Skip to main content
Log in

The case for panpsychism: a critical assessment

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to panpsychists, physical phenomena are, at bottom, nothing but experiential phenomena. One argument for this view proceeds from an alleged need for physical phenomena to have features beyond what physics attributes to them; another starts by arguing that consciousness is ubiquitous, and proposes an identification of physical and experiential phenomena as the best explanation of this alleged fact. The first argument assumes that physical phenomena have categorical natures, and the second that the world’s experience-causing powers or potentials underdetermine its physical features. I argue that panpsychists are not entitled to these assumptions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. §5 also criticizes David Chalmers’s “Hegelian” argument for panpsychism.

  2. The distinction between strong and weak panpsychism is equivalent to Galen Strawson’s distinction between “pure panpsychism” and “psychism”: (Strawson, 2020, p. 317).

  3. Strong panpsychists aren’t committed to saying that every physical entity has a mental life: it’s consistent with strong panpsychism to say that a doormat, for example, is a complex of minds that do not constitute a further mind having the minds in the collection as parts.

  4. Chalmers distinguishes constitutive from emergent panpsychism in (Chalmers, 2017, p. 25).

  5. The classic source for Kantian noumenalism is Kant (1781/1998); see esp. (Kant,1781/1998, 350). Langton (1998) is a sympathetic interpretation of Kant along the lines sketched above. Recent defenses of the view that physical facts reduce to facts about experience-causing powers include (Robinson, 1982, pp. 108–123), Fumerton (1985), Foster (2008), Chalmers (2010), and Smithson (2017) (though unlike Kant, Robinson and Foster think we do know something about the nature of the source of experience, namely that it’s God).

  6. The classic source for phenomenalism is (Mill, 1865/1979, pp. 177–209). More recent defenses of phenomenalism include Price (1932), (Price, 1940, pp. 141–92), (Ayer, 1936, pp. 138–46), Ayer(1946–1947), Lewis (1946), and Pelczar (2019).

  7. Bain (2006) argues for a structuralist reduction of spacetime; Rovelli (2006) argues for an eliminativist stance on time and space.

  8. (Eddington, 1929, p. 276).

  9. This definition might need refinement to be useful for a wider range of philosophical applications, but for present purposes it should do. For more on intrinsicality, see Langton and Lewis (1998), Marshall and Parsons (2001), and Marshall (2016).

  10. See (Eddington, 1929, pp. 247–92), (Mørch, 2014, p. 28), (Strawson, 2017, pp. 57–60), and (Goff, 2017, pp. 135–64). “IP” stands for Incompleteness of Physics.

  11. Prominent defenses of structuralism include Russell (1927a), (Ladyman et al., 2007, pp. 130–89), Sider (2011), French (2014), and Tegmark (2014); see also Dirac (1938-1939), and, for what may be the earliest modern version of structuralism, Boscovich (1763/1922).

  12. For neutral monism, see (James, 1912, pp. 226–233) and (Russell, 1927b, pp. 287–302); for panprotopsychism, see (Chalmers, 1996, pp. 277–292); for a relevant form of non-standard materialism, see (Stoljar, 2020, pp. 220–221).

  13. What about things like quarks? More on these below.

  14. One possible view is that powers are themselves experiential phenomena: see, e.g., (Mørch,Mørch (2014),90-119). However, we can attribute things experience-causing powers without construing the powers as experiences.

  15. See (Goff, 2017, pp. 166–671) and (Strawson, 2017, p. 77).

  16. For arguments against categoricalism similar to the one given here, see McKitrick (2003) and Mumford (2006).

  17. (Armstrong, 1997, p. 79).

  18. (Handfield, 2005, pp. 452–456).

  19. For a full development of this tu quoque against Armstrong, see (Handfield, 2005, pp. 456–458) and Bird (2005).

  20. (Stoljar and Smith, 1998, pp. 90–99).

  21. (Stoljar and Smith, 1998, p. 87).

  22. See (Stoljar and Smith, 1998, pp. 96–99), where Smith and Stoljar argue that such an analysis is justified by the alleged fact that any difference or similarity between two possible worlds must be a difference or similarity in the worlds’ non-dispositional features.

  23. (Goff, 2017, pp. 137–138).

  24. (Goff, 2017, pp. 138–139).

  25. (Goff, 2017, p. 139).

  26. (Goff, 2017, p. 139).

  27. (Goff, 2017, p. 140). See also (Russell, 1927/1992, 325), (Eddington, 1929, p. 262), (Hartshorne, 1946, p. 413), (Foster, 1993, p. 295), (Adams, 2007, p. 40), (Strawson, 2008, p. 20), and (Chalmers, 2017, p. 26).

  28. Exceptions are Galen Strawson and Philip Goff, who explicitly invoke Occam’s Razor in this context: see Strawson (2003, pp. 75–76) and Goff (2017, pp. 169–171).

  29. See Eddington (1929, pp. 258–260) and Strawson (2008, pp. 57–59).

  30. According to some materialists, E1 is false, since the neural correlates of my experiences do differ from other physical phenomena in ways that explain why they have conscious qualities but other physical phenomena (like digestive states or meteorological states) do not; see, e.g., Armstrong (1968), Lewis (1972), and Jackson (1994). Panpsychists argue that we have to accept E2 on pain of saying that it’s just a brute, inexplicable fact that some physical phenomena but not others come with conscious qualities. However, it’s unclear that it’s less plausible to think that this fact is brute and inexplicable than to suppose that things like quarks are conscious.

  31. See Nagel (1979) and Strawson (2006, pp. 60–67).

  32. N1 is a “no emergence” claim that many mind-body dualists deny; it’s also unclear that emergentism, whatever its demerits, is less attractive than panpsychism: see Stephan (2017). N2 says, in effect, that the physical world has a bottom mereological level; this seems plausible, though it’s not obviously true. The idea behind N4 is that it’s reasonable to suppose that there’s no difference in kind between our own fundamental physical constituents and other fundamental physical entities; Barry Dainton challenges this claim in Dainton (2021).

  33. See Place (1956) and Smart (1959).

  34. See (Campbell, 1970, pp. 100–104), Kirk (1974), and (Chalmers, 1996, pp. 94–99).

  35. The first premise of the zombie argument is stronger than required for a modal argument against strong panpsychism. We could replace it with: We can imagine a world that contains all the rocks that our world contains, but no consciousness. Such a world is also impossible, according to strong panpsychists, since according to them actual rocks are made of consciousness.

  36. For refinements of Z2, see Chalmers (2002).

  37. See Stoljar (2001) (though Stoljar doesn’t advocate panpsychism) and (Chalmers, 2017, pp. 28–29) (quoted below). In Stoljar’s terms, the panpsychists’ objection to Z1 is that it’s true only on a “theory-based” conception of the physical, but not on an “object-based” conception of the physical.

  38. For the abductive argument against external world skepticism, see (Locke, 1694/1979, p. IV.xi), (Russell, 1912, p. 5), (Broad, 1925, pp. 140–220), (Mackie, 1976, pp. 662–669), (Jackson, 1977, pp. 141–151), Putnam (1982), Vogel (1990), (Davidson, 2001, p. 151), Vogel (2005), Chalmers (2010), and Huemer (2015).

  39. (Chalmers, 2017, pp. 22–23, 24–30).

  40. (Chalmers, 2017, pp. 28–29).

  41. (Chalmers, 2017, p. 26).

  42. Curiously, Chalmers himself appears favor of a kind of noumenalism in Chalmers (2010): see esp. (Chalmers, 2010, p. 479), where he suggests that “as long as a hypothesis involves some reasonable explanation for the regularities in our experience, then it will not be a global skeptical hypothesis.”

  43. I gratefully acknowledge valuable comments on previous versions of this paper from my colleagues at the National University of Singapore, and the anonymous reviewers for this journal.

References

  • Adams, R. M. (2007). Idealism vindicated. In P. Inwagen & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Persons: Human and divine (pp. 35–54). Oxford University Press.

  • Armstrong, D. (1968). A materialist theory of the mind. Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge University Press.

  • Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth and logic. Victor Gollancz.

  • Ayer, A. J. (1946–1947). Phenomenalism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 47, 163–196.

  • Bain, J. (2006). Spacetime structuralism. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 37–65). Elsevier.

  • Bird, A. (2005). The ultimate argument against Armstrong’s contingent necessitation view of laws. Analysis, 65(2), 147–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boscovich, Roger Joseph. (1763/1922). A Theory of Natural Philosophy, J.M. Child, trans. Open Court Publishing Company.

  • Broad, C. D. (1925). Mind and its place in nature. Harcourt, Brace & Co.

  • Campbell, K. (1970). Body and mind. Macmillan.

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. In Search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press.

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In S. G. Tamar & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–200). Clarendon Press.

  • Chalmers, D. (2010). The matrix as metaphysics. The character of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

  • Chalmers, D. (2017). Panpsychism and panprotopsychism. In B. Godehard & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 19–47). Oxford University Press.

  • Dainton, B. The silence of physics. Erkenntnis .

  • Davidson, D. (2001). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In I. Subjective (Ed.), Objective (pp. 137–157). Clarendon Press.

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1938–1939). The relation between mathematics and physics. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 59(2), 122.

  • Eddington, A. S. (1929). The nature of the physical world. Macmillan.

  • Foster, J. (1993). The succinct case for idealism. In H. Robinson (Ed.), Objections to physicalism (pp. 293–313). Clarendon Press.

  • Foster, J. (2008). A world for us: The case for phenomenalistic idealism. Oxford University Press.

  • French, Steven. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford University Press.

  • Fumerton, R. (1985). Metaphysical and epistemological problems of perception. University of Nebraska Press.

  • Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and fundamental reality. Oxford University Press.

  • Handfield, T. (2005). Armstrong and the modal inversion of dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 55(220), 452–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1946). Leibniz’s greatest discovery. Journal of the History of Ideas, 7(4), 411–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2015). Serious theories and skeptical theories: Why you are probably not a brain in a vat. Philosophical Studies, 173(4), 1031–1052.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A representative theory. Cambridge University Press.

  • Jackson, F. (1994). Finding the mind in the natural world. In Philosophy and Cognitive Sciences: Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein Symposium Roberto Casati, B. Smith, and Stephen L. White, Holder-Pichler-Tempsky, (pp. 227–249).

  • James, W. (1912). La notion de conscience. Essays in radical empiricism (pp. 206–233). Longman Green & Company.

  • Kant, I. (1781/1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press.

  • Kirk, R. (1974). Sentience and behavior. Mind, 83(329), 43–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurret, D., & Collier, J. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press.

  • Langton, R. (1998). Kantian humility: Our ignorance of things in themselves. Clarendon Press.

  • Langton, R., & Lewis, D. (1998). Defining ‘intrinsic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(2), 333–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1946). An analysis of knowledge and valuation. Open Court.

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50(3), 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1694/1979). An essay concerning human understanding. Clarendon Press.

  • Mackie, J. L. (1976). Problems from locke. Clarendon Press.

  • Marshall, D. (2016). An analysis of intrinsicality. Noûs, 50(4), 704–739.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, D., & Parsons, J. (2001). Langton and Lewis on “Intrinsic". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(2), 347–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKitrick, J. (2003). The bare metaphysical possibility of bare dispositions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(2), 349–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1865/1979). An examination of Sir William Hamilton’s philosophy, and of the principal philosophical questions discussed in his writings. University of Toronto Press.

  • Mørch, H. H. (2014). Panpsychism and Causation: A New Argument and a Solution to the Combination Problem. Ph.D. thesis, University of Oslo.

  • Mumford, S. (2006). The ungrounded argument. Synthese, 149(3), 471–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1979). Panpsychism. In Mortal questions (pp. 181–195). Cambridge University Press.

  • Pelczar, M. (2019). Defending phenomenalism. Philosophical Quarterly, 69(276), 574–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47, 44–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. H. (1932). Perception. Methuen & Co.

  • Price, H. H. (1940). Hume’s theory of the external world. Clarendon Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1982). Brains in a vat. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Reason, truth, and history (pp. 1–21). Cambridge University Press.

  • Robinson, H. (1982). Matter and sense: A critique of contemporary materialism. Cambridge University Press.

  • Rovelli, C. (2006). The disappearance of space and time. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 25–36). Elsevier.

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Williams & Norgate.

  • Russell, B. (1927a). The analysis of matter. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

  • Russell, B. (1927). An outline of philosophy. George Allen & Unwin.

  • Russell, B. (1927/1992). The analysis of matter. Routledge.

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Clarendon Press.

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithson, R. (2017). A new epistemic argument for idealism. In T. Goldschmidt & K. L. Pearce (Eds.), Idealism: New essays in metaphysics (pp. 17–33). Oxford University Press.

  • Stephan, A. (2017). Emergence and panpsychism. In G. Brüntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 334–48). Oxford University Press.

  • Stoljar, D. (2001). Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(2), 253–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2020). Panpsychism and non-standard materialism: Some comparative remarks. In W. E. Seager (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of panpsychism (pp. 218–229). Routledge.

  • Stoljar, D., & Smith, M. (1998). Global response-dependence and noumenal realism. The Monist, 81(1), 85–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2003). Realistic materialism. In L. M. Antony & N. Hornstein (Eds.), Chomsky and his critics (pp. 49–88). Blackwell.

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism. In A. Freeman (Ed.), Consciousness and its place in nature: Does physicalism entail panpsychism? (pp. 3–29). Imprint Academic.

  • Strawson, G. (2008). Real materialism: And other essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Strawson, G. (2017). Mind and being: The primacy of panpsychism. In Godehard Brüntrup & Ludwig Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 75–112). Oxford University Press.

  • Strawson, G. (2020). What does “physical" mean? A prolegomenon to physicalist panpsychism. In W. Seager (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of panpsychism (pp. 317–339). Routledge.

  • Tegmark, M. (2014). Our mathematical universe: My quest for the ultimate nature of reality. Alfred A. Knopf.

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(11), 658–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (2005). The refutation of skepticism. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell Publishing.

Download references

Funding

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Pelczar.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pelczar, M. The case for panpsychism: a critical assessment. Synthese 200, 312 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03775-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03775-y

Keywords

Navigation