialectical approach to identifying more articles about ordinary language philosophy in Weatherson's corpus. From any one article like Ryle's, the similarity scores point toward as many as several dozen additional examples. These can then serve as the basis for additional similarity scores, which produce new examples, and so on.

We applied the 90-dimensional similarity measurement to Weatherson’s corpus in the following iterated way: First, we took the list of canonical ordinary language philosophy articles (Table 2) and generated a list of the 50 most similar articles for each article in that list. Call those articles that appear in at least one of those top-50 most similar lists prospective articles (they may or may not actually be examples of ordinary language philosophy). Prospective articles could appear in multiple top 50 lists. For example, Judith Jarvis’s “Notes On Strawson's Logic” (1961) was one of the 50 most similar articles to Ryle (1932), Austin et al. (1950), and Strawson (1950a, 1950b). We read the 105 prospective articles that appeared in at least two top 50 lists, tagging those that really were about ordinary language philosophy (examples of ordinary language philosophy or criticisms of it). This resulted in a list of 85 newly coded ordinary language philosophy articles. We then repeated this process, gathering all articles that appeared in at least two top-50 lists for our new, larger roster of tagged ordinary language philosophy articles. This produced a significantly longer list of prospective articles, since there were many more top-50 lists to be a part of. At the same time, the list contained more articles that we had already seen. By the third iteration of the process, we had 977 prospective articles, including 189 we had already tagged as “not ordinary language philosophy” and 255 we had already tagged as ordinary language philosophy.

This process could have gone on much longer, quickly reaching an intractable size for human tagging. We actually examined every paper we tagged, so dealing with 1,000 examples was already quite daunting. And with each iteration of the process of finding articles similar to those we had already tagged as ordinary language philosophy we were reaching a more peripheral set of prospective articles—those similar to those similar to those similar to our original “canonical” list in our third iteration.

While our approach uncovered hundreds of examples of ordinary language philosophy, no list would be exhaustive in a non-controversial way, since the boundaries of “being an ordinary language philosophy paper” are vague, and expert human readers will disagree about whether to classify some articles as ordinary language philosophy. In the pursuit of what Pääkkönen and Ylikoski (2021, p. 1487) call “objectivity through transparency”, we welcome debate about the appropriateness of our judgments to include any of the hundreds of papers that we identify as examples, discussions, or criticisms of ordinary language philosophy (see Appendix A for the full list).

Other methods might have achieved greater coverage at the cost of less certainty: Training a classifier on features beyond the topics might have enabled us to identify hundreds of articles automatically, with spot checking providing some sense of the accuracy. We preferred the certainty and familiarity our more qualitative approach affords. So, given the practical difficulty of going further and the achievement of our initial goal of finding many ordinary language philosophy articles, we stopped our search after three iterations of the similarity measurement. That process generated a large, systematically produced, and hand-classified list of ordinary language philosophy papers that can help us understand the historical trajectory of ordinary language philosophy in Weatherson’s corpus over time.

Combined with our earlier searches through the top articles in Weatherson’s topics 22 and 24, this new method resulted in 402 total articles tagged as being about ordinary language philosophy. (See Appendix A for the full list.)

Plotting the hand-coded examples of ordinary language philosophy over time produces a chart that confirms the outline of the standard story: the number of ordinary language articles begins a steep climb after World War 2, is at its height from 1950 to 1965, and sharply drops off by the early 1970s (see Fig. 3).

Fig. 3
figure 3

Number of hand-coded ordinary language philosophy articles over timeFootnote

We also examined the number of ordinary language philosophy articles as a percentage of all articles published, to control for the possibility that changes were driven by overall changes in the number of philosophy articles over time. Though the figures told a similar story (aside from somewhat less prominence for ordinary language philosophy in the 1960s compared to the 1950s), we decided to show the raw numbers on the theory that the existence of ordinary language articles is important for our purposes irrespective of the number of articles being published about other philosophical topics.

Fig. 4
figure 4

Number of hand-coded papers about Wittgenstein, distinguished from non-Wittgensteinian ordinary language philosophy, over time

We can also see in which journals most of the mid-century ordinary language articles appeared (see Table 4). Only two of the journals in Weatherson’s corpus did not publish any articles we coded as ordinary language philosophy, namely Philosophy of Science and Philosophy and Public Affairs.

Table 4 Number of ordinary language articles appearing in different journals in Weatherson (2022)

5 New wave ordinary language philosophy: epistemic contextualism and some experimental philosophy

One of the bigger debates that plays out among the ordinary language philosophy articles in Weatherson (2022) concerns Norman Malcolm’s criticism of G.E. Moore’s “Defense of Common Sense” (1925) and “Proof of an External World” (1939), in which Malcolm claims that Moore’s use of the word “know” is “a radical departure from ordinary usage” (Malcolm, 1949). Table 5, below, is the list of all articles tagged as ordinary language philosophy that concern Malcolm’s criticism of Moore in Weatherson (2022), compiled in the course of hand-tagging examples of ordinary language philosophy discussed in the previous section:

Table 5 The debate over Malcolm’s criticism of Moore’s use of “know”

One article that sticks out in this table is Allan Hazlett’s 2009 paper “Knowledge and Conversation”, which revisits the debate about Malcolm’s criticism of Moore’s use of “know”. There is a gap of 44 years from the last article published on the debate in the 1960s and the publication of Hazlett’s article. Hazlett uses Grice’s (1975) theory of conversational implicature to criticize Malcolm’s claims about the proper use of “know”, but his article does not depart substantially from the issues discussed by the other articles in Table 5—it is clearly a paper engaged with central questions about the methodology of ordinary language philosophy and its relevance to debates about the nature of knowledge.

There is continuity in the underlying debate about the relation between the ordinary use of the word “know” and the nature of knowledge from the 1940s through the 2000s, but as Weatherson puts it, “It turns out that the language of twenty-first century philosophy is rather different from the language of twentieth-century philosophy” (Sect. 9.2), especially in the dramatically greater rate at which twenty-first century philosophers use expressions like “commitment”, “claim”, “account”, “role”, “challenge”, and “relevant” in contrast with their mid-twentieth century counterparts (Sect. 9.3).Footnote 22 The change in philosophical “buzzwords” makes it hard for Weatherson’s model to identify an underlying continuity, because all it is tracking is the frequency with which words occur.

To properly verify the accuracy of the standard story of the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy, we need to be able to identify those articles that continue ordinary language debates even when their language has changed from the middle of the twentieth century. Topics 22 and 24 won’t help identify examples of “new wave” ordinary language philosophy. We need to focus on the arguments of these papers to uncover the status of ordinary language philosophy in the twenty-first century.

New wave ordinary language philosophy consists of two distinct projects that are continuous with classic ordinary language philosophy: a constructive project that uses facts about the way expressions are used outside philosophical debates as the foundation for conclusions about topics of philosophical interest, and a critical project that argues that philosophers are prone to fall into confusion or produce nonsense insofar as they depart from the way expressions are ordinarily used. The constructive project is a descendant of J.L. Austin’s use of a “sharpened awareness of words’ to ‘sharpen our perception of…the phenomena” (Austin, 1956, p. 8), and the critical project takes its inspiration from classic claims like Wittgenstein’s (1969, Sect. 10) that when one is sitting at a sick man’s bedside, looking attentively into his face, neither the assertion “I know that a sick man is lying here” nor the question “So I don’t know, then, that there is a sick man lying here?” makes sense and Austin’s (1962, p. 15) argument that the word “directly” has been ‘stretched’ by philosophers to the point that it has become “meaningless” (Hansen, 2014, p. 556).

Citing facts about the way ordinary speakers ascribe or deny knowledge using the word “know” as evidence for or against theories about the nature of knowledge is the paradigmatic example of the constructive project in contemporary ordinary language philosophy. For example, another Hazlett paper, “The Myth of Factive Verbs” (2010), is also explicitly concerned with ordinary language philosophy. It begins as follows:

At least since the days of ‘ordinary language philosophy’, epistemologists (some more than others) have been interested in knowledge attributions—the meaning or meanings of ‘knows’, the use or uses of sentences of the form ‘S knows p’, and so on. And there has more recently been renewed interest in how ‘knows’ is used. (Hazlett, 2010, p. 497)

Hazlett attributes the renewed interest in how the word “knows” is used to the rise of epistemic contextualism. Epistemic contextualism is the view that “knows” varies its extension in different contexts of use, so that someone can count as knowing that she has hands in ordinary contexts, and not count as knowing that she has hands when the standards for knowledge are raised, as they are in discussions of skeptical possibilities.Footnote 23 Epistemic contextualism involves both an explicitly linguistic thesis about the ordinary use of “knows”, and an inference to the nature of knowledge on the basis of that ordinary use. The most influential article in the development of epistemic contextualism that appears in Weatherson’s corpus is DeRose (1992), which begins by making observations about the way ordinary speakers would make knowledge ascriptions and knowledge denials, and argues that those facts both contribute to an explanation of the appeal of skeptical arguments and provide a foundation for a response to such arguments.

DeRose (2005) explicitly claims that his approach to epistemic contextualism is a form of ordinary language philosophy (p. 174) and he gives a particularly clear statement of how epistemic contextualism draws on ordinary language resources:

The best grounds for accepting contextualism concerning knowledge attributions come from how knowledge-attributing (and knowledge-denying) sentences are used in ordinary, non-philosophical talk: what ordinary speakers will count as ‘knowledge’ in some non-philosophical contexts they will deny is such in others. (DeRose, 2005, p. 172).

The rise of epistemic contextualism in the 1990s and 2000s and the challenges to its methodology based on observations about the way “know” is ordinarily used needs to be part of the story of ordinary language philosophy. The language in which the debate is conducted is different from mid-twentieth century debates, but the arguments are continuous with those classic debates.

One twenty-first century twist on traditional ordinary language methods is the use of formal experimental methods to survey ordinary use. These experimental approaches to verifying ordinary use are based on the assumption that “Claims about ‘what ordinary speakers will count as “knowledge”’ (DeRose, 2005, p. 72) are empirical claims, which can be tested” (Schaffer & Knobe, 2012, p. 4). Schaffer and Knobe (2012) discuss experimental surveys that seem to show that ordinary speakers make judgments about whether speakers “know” things that conflict with the claims about ordinary use made by epistemic contextualists. They conduct an experimental survey that they interpret as providing evidence in favor of their distinctive form of contextualism (“contrastivism”). Since the middle of the twentieth century, it has been disputed whether quantitative surveys of how speakers do in fact talk are the right way to study “ordinary use” (Cavell, 1958, 1965; Hansen, 2017; Longworth, 2018; Ryle, 1961; Sandis, 2021), but however those debates are resolved, the debates concern the proper methodology of ordinary language philosophy, and so they should be included in our counts of articles practicing or criticizing ordinary language philosophy.

Consider the debate surrounding “the Knobe Effect”, in which ordinary speakers’ judgements about whether side-effects of actions are done intentionally or not appear sensitive to their moral assessment of the side effects. Knobe (2003, p. 190) claims that what ordinary speakers are inclined to say about such cases is a good way (if not the only good way) of investigating how we think about intentional action:

Now, when we encounter a controversy like this one [about whether side effects can be brought about intentionally], it can sometimes be helpful to ask ourselves what people would ordinarily say about the situation under discussion. Would people ordinarily say that the side effects of a behaviour were brought about intentionally? Clearly, ordinary language does not here constitute a court of final appeal. (Even if it turns out that people ordinarily call side effects ‘intentional’, we might conclude that they are truly unintentional.) Still, it does seem plausible that the examination of ordinary language might provide us with some useful guidance about difficult cases like this one.

Familiar questions from old debates about ordinary language philosophy were immediately raised about Knobe’s approach to investigating the concept of intentional action. For example, Adams and Steadman (2004) argue that Knobe hasn’t identified facts about the “core concepts” of intentional action, but rather “pragmatic aspects of intentional language and its role in moral praise and blame”. This is a standard response to ordinary language approaches to philosophical questions, usually attributed to Grice (1961, 1975), but which can be found in even earlier mid-twentieth century criticisms of ordinary language philosophy (Mates, 1958; Whiteley, 1959).

New wave debates in ordinary language philosophy differ from classic debates in that they are situated against the background of Gricean pragmatics or debates about the semantics-pragmatics interface highlighted by theories and criticisms of epistemic contextualism.Footnote 24 Jessica Brown’s (2006) criticism of contextualist theories of knowledge, for example, argues that the facts about how ordinary speakers use “know” can be better explained using the Gricean maxim of relevance, instead of DeRose’s preferred explanation in terms of the semantics of “know”. All of the examples that we classify as new wave ordinary language philosophy engage with Grice’s challenge to ordinary language philosophy, or with observational or experimental data about language use as it bears on philosophical questions.

The most direct and sustained engagement with Grice’s arguments against ordinary language philosophy in Weatherson’s corpus is Travis (1991), a critical review of Grice’s Studies in the Way of Words (1989). Travis pushes back against Grice’s criticisms of ordinary language philosophy by arguing that Grice’s distinction between what is said and what is implicated by the use of a sentence relies on a notion of what is said by a sentence that both Austin and Wittgenstein criticize. Without Grice’s stable notion of what is said, Travis argues that the distinction between saying and implicating breaks down, and with it Grice’s main resource for criticizing ordinary language philosophy. Travis (1996) provides additional arguments for the idea that what is said by uses of a sentence isn’t determined by the conventional meaning of the sentence, and Travis explicitly says that his arguments are inspired by Austin: “It would be fair to view this essay as no more than a working out of some ideas of J.L. Austin” (Travis, 1996, p. 451 n.1).

There are also examples of new wave versions of the more radical “critical” project of ordinary language philosophy (Hansen, 2014, 2020), which involves charging philosophers with speaking nonsense or saying things that are meaningless or failing to say anything at all as a result of straying too far from ordinary contexts of use. Kaplan (1991) argues that the notion of justification as it is standardly used in analytic epistemology floats so free of ordinary interests and constraints on answers that no meaningful account of such a “pure”, “extraordinary” notion can be given. He describes the criticism of the “pure” view of justification as “Austinian/Wittgensteinian” (p. 153). And Kaplan (2000) responds to Barry Stroud’s (1984) influential Grice-inspired criticism of ordinary language approaches to skeptical arguments by arguing that if radical skepticism does not require a radical transformation of our everyday practices it isn’t something that we really understand—the standard skeptical attitude that aims to call into question all of our knowledge while leaving our ordinary epistemological practices untouched is not coherent (p. 302).

Avner Baz is the most persistent advocate of the critical project in new wave ordinary language philosophy. Baz (2012b), like Kaplan (1991), criticizes a central epistemological notion employed in analytic epistemology for being completely detached from the kinds of interests that would guide its use in ordinary conversation. Baz argues that questions posed by philosophers about the meaning of “know that” are “fundamentally different from any question we might need to consider as part of our everyday employment of these expressions” (p. 91, emphasis in original). Insofar as the questions philosophers ask about “know that” lacks a connection to any of the ordinary purposes that one might have in asking whether someone knows something, we may be “tempted to think we understand” philosophers’ questions when we in fact do not (p. 123).

The explicit advocacy of ordinary language philosophy methods in the new wave period licenses an investigation of new wave ordinary philosophy using the methods we developed for the more classic form. Still, though there are clear continuities between some examples of new wave and classic ordinary language philosophy, and some new wave ordinary language philosophers explicitly describe what they are doing as ordinary language philosophy, the presence of the new wave does not emerge directly out of our investigation of the classic era of ordinary language philosophy. There are some hints about the relation between classic and new wave ordinary language philosophy that emerge when we turn our attention to articles that are most similar to new wave articles, like the presence of Wisdom’s classic ordinary language philosophy paper “Other Minds (VIII)” (1943), and Alan R. White’s “On Claiming to Know” (1957) among the 50 most similar papers to Baz (2012). Like Baz (2012), both Wisdom (1943) and White (1957) concern the way we talk about knowledge. Wisdom’s article takes the form of a dialogue between several characters, “White”, “Gray”, “Black”, and “Brown”, about whether skeptics who argue we can never really know anything are “altering, narrowing our actual use” of expressions like “know” (p. 298). (Black, in Wisdom’s article, defends the view that the skeptic’s use of “know” is an intelligible extension of more familiar uses of “know” against White and Gray’s arguments.). A.R White (1957) is a discussion of the use of different sentences in which “know” figures, such as “I know”, “He knows”, “He says he knows”, and “He would be correct in saying he knows”.Footnote 25

The fact that some classic ordinary language papers show up in the most similar lists to new wave papers is suggestive, but ultimately our investigation of the new wave proceeded from observations about the continuity of arguments and method between classic and new wave ordinary language philosophy rather than from an application of our quantitative similarity measure to canonical classic ordinary language philosophy articles. Here again, our method depends quite substantially on qualitative domain expertise.

While there is no accepted canon of new wave ordinary language philosophy papers, we submit that the articles in Table 6 constitute the basis for an iterated similarity measurement of the kind we performed for canonical classic ordinary language philosophy papers in Sect. 4 above.

Table 6 Exemplars of new wave ordinary language philosophy or criticisms of new wave ordinary language philosophy

To identify examples of new wave ordinary language philosophy, we used a combination of manually identifying relevant examples and using an iterated application of the 90-dimensional measure of similarity discussed in the previous section. That is, using the similarity measurement, we found the top 50 most similar articles to each article in Table 6; we made a list of all articles that are on at least two such top-50 lists; we read those articles and identified the examples of new wave ordinary language philosophy [stage 1]; we then applied the similarity measurement to find the top 50 most similar papers to each paper identified as new wave ordinary language philosophy at stage 1; we made a list of all articles that were on at least two top-50 lists for the articles in Table 6 and the articles identified in stage 1; we read those new articles and identified the examples of new wave ordinary language philosophy [stage 2]; we repeated the process using all the articles identified as new wave in stages 1 and 2 to reach stage 3, where we stopped. (See Appendix B for the full list of examples of new wave ordinary language philosophy.)

When we add the “new wave” to the classical examples of ordinary language philosophy we identified in the Weatherson corpus, combining the results of our investigations into classic and new wave articles in one image, we get a picture of the history of ordinary language philosophy that defies the second half of the standard story of its rise and fall (see Fig. 5). This new wave needs to be part of how we understand the history of ordinary language philosophy.

Fig. 5
figure 5

Number of hand-coded “classic” and “new wave” ordinary language philosophy articles over time

6 “Horseshoe Crab” and “Apple Newton” articles

6.1 “Horseshoe Crab” Articles

We classified a handful of articles that were published during the “new wave” period (roughly early 1990s through 2013, the end of the period covered by Weatherson’s corpus) as “classic” ordinary language philosophy articles and not new wave ordinary language philosophy articles. These papers are “horseshoe crabs”, living fossils whose language and argumentation have survived from an earlier era. For example, consider Graham McFee, “The Surface Grammar of Dreaming” (1994), which adopts the ordinary language approach used by Norman Malcolm in his investigation of dreaming (Malcolm, 1959), namely focusing on “dream reports”—the way we talk about our dreams. Explaining this approach, McFee writes:

This is one sense in which the topic here is the surface grammar of dreaming: that one should begin from what we say about dreams, being neither too mesmerised by this surface, nor totally ignoring it. In effect, what is required is an overview (übersicht) of our use of the word ‘dreaming’ (and its cognates), since our philosophical puzzlement derives from the lack of perspicuity in that use. (McFee, 1994, pp. 114–115).

Notice the similarity in McFee’s description of his method to the “generic” statements of ordinary language methodology made by Hallie (1961) and Flew (1949) discussed in Sect. 3, above: philosophical problems arise from lack of clarity about the ordinary use of a key expression (in this case, “dreaming”); once we have a clear view of that ordinary use, philosophical puzzlement surrounding whatever the key expression picks out should dissolve. If you look hard enough, it is possible to find examples of paradigmatically classic mid-century style ordinary language philosophy still alive from the mid-1990s to the beginning of the twenty-first century.

6.2 “Apple Newton” Articles

There are some articles published during the classic period of ordinary language philosophy that we classified as new wave and not classic ordinary language philosophy. Like the Apple Newton personal digital assistant, these articles make technological advances that take a while to be widely adopted: they anticipate developments that will eventually constitute a new approach to ordinary language that draws on findings from a more systematic study of semantics and pragmatics than classic ordinary language philosophy.

For example, Peter Unger’s “A Defense of Skepticism” (1971) argues for the conclusion that we don’t know nearly anything that we purport to know, on the grounds that knowledge requires certainty, and that the ordinary meaning of the expression “certain” is what Unger calls an absolute expression. Absolute expressions are one type of scalar or gradable expression that apply to objects only when they have the highest degree of the property picked out by the relevant scale. Other examples of absolute scalar expressions are “flat” and “straight”; according to Unger, these terms only apply to objects that are absolutely, completely flat or straight. Absolute scalar expressions contrast with relative scalar expressions, which can apply to objects that only have the relevant property picked out by the scale to some contextually salient degree, and which do not have maximum degrees. Examples of relative scalar expressions include “tall” and “expensive”—nothing can be tall or expensive to an absolute degree, and what counts as tall or expensive can vary depending on the context. If “certain” is an absolute scalar expression, then being certain requires being absolutely certain, and we almost never achieve that degree of certainty; if knowledge requires certainty, then we almost never know anything.

Unger’s distinction between absolute and relative scalar expressions was taken up and developed by linguists (Kennedy, 2007; Kennedy & McNally, 2005; Rusiecki, 1985), and deployed by philosophers in debates about the nature and plausibility of epistemic contextualism (Stanley, 2004, DeRose, 2005, Blome-Tillman, 2017). Unger’s “A Defense of Skepticism” anticipates these new wave debates by more than 30 years.

7 Conclusions and generalizable methods

In this paper we have evaluated the standard story about the rise and fall of ordinary language philosophy by building on Weatherson’s (2022) topic model of philosophy articles. We find quantitative evidence that supports the first part of the standard story, according to which ordinary language philosophy becomes popular in the 1940s, peaks between the early 1950s and the late 1960s, and then rapidly declines. But there is a “new wave” of ordinary language philosophy in the early twenty-first century, whose arguments are continuous with the arguments of classic ordinary language philosophy, that defies the second part of the standard story.

Our semi-automated method of identifying articles similar to a target article should also be useful in investigating topics beyond ordinary language philosophy. Measuring distance on the basis of a topic model yields intuitively illuminating responses to very specific requests, like “find articles similar to Ryle’s ‘Use, Usage, and Meaning’”. In combination with our dialectical approach—the essential step in digital humanities studies of combining quantitative results with hermeneutics (i.e. reading the articles) and expertise in a humanities field (i.e. knowing something about a philosophical approach and its history)—this method should be generalizable to investigations of other fields. Future extensions of this work might build on it in two directions. First, more highly automated digital analysis might productively stir the archive further. More advanced classification or sorting (see note 4) could turn up articles that we did not see, perhaps taking advantage of our hand-tagging labor as part of the training for a more machine-learning-intensive approach. Second, our method as is could be extended to similar historical investigations, in philosophy or elsewhere. This would require a topic modeling process that is at least as good as Weatherson’s, which is careful and well documented. But given such a model, it should work—when we have used this method to investigate other philosophical subfields, we have found results that seem as promising as those we found for ordinary language philosophy.Footnote 26 Readers can generate a similar list for any subfield of interest by selecting a few canonical articles and using a similar process of generating distance lists, tagging the results, generating new similarity lists from them, and so on.

Another product of our approach has been the assembly of a bibliography of ordinary language philosophy articles from the large corpus that Weatherson assembled. We have attached the lists of what we hand coded as “classic” and “new wave” ordinary language philosophy as online appendices.Footnote 27

We want to register one important caveat about our findings. The picture of the trajectory of ordinary language philosophy that we draw is as comprehensive as we could make it within the limits of Weatherson’s corpus. But the journals that Weatherson has chosen to include in order to represent “what’s generally happening in philosophy” at any given time involve various compromises, and some of the journals in which important work on ordinary language philosophy has been published (Inquiry for example) are not included in Weatherson’s list of journals (Sect. 1.1). And our investigation doesn’t include books, dissertations, syllabi, exam questions, conferences, talks, or any work not written in English.Footnote 28 But even with those limitations, we now have a much fuller and more detailed picture of the historical trajectory of ordinary language philosophy than has previously been available. Other researchers can begin to fill in the other parts of this picture that we have left blank.

In his discussion of how the topic of Idealism went from being “the dominant force in anglophone philosophy” in the late 19th and early twentieth centuries to simply no longer being a topic that was discussed in the journals included in his corpus, Weatherson cites the following passage from Wilfrid Sellars about the rise and fall of systems of philosophy (Sect. 2.2):

It has been said that a system of philosophy is not refuted, but becomes ignored. This is true. It is equally true (and for the same reason) that a clash of systems in the philosophical drama ends not in victory and defeat, but in a changing of the scene. Put from a somewhat different point of view, the historical development of philosophy is more truly conceived as the periodic formulation of new questions, than as a series of attempted answers to an enduring body of problems. To be sure, the new questions which appear in this process can be regarded, for the most part, as revisions or reformulations of earlier issues; however, the fact of revision and reformulation is of the essence of the matter, making new questions out of old. Put in these terms, a system dies when the questions it seeks to answer are no longer asked; and only where the questions are the same can there be a genuine clash of answers. (Sellars, 1948, p. 601)Footnote 29

Sellars’s characterization fits ordinary language philosophy particularly well, especially since with the rise of new wave ordinary language philosophy in the early twenty-first century, some of the old questions posed by ordinary language philosophy are being asked again, but using the new language of contextualism and some types of experimental philosophy: how are expressions ordinarily used? Can ordinary use be identified by using experimental methods? What do facts about the way we ordinarily use expressions tell us about the semantics of those expressions, and about non-linguistic features of the world, like the nature of knowledge and intentional action?

Now that those questions are being asked again, we need to revise the standard story: ordinary language philosophy went into hibernation for 30 years but has returned in the twenty-first century, sometimes going by various aliases, most notably “contextualism” and some varieties of “experimental philosophy”.