Skip to main content
Log in

How (far) can rationality be naturalized?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper shows why and how an empirical study of fast-and-frugal heuristics can provide norms of good reasoning, and thus how (and how far) rationality can be naturalized. We explain the heuristics that humans often rely on in solving problems, for example, choosing investment strategies or apartments, placing bets in sports, or making library searches. We then show that heuristics can lead to judgments that are as accurate as or even more accurate than strategies that use more information and computation, including optimization methods. A standard way to defend the use of heuristics is by reference to accuracy-effort trade-offs. We take a different route, emphasizing ecological rationality (the relationship between cognitive heuristics and environment), and argue that in uncertain environments, more information and computation are not always better (the “less-can-be-more” doctrine). The resulting naturalism about rationality is thus normative because it not only describes what heuristics people use, but also in which specific environments one should rely on a heuristic in order to make better inferences. While we desist from claiming that the scope of ecological rationality is unlimited, we think it is of wide practical use.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alexy R. (1993) Justification and application of norms. Ratio Juris 6: 157–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson J. R. (1990) The adaptive character of thought. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R. (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, N., Biele, G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2011). Logical consistency and accuracy of beliefs: Survey evidence on health decision-making among economists. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Bergert F. B., Nosofsky R. M. (2007) A response–time approach to comparing generalized rational and take-the-best models of decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 33: 107–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K. (2009) Rational decisions. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbacher D. (1988) Verantwortung für zukünftige Generationen. Reclam, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop M. (2008) Reflections on a normative psychology. In: Beckermann A., Walter S. (eds) Philosophy: Foundations and applications. Mentis, Paderborn, pp 25–262

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop M., Trout J. D. (2005) Epistemology and the psychology of human judgment. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bookstaber R., Langsam J. (1985) On the optimality of coarse behavior rules. Journal of Theoretical Biology 116: 161–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R., Richerson P. J. (2005) The origin and evolution of cultures. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandstätter E., Gigerenzer G., Hertwig R. (2006) The priority heuristic: A process model of risky choice. Psychological Review 113: 409–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandstätter E., Gigerenzer G., Hertwig R. (2008) Risky choice with heuristics: Reply to Birnbaum (2008), Johnson, Schulte-Mecklenbeck, and Willemsen (2008) and Rieger and Wang (2008). Psychological Review 115: 281–290

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighton, H. (2006). Robust inference with simple cognitive models. In C. Lebiere & R. Wray (Eds.), Between a rock and a hard place: Cognitive science principles meet AI-hard problems. Papers from the AAAI Spring symposium (AAAI Tech. Rep. No. SS-06-03, pp. 17–22). Menlo Park, CA: AAAI Press.

  • Brighton H., Gigerenzer G. (2008) Bayesian brains and cognitive mechanisms: Harmony or dissonance?. In: Chater N., Oaksford M. (eds) The probabilistic mind: Prospects for Bayesian cognitive science. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 189–208

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bröder A. (2003) Decision making with the “adaptive toolbox”: Influence of environmental structure, intelligence, and working memory load. Journal of Experimental Psychology 29: 611–625

    Google Scholar 

  • Bröder A., Gaissmaier W. (2007) Sequential processing of cues in memory-based multi-attribute decisions. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 14: 895–900

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruss F. T. (2000) Der Ungewissheit ein Schnippchen schlagen. Spektrum der Wissenschaft 6: 106–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R. (1947) On the application of inductive logic. Philosophy and Phenonmenlogical Research 8: 133–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiappe D. L., Vervaeke J. (1997) Fodor, Cherniak, and the naturalization of rationality. Theory & Psychology 7: 799–821

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper G. F. (1990) Computational complexity of probabilistic inference using Bayesian belief networks. Artificial Intelligence 42: 393–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Czerlinski, J., Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1999). How good are simple heuristics? In G. Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, & the ABC Research Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart (pp. 97–118). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Dagum P., Luby M. (1993) Approximating probabilistic inference in Bayesian belief networks is NP-hard. Artificial Intelligence 60: 141–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels N. (1979) Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics. The Journal of Philosophy 76: 256–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston L. J. (1988) Classical probability in the enlightenment. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes R. M. (1979) The robust beauty of improper linear models in decision making. American Psychologist 34: 571–582

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawes R. M., Corrigan B. (1974) Linear models in decision making. Psychological Bulletin 81: 95–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeMiguel, V., Garlappi, L., & Uppal, R. (2009). Optimal versus naive diversification: How inefficient is the 1/N portfolio strategy? Review of Financial Studies, 22, 1915–1953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dhami M. K. (2003) Psychological models of professional decision-making. Psychological Science 14: 175–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dhami M. K., Ayton P. (2001) Bailing and jailing the fast and frugal way. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 14: 141–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieckmann A., Rieskamp J. (2007) The influence of information redundancy on probabilistic inferences. Memory & Cognition 35: 1801–1813

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dudey T., Todd P. M. (2002) Making good decisions with minimal information: Simultaneous and sequential choice. Journal of Bioeconomics 3: 195–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einhorn H. J., Hogarth R. M. (1975) Unit weighting schemes for decision making. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 13: 171–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ettenson R., Shanteau J., Krogstad J. (1987) Expert judgment: Is more information better?. Psychological Report 60: 227–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ford J. K., Schmitt N., Schechtman S. L., Hults B. H., Doherty M. L. (1989) Process tracing methods: Contributions, problems, and neglected research questions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 43: 75–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia-Retamero R., Dhami M. K. (2009) Take-the-best in expert-novice decision strategies for residential burglary. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 16: 163–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G. (2004) Striking a blow for sanity in theories of rationality. In: Augier M., March J. G. (eds) Models of a man: Essays in memory of Herbert A.Simon. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 389–409

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G. (2007) Gut feelings: The intelligence of the unconscious. Viking Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G. (2008) Rationality for mortals. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G., Brighton H. (2009) Homo heuristicus: Why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science 1: 1–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G., Gaissmaier W., Kurz-Milcke E., Schwartz L. M., Woloshin S. W. (2007) Helping doctors and patients make sense of health statistics. Psychological Science in the Public Interest 8: 53–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G., Goldstein D. G. (1996) Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review 103: 650–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., Selten, R. (eds) (2001) Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G., Swijtink Z., Porter T., Daston L., Beatty J., Krüger L. (1989) The empire of chance. How probability changed science and everyday life. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., & the ABC Research Group. (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Gilbert J. P., Mosteller F. (1966) Recognizing the maximum of a sequence. American Statistical Association Journal 61: 35–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A. (1986) Epistemology and cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A. (2008) Human rationality: Epistemological and psychological perspectives. In: Beckermann A., Walter S. (eds) Philosophy: Foundations and applications. Mentis, Paderborn, pp 230–247

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein D. G., Gigerenzer G. (2002) Models of ecological rationality: The recognition heuristic. Psychological Review 109: 75–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good I. J. (1967) On the principle of total evidence. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17: 319–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman N. (1965) Fact, fiction, and forecast. Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis, IN

    Google Scholar 

  • Green L. A., Mehr D. R. (1997) What alters physicians’ decisions to admit to the coronary care unit?. The Journal of Family Practice 45: 219–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice H. P. (1975) Logic and conversation. In: Cole P., Morgan J. L. (eds) Syntax and semantics, vol. 3: Speech acts. Academic Press, New York, pp 41–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Günther K. (1993) The sense of appropriateness. SUNY Press, Albany, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J. (1997) Between facts and norms. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna R. (2006) Rationality and the ethics of logic. The Journal of Philosophy 103: 67–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig R., Gigerenzer G. (1999) The “conjunction fallacy” revisited: How intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 12: 275–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogarth R. M., Karelaia N. (2005) Ignoring information in binary choice with continuous variables: When is less “more”?. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 49: 115–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogarth R. M., Karelaia N. (2006) Take-the-best and other simple strategies: Why and when they work ‘well’ in binary choice. Theory and Decision 61: 205–249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huberman G., Jiang W. (2006) Offering vs. choice in 401(k) plans: Equity exposure and number of funds. Journal of Finance 61: 763–801

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson J. M. C., Gigerenzer G. (2005) Simple heuristics and rules of thumb: Where psychologists and behavioural biologists might meet. Behavioural Processes 69: 97–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson E. J., Goldstein D. G. (2003) Do defaults save lives?. Science 302: 1338–1339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson E. J., Schulte-Mecklenbeck M., Willemsen M. C. (2008) Process models deserve process data: A comment on Brandstätter, Gigerenzer, and Hertwig (2006). Psychological Review 115: 263–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). In J. Timmermann (Ed.), Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Hamburg: Meiner. (Original work published 1781/1787.)

  • Kim J. (1988) What is “naturalized epistemology”?. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 381–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohli R., Jedidi K. (2007) Representation and inference of lexicographic preference models and their variants. Marketing Science 26: 380–399

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee M. D., Loughlin N., Lundberg I. B. (2002) Applying one reason decision making: The prioritization of literature searches. Australian Journal of Psychology 54: 137–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makridakis S., Hibon M. (2000) The M3-competition: Results, conclusions and implications. International Journal of Forecasting 16: 451–476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martignon L., Hoffrage U. (2002) Fast, frugal, and fit: Simple heuristics for paired comparison. Theory & Decision 52: 29–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martignon L., Vitouch O., Takezawa M., Forster M. R. (2003) Naive and yet enlightened: From natural frequencies to fast and frugal decision trees. In: Hardman D., Macchi L. (eds) Thinking: Psychological perspectives on reasoning, judgment and decision making. Wiley, Chichester, pp 189–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A., Rawlings, P. (eds) (2004) The Oxford handbook of rationality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Messick D. M. (1993) Equality as a decision heuristic. In: Mellers B. A., Baron J. (eds) Psychological perspectives on justice. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 11–31

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Michalewicz Z., Fogel D. (2000) How to solve it: Modern heuristics. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mugford S. T., Mallon E. B., Franks N. R. (2001) The accuracy of Buffon’s needle: A rule of thumb used by ants to estimate area. Behavioral Ecology 12: 655–658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nosofsky R. M., Bergert F. B. (2007) Limitations of exemplar models of multi-attribute probabilistic inference. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 33: 999–1019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R. (1993) The nature of rationality. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Payne J. W., Bettman J. R., Johnson E. J. (1993) The adaptive decision maker. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Petrie M., Halliday T. (1994) Experimental and natural changes in the peacock’s (Pavo cristatus) train can affect mating success. Behavioral and Ecological Sociobiology 35: 213–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pohl R. (2006) Empirical tests of the recognition heuristic. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 19: 251–271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1982) Why reason can’t be naturalized. Synthese 52: 3–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine W. V. O. (1969) Epistemology naturalized. In: Quine W. V. O. (eds) Ontological relativity and other essays. Columbia Press, New York, pp 69–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1990). Pursuit of truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (2nd ed. 1992).

  • Rawls J. (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy R. (1988) Foundations and grand challenges of artificial intelligence: AAAI presidential address. AI Magazine 9: 9–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieskamp J., Hoffrage U. (2008) Inferences under time pressure: How opportunity costs affect strategy selection. Acta Psychologica 127: 258–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieskamp J., Otto P. E. (2006) SSL: A theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 135: 207–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage L. J. (1972) The foundations of statistics. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt F. L. (1971) The relative efficiency of regression and simple unit weighting predictor weights in applied differential psychology. Educational and Psychological Measurement 31: 699–714

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schooler L. J., Hertwig R. (2005) How forgetting aids heuristic inference. Psychological Review 112: 610–628

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selten R. (2001) What is bounded rationality?. In: Gigerenzer G., Selten R. (eds) Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 13–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Serwe S., Frings C. (2006) Who will win Wimbledon? The recognition heuristic in predicting sports events. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 19: 321–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanteau J. (1992) How much information does an expert use? Is it relevant?. Acta Psychologica 81: 75–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon H. A. (1955) A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics 69: 99–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon H. A. (1990) Invariants of human behavior. Annual Review of Psychology 41: 1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith V. L. (2003) Constructivist and ecological rationality in economics. American Economic Review 93: 465–508

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein E. (1996) Without good reason: The rationality debate in philosophy and cognitive science. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler G. J. (1961) The economics of information. Journal of Political Economy 69: 213–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd P. M. (2001) Fast and frugal heuristics for environmentally bounded minds. In: Gigerenzer G., Selten R. (eds) Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 51–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. M., & Miller, G. F. (1999). From pride and prejudice to persuasion: Satisficing in mate search. In G. Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, & the ABC Research Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart (pp. 287–308). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Tversky A. (1972) Elimination by aspects: A theory of choice. Psychological Review 79: 281–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wübben M., Wangenheim F. v. (2008) Instant customer base analysis: Managerial heuristics often “get it right”. Journal of Marketing 72: 82–93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yee M., Hauser J., Orlin J., Dahan E. (2007) Greedoid-based non-compensatory two-stage consideration-then-choice inference. Marketing Science 26: 532–549

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerd Gigerenzer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gigerenzer, G., Sturm, T. How (far) can rationality be naturalized?. Synthese 187, 243–268 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-0030-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-0030-6

Keywords

Navigation