Skip to main content
Log in

Dennettian Panpsychism: Multiple Drafts, All of Them Conscious

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I explore some surprising convergences between apparently opposite theories of consciousness—panpsychism (specifically constitutive panpsychism) and eliminativism (specifically Dennett’s multiple drafts model). I outline what a ‘Dennettian panpsychism’ might look like, and consider some of the challenging but fertile questions it raises about determinacy, holism, and subjecthood.

What unites constitutive panpsychism and the multiple drafts model is that both present the unitary consciousness we can report as resting atop a multiplicity of independent processes; both reject as misguided the search for a definite threshold between processing that is truly conscious and that which is merely preconscious. What divides them is that Dennett regards it as unreasonable to posit inaccessible consciousness, but reasonable to doubt or deny the existence of consciousness, while panpsychists think the opposite.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For my interpretation here, I am indebted to Akins (1996), who pulls out a number of key theses that constitute the multiple drafts model: the three most important for the discussion in this section are:

    • ‘There are no’fixed facts’ about the events and contents of conscious experience other than facts about probes (and bindings). […].

    • On a small time scale, there is no distinction, in principle, between a revision of perceptual input and a revision of memory. […].

    • There is no determinate time of occurrence for conscious events. (Akins 1996, pp.2–3).

  2. On ‘fusionist’ panpsychism, defended by Seager (2010, 2017) and Mørch (2014), the phenomenal field of a human being is an indivisible whole, which arises when many simpler phenomenal elements come together in the right configuration but is not in any literal sense composed of those elements: once the whole exist, the parts are gone. A similar mutual exclusion between conscious parts and conscious whole is built into the Integrated Information theory (Oizumi et al., 2014; Tononi 2012), which is not panpsychist but close to it.

  3. Dennett talks about the multiple drafts almost always in representational terms: he is interested in what seems to the subject to be happening, how the world is presented to them. Most panpsychists are not pan-representationalists: that is, they generally do not take all forms of consciousness to have representational content. This means that the account of determinacy and indeterminacy given here can’t go ‘all the way down’ to the level of molecules and atoms. But it is perfectly compatible with this to think of consciousness as mostly or always representational once we reach the level of neural subsystems.

References

  • Akins, K. (1996). Lost the plot? Reconstructing Dennett’s multiple drafts theory of consciousness. Mind & Language, 71(1), 1–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2010). The unity of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., & Chalmers, D. (2003). What is the unity of consciousness? In A. Cleeremans (Ed.), The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration, Dissociation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2007). Overflow, access, and attention. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5–6), 530–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2008). Consciousness and cognitive access. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, 289–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2011). Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(12), 567–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boly, M., et al. (2017). Are the neural correlates of consciousness in the front or in the back of the cerebral cortex? Clinical and neuroimaging evidence. The Journal of Neuroscience, 37(40), 9603–9613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bronfman, Z., Brezis, N., Jacobson, H., & Usher, M. (2014). We see more than we can report: ‘Cost-free’ color phenomenality outside focal attention. Psychological Science, 25, 1394–1403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R. (2012). “The myth of phenomenal overflow.” Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 599–604. 

  • Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2015). Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism. In Y. Nagasawa & T. Alter (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Essays on Russellian monism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2017). The combination problem for panpsychism. In G. Brüntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M., & Dennett, D. (2011). Consciousness cannot be separated from function. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, 358–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1988). The waterfall illusion. Analysis, 48(3), 142–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2000). Stream of consciousness: Unity and continuity in conscious experience. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Changeux, J.-P., Naccache, L., Sackur, J., & Sergent, C. (2006). Conscious, preconscious, and subliminal processing: A testable taxonomy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 204–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. (1988). Quining Qualia. In A. Marcel & E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in Modern Science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1992). The self as centre of narrative gravity. In F. Kessel, P. Cole, & D. Johnson (Eds.), Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, J., & Humphreys, G. W. (1989). Visual search and stimulus similarity. Psychological Review, 96, 433–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, J., & Humphreys, G. (1992). Beyond the search surface: visual search and attentional engagement. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18(2), 578–588. discussion 589–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Efron, R. (1967). The duration of the present. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 138, 713–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fink, S. (Ms.) ‘How many stripes are on the tiger in my dreams?’ https://philarchive.org/rec/FINHMS. Accessed October 2021.

  • Fink, S., Lyre, H., & Kob, L. (2021). A structural constraint on neural correlates of consciousness. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2(7). https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.79.

  • Freeman, J., & Simoncelli, E. P. (2011). Metamers of the ventral stream. Nature Neuroscience, 14(9), 1195–1201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geldard, F. (1982). Saltation in somesthesis. Psychological Bulletin, 92(1), 136–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geldard, F., & Sherrick, C. (1972). The cutaneous ‘rabbit’: A perceptual illusion. Science, 178(4057), 178–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2013). Orthodox property dualism + linguistic theory of vagueness = panpsychism. In R. Brown (Ed.), Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and fundamental reality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P., & Roelofs, L. (Forthcoming). “In defence of phenomenal sharing.” In J. Bugnon, M. Nida-Rümelin, & D. O’Conaill (Eds.), The phenomenology of self-awareness and conscious subjects. Routledge.

  • Gross, S., & Flombaum, J. (2017). Does perceptual consciousness overflow cognitive access? The challenge from probabilistic, hierarchical processes. Mind and Language, 32(3), 257–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haun, A.M., Tononi, G., Koch, C., & Tsuchiya, N. (2017). Are we underestimating the richness of visual experience? Neuroscience of Consciousness (1)1–4.

  • Husserl, E. (1991). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917), trans. John Brough, Collected Works, (Vol. 4). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolers, P., & von Grünau, M. (1976). Shape and color in apparent motion. Vision Research, 16(4), 329–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kouider, S., de Gardelle, V., & Sackur, J. (2012). Do we still need phenomenal consciousness? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, 140–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kouider, S., & Dehaene, S. (2007). Levels of processing during non-conscious perception: A critical review of visual masking. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 362, 857–875.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamme, V. (2015). The crack of dawn: Perceptual functions and neural mechanisms that mark the transition from unconscious processing to conscious vision. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds), Open MIND: 22(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group (pp. 1-34). https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570092.

  • Lau, H., & Rosenthal, D. (2011). Empirical support for higher-order theories of conscious awareness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(8), 365–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, D. M. (2008). Crowding–An essential bottleneck for object recognition: A mini-review. Vision Research, 48, 635–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendelovici, Angela. (2020). Panpsychism’s combination problem is a problem for everyone. In W. Seager (Ed.), Routledge Handbook of Panpsychism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. (2017). Can subjects be proper parts of subjects? The de-combination problem. Ratio, 30(2), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. (2018). Forming a positive concept of the phenomenal bonding relation for constitutive panpsychism. Dialectica, 71(4), 541–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2017). What combination problem? In G. Brüntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mørch, H. H. (2014). ‘Panpsychism and causation: A new argument and a solution to the combination problem PhD dissertation. University of Oslo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, J. (2016). Perceptual confidence. Analytic Philosophy, 57(1), 15–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2004). ‘Panpsychism’ (originally published 1979). In D. S. Clarke (ed.), Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings. Albany: State University of New York Press

  • Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., & Tononi, G. (2014). ‘From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated information theory 3.0.’ PLOS Computational Biology 10(5), e1003588. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003588.

  • Pelli, D. G., & Tillman, K. A. (2008). The uncrowded window of object recognition. Nature Neuroscience, 11, 1129–1135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pockett, S. (2002). On subjective back-referral and how long it takes to become conscious of a stimulus: A reinterpretation of Libet’s data. Consciousness and Cognition, 8, 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pockett, S. (2003). How long is ‘now’? Phenomenology and the specious present. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2, 55–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roelofs, L. (2016). “The unity of consciousness, within and between subjects.” Philosophical Studies, 173(12), 3199–3221. 

  • Roelofs, L. (2019). Combining minds: How to think about composite subjectivity. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Roelofs, L. (2020). “Can we sum subjects? Evaluating Panpsychism’s hard problem.” In W. Seager (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of Panpsychism (pp. 245–258). New York: Routledge.

  • Rosenthal, D. (2007). Phenomenological overflow and cognitive access. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5–6), 522–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2014). The crazyist metaphysics of mind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92(2014), 665–682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (1995). Consciousness, information and panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2–3, 272–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2006). The ‘Intrinsic Nature’ argument for panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10–11), 129–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2010). Panpsychism, aggregation and combinatorial infusion. Mind and Matter, 8(2), 167–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2017). Panpsychist infusion. In G. Brüntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechter, E. (2013). Two unities of consciousness. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(2), 197–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2003). Consciousness and co-consciousness. In Axel Cleeremans (Ed.), The Unity of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 74(11), 1–29.

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic monism—Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10–11), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2012). Integrated information theory of consciousness: An updated account. Archives Italiennes De Biologie, 150(2–3), 56–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A., & Gelade, G. (1980). A feature-integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology, 12(1), 97–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A., & Sato, S. (1990). Conjunction search revisited. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 16(3), 459–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsuchiya, N., et al. (2015). No-Report paradigms: Extracting the true neural correlates of consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 19(12), 757–770

  • Tye, M. (2009). A new look at the speckled hen. Analysis, 69(2), 258–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2010). Up close with the speckled hen. Analysis, 70(2), 283–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1912). Experimentelle Studien über das Sehen von Bewegung [Experimental studies on motion vision]. Zeitschrift Für Psychologie, 61(1), 161–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, P. (2015). ‘The emergence of mental content: An essay in the metaphysics of mind PhD dissertation. Oslo: University of Oslo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, P. (2021). “The selection problem for constitutive Panpsychism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 99(3), 564–578.

  • Zeki, S. (2007). A theory of micro-consciousness. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper expands on some themes first discussed over pages 222 to 225 of Roelofs, 2019. Its further development owes a great deal to helpful conversations with, among many others, Sascha Benjamin Fink, Krzysztof Dolega, Burke Hendrix, Donnchadh O’Conaill, and anonymous referees for Acta Analytica.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luke Roelofs.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roelofs, L. Dennettian Panpsychism: Multiple Drafts, All of Them Conscious. Acta Anal 37, 323–340 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00496-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00496-8

Keywords

Navigation