Skip to main content
Log in

How can embodied cognition naturalize bounded rationality?

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Publisher Correction to this article was published on 05 May 2023

This article has been updated

Abstract

The paper discusses how research on embodied cognition in cognitive science can contribute to the naturalization of rationality. The investigation takes place in two steps. First, we provide a conceptual map of possible new ideas of rationality inspired by embodied cognition. Given the plurality of theories of embodied cognition, we distinguish different approaches according to their increasing degree of radicalism. We consider ecological rationality as currently the best candidate for naturalizing rationality, and, after identifying its descriptive and normative building blocks, we provide an increasingly radical embodied interpretation of them. The outcome is four new concepts of rationality, in increasing order of embodied radicalism: embodied bounded rationality, body rationality, extended rationality, and radical embodied rationality. We emphasize that while less radical concepts currently align better with the idea of methodological naturalism, radical concepts are best conceived of as instances of ontological naturalism. The second step of our investigation concerns comparing the four embodied rationality concepts in light of three meta-criteria: internal epistemic values, empirical success, and intertheoretic compatibility. While empirical success currently favors less radical concepts, intertheoretic compatibility demonstrates the promises of rationality’s embodied radicalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. Our analysis is confined to rationality in individual judgment and decision-making, which, as Gigerenzer & Sturm (2012) make clear, is also connected to practical (i.e., means-ends) rationality. We will not discuss rationality in other domains such as epistemology or ethics.

  2. It’s worth emphasizing the use of the attribute “grounded” here, as “groundedness” is what we are looking for in a naturalized theory of rationality, and, importantly, what we think an alliance with embodied cognition can provide. Although it is a term usually associated with the approach of Barsalou (2008), we take groundedness to be a distinctive feature of all the approaches within embodied cognition.

  3. As we’ll see in Sect. 3, reformulating the descriptive and normative building blocks has important ontological and methodological implications.

  4. We will not decompose the normative building block into further components (hence our use of “singular”), but normative criteria can certainly be analyzed in a more granular fashion.

  5. Exaptation also works at the neural level in the form of “neural reuse,” where sensorimotor, interoceptive, and affective neural resources are phylogenetically and ontogenetically refunctionalized (Anderson, 2014). As such, it is also relevant for embodied bounded rationality, even if, again, it is not clear whether exaptation is relevant only descriptively or also normatively. A crucial philosophical question concerns whether, and to what extent, an exapted neural process not at the disposal of individuals can be assessed in terms of individuals’ rationality.

  6. Constructionist insights in the form of niche constructionism can also be found in Clark (2006).

  7. It’s worth noting here that radical embodied cognition shares many affinities with James Gibson’s (1979) pioneering approach to “ecological psychology” in that it also dispenses with mental representations entirely in the study of perception. For the complementarity between the two approaches, see McGann et al. (2020).

  8. At the same time, we follow Gigerenzer & Sturm (2012) and Sturm’s (2021) rebuttals of common criticisms about the naturalistic proposal of ecological rationality.

  9. See Hertwig et al., (2021) for a recent attempt to extend ecological rationality along a more dynamic direction.

  10. Though, see Favela et al. (2021) for promising methodological developments in dynamical cognitive science.

  11. Sturm’s argument is aimed at naturalism with respect to the rationality of judgment and decision-making. He does not claim that critical methodological naturalism should be adopted in all cases where the naturalism of a theory is at issue (see Sturm, 2021, p. 84).

  12. Although we are focusing on individual theories of judgment and decision-making, there is good reason to think that many of the same heuristics also can be applied to social contexts where decisions are made by collective entities such as firms, states, etc.—see, for example, Hertwig & Hoffrage (2013).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. (2014). After phrenology: Neural reuse and the interactive brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arnau, E., Ayala, S., & Sturm, T. (2014). Cognitive externalism meets bounded rationality. Philosophical Psychology, 27(1), 50–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (Eds.). (1995). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 577–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59(1), 617–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M., & Wilutzky, W. (2017). Is it possible to experimentally determine the extension of cognition? Philosophical Psychology, 30(8), 1104–1125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, L., & Grayot, J. D. (2021). New functionalism and the social and behavioral sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 11(4), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bocanegra, B. R., Poletiek, F. H., Ftitache, B., & Clark, A. (2019). Intelligent problem-solvers externalize cognitive operations. Nature Human Behaviour, 3(2), 136–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighton, H., & Todd, P. M. (2009). Situating rationality: Ecologically rational decision making with simple heuristics. In P. Robbins, & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 322–346). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2011). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Reasons, robots and the extended mind. Mind & Language, 16(2), 121–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(8), 370–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. J. (1981). Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4(3), 317–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2006). Mechanism. In S. Sarkar, & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), Philosophy of science: An encyclopedia (pp. 469–478). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J. B. (2003). The theory of the individual in economics: Identity and value. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J. B. (2010). Individuals and identity in economics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro, M., & Macarthur, D. (2008). Introduction: The nature of naturalism. In De M. Caro, & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in question (pp. 1–17). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dekker, E., & Remic, B. (2019). Two types of ecological rationality: Or how to best combine psychology and economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 26(4), 291–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1971). Intentional systems. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(4), 87–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Buhrmann, T., & Barandiaran, X. (2017). Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2013). The value of cognitive values. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 796–806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Favela, L. H. (2020). Dynamical systems theory in cognitive science and neuroscience. Philosophy Compass, 15(8), e12695.

    Google Scholar 

  • Favela, L. H., Amon, M. J., Lobo, L., & Chemero, A. (2021). Empirical evidence for extended cognitive systems. Cognitive Science, 45(11), e13060.

  • Favela, L. H., & Chemero, A. (2015). The animal-environment system. Perceptual and emotional embodiment (pp. 67–82). London: Routledge: & M. H. Fischer. Y. Coello.

    Google Scholar 

  • Favela, L. H., & Chemero, A. (2021). Explanatory pluralism: A case study from the life sciences. PhilSci-Archive. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/19146

  • Felin, T., & Koenderink, J. (2022). A generative view of rationality and growing awareness. Frontiers in Psychology, 13, 807261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foglia, L., & Wilson, R. A. (2013). Embodied cognition. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 4(3), 319–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frolov, D. (2022). Post-Northian institutional economics: A research agenda for cognitive institutions. Journal of Institutional Economics, 1–17. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1744137422000285

  • Gallagher, S. (2011). Interpretations of embodied cognition. In W. Tschacher, & C. Bergomi (Eds.), The implications of embodiment: Cognition and communication (pp. 59–71). Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2013). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25, 4–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2018a). Embodied rationality. In G. Bronner, & Di F. Iorio (Eds.), The mystery of rationality. Mind, beliefs and social science (pp. 83–94). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2018b). New mechanisms and the enactivist concept of constitution. In P. M. Guta (Ed.), Consciousness and the ontology of properties (pp. 207–220). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2020). Action and interaction. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Gallagher, S., Mastrogiorgio, A., & Petracca, E. (2019). Economic reasoning and interaction in socially extended market institutions. Frontiers in Psychology, 10, 1856.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2(12), 493–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Mastrogiorgio, A., Petracca, E., & Viale, R. (2020). Embodied bounded rationality. In R. Viale (Ed.), Routledge handbook of bounded rationality (pp. 377–390). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Galparsoro, J. I., & Cordero, A. (Eds.). (2013). Reflections on naturalism. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

  • Gibbs, R. W. Jr. (2005). Embodiment and cognitive science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin

  • Gigerenzer, G. (1996). On narrow norms and vague heuristics: A reply to Kahneman and Tversky (1996). Psychological Review, 103(3), 592–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2021). Embodied heuristics. Frontiers in Psychology, 12, 711289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Brighton, H. (2009). Homo heuristicus: Why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1(1), 107–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. E., Hertwig, R. E., & Pachur, T. E. (Eds.). (2011). Heuristics: The foundations of adaptive behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Gaissmaier, W. (2011). Heuristic decision making. Annual Review of Psychology, 62(1), 451–482.

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2002). Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Sturm, T. (2012). How (far) can rationality be naturalized? Synthese, 187(1), 243–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Todd, P. M. (Eds.). (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A., & de Vignemont, F. (2009). Is social cognition embodied? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 154–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2012). A moderate approach to embodied cognitive science. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 71–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1994). The theory theory. In L. A. Hirschfeld, & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and culture (pp. 257–293). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation—a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology, 8(1), 4–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grayot, J. (2017). The quasi-economic agency of human selves. Œconomia - History, Methodology, Philosophy, 7(4), 481–511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grayot, J. D. (2021). Economic agency and the subpersonal turn in economics. In J. Reiss (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of economics (pp. 83–95). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, R. P. (2017). “The gaze heuristic:” Biography of an adaptively rational decision process. Topics in Cognitive Science, 9(2), 264–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R. E., & Hoffrage, U. E. (Eds.). (2013). Simple heuristics in a social world. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hertwig, R., Leuker, C., Pachur, T., Spiliopoulos, L., & Pleskac, T. J. (2021). Studies in ecological rationality. Topics in Cognitive Science, 14(3), 467–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochstein, E. (2017). Why one model is never enough: A defense of explanatory holism. Biology & Philosophy, 32(6), 1105–1125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horst, S. (2007). Beyond reduction: Philosophy of mind and post-reductionist philosophy of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaaronen, R. O. (2020). Mycological rationality: Heuristics, perception and decision-making in mushroom foraging. Judgment and Decision Making, 15(5), 630–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2003). Maps of bounded rationality: Psychology for behavioral economics. American Economic Review, 93(5), 1449–1475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher, & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1996). Cognitive and non-cognitive values in science: Rethinking the dichotomy. In L. H. Nelson, & J. Nelson (Eds.), Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science (pp. 39–58). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mastrogiorgio, A., Felin, T., Kauffman, S., & Mastrogiorgio, M. (2022). More thumbs than rules: Is rationality an exaptation? Frontiers in Psychology, 13, 805743.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mastrogiorgio, A., & Petracca, E. (2016). Embodying rationality. In L. Magnani, & C. Casadio (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology (pp. 219–237). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McGann, M., Di Paolo, E. A., Heras-Escribano, M., & Chemero, A. (2020). Editorial: Enaction and Ecological psychology: Convergences and complementarities. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 617898.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oullier, O., & Basso, F. (2010). Embodied economics: How bodily information shapes the social coordination dynamics of decision-making. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 365(1538), 291–301.

  • Petracca, E. (2017). A cognition paradigm clash: Simon, situated cognition and the interpretation of bounded rationality. Journal of Economic Methodology, 24(1), 20–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petracca, E. (2021). Embodying bounded rationality: From embodied bounded rationality to embodied rationality. Frontiers in Psychology, 12, 710607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petracca, E., & Gallagher, S. (2020). Economic cognitive institutions. Journal of Institutional Economics, 16(6), 747–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2005). [1959]. The logic of scientific discovery. London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Proffitt, D. R., & Linkenauger, S. A. (2013). Perception viewed as a phenotypic expression. In W. Prinz, M. Beisert, & A. Herwig (Eds.), Action science: Foundations of an emerging discipline (pp. 171–197). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raab, M. (2017). Motor heuristics and embodied choices: How to choose and act. Current Opinion in Psychology, 16, 34–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raab, M. (2020). Judgment, decision-making, and embodied choices. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risjord, M. (2014). Philosophy of social science: A contemporary introduction. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Risko, E. F., & Gilbert, S. J. (2016). Cognitive offloading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(9), 676–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolla, G. (2021). Reconceiving rationality: Situating rationality into radically enactive cognition. Synthese, 198(1), 571–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2004). Metalinguistic signalling for coordination amongst social agents. Language Sciences, 26(6), 621–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2005). Economic theory and cognitive science: Microexplanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2010). The economic agent: Not human, but important. In U. Mäki (Ed.), Philosophy of economics (pp. 691–735). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2014a). Philosophy of economics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2014b). Psychological versus economic models of bounded rationality. Journal of Economic Methodology, 21(4), 411–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D., & Stirling, W. (2021). Economics, social neuroscience, and mindreading. In J. Harbecke, & C. Herrmann-Pillath (Eds.), Social neuroeconomics: Mechanistic integration of the neurosciences and the social sciences (pp. 174–201). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. The Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2019). Embodied cognition. Routledge. 2nd edition. London: Routledge.

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2004). The mind incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L., & Spaulding, S. (2021). Embodied cognition. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (Ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/embodied-cognition/

  • Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69(1), 99–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1956). Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review, 63(2), 129–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1979). Information processing models of cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 30(1), 363–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1983). Reason in human affairs. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1975). Simplicity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge (pp. 239–254). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sturm, T. (2021). Towards a critical naturalism about bounded rationality. In R. Viale (Ed.), Routledge handbook of bounded rationality (pp. 73–89). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. M., & Gigerenzer, G. (Eds.). (2012). Ecological rationality: Intelligence in the world. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vera, A. H., & Simon, H. A. (1993). Situated action: A symbolic interpretation. Cognitive Science, 17(1), 7–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. A. (2010). The Goldilocks problem and extended cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 11(4), 313–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part I: A counterfactual account. Noûs, 37(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J., & Ross, L. (2021). Scientific explanation. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (Ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/scientific-explanation/.

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zednik, C. (2011). The nature of dynamical explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78(2), 238–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Shaun Gallagher and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful and constructive comments. The usual caveats apply.

Funding

James Grayot acknowledges funding from Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia, CEEC 4th edition.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

All authors provided a substantial contribution to the conceptualization, writing, and revision of the manuscript. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Enrico Petracca.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research has been conducted in the absence of relationships, of either financial or non-financial nature, that could constitute a potential conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The original online version of this article was revised: a mistake was introduced by Springer Nature during the proof correction process.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Petracca, E., Grayot, J. How can embodied cognition naturalize bounded rationality?. Synthese 201, 115 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04124-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04124-3

Keywords

Navigation