Skip to main content
Log in

Signals are minimal causes

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although the definition of ‘signal’ has been controversial for some time within the life sciences, current approaches seem to be converging toward a common analysis. This powerful framework can satisfactorily accommodate many cases of signaling and captures some of its main features. This paper argues, however, that there is a central feature of signals that so far has been largely overlooked: its special causal role. More precisely, I argue that a distinctive feature of signals is that they are minimal causes. I explain this notion, suggest some strategies for identifying its instances and defend its relevance by means of conceptual and empirical considerations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In most of the examples we will discuss, the roles of sender and receiver are played by different organisms, but they can also be parts of the same organism (e.g. brain states, hormones).

  2. Probably, processes other than natural selection (such as learning) can also ground functions (Abrams 2005; Frick et al. 2019; Shea 2018). Nonetheless, for simplicity, and given that most of the examples we will discuss involve evolutionary functions, I will focus on those.

  3. Nonetheless, not everyone agrees with this picture. For instance, some people hold that an evolved sender is not required (e.g. Stegmann 2009; cf. Artiga 2014). Fortunately, I think that nothing I'll say here depends on this claim. Others, however, oppose the idea that animal communication involves an exchange of meaningful signals (Dawkins and Krebs 1978; Rendall et al. 2009; Rendall and Owren 2013). This latter approach will be briefly discussed in Sect. 4.3.

  4. In certain special circumstances, saliva might actually work as a signal. For instance, some stingless bees use saliva to lay a trail that indicates that an important source of food has been found (Schorkopf et al. 2007). Nonetheless, it is much harder to accept that saliva plays a representational role simply in virtue of how it is used in digestion.

  5. Millikan (1984) was one of the first philosophers to propose a teleological theory of representations along the lines of RV.

  6. As a reviewer suggested, one might object that it is not obvious that the mouth or the stomach has the function of responding to the presence of saliva. In any case, I think this example is not only of historical interest, but also points in the direction of a range of similar examples that do seem to raise a real challenge.

  7. Nonetheless, I think that some objections along the same lines actually fail to challenge RV (Scarantino 2013a: p. 76; Scott-Phillips 2008). RV, for instance, rightly excludes reciprocal interactions from being signals. Consider grooming: it alters the behavior of another individual (toward reciprocity) and probably evolved because of this effect, but in this case there is no clear condition C that grooming is supposed to correspond to, and whose presence causes the recipient's action to increase fitness. Certainly, sometimes grooming works as a signal, as when a chimpanzee engages in this activity in order to indicate her willingness to build an enduring relationship (de Waal 1982). However, in this case, the sender’s positive attitude toward engaging in a relationship plays the role of C, so RV correctly entails that it is a signal (cf. Kalkman 2019).

  8. These two conditions could be expressed more succinctly as follows: ‘S is a non-enabling cause of A.’ Nonetheless, for clarity of exposition, I prefer to keep these two claims separate here.

  9. 'Intervention' is here a technical term: it roughly means an ideal manipulation by which we change the value of a particular variable.

  10. Another criterion provided by Macedonia and Evans (1993: p. 179), which is still very important in actual research (Shettleworth 2010: p. 515) is production specificity: a signal that refers to a particular object must reliably be given in its presence, and not under other conditions (see also Smith 1991: p. 215). Although this criterion might be heuristically useful for identifying signals, I presume it probably fails to point to a distinctive property of signals. In short, my worry is that if this criterion is understood strongly, then it is incompatible with the possibility of misrepresentation (i.e. the fact that signals are sometimes given in the wrong conditions; see Scarantino 2013b), whereas weakly understood it just claims that signals carry correlational information of whatever they represent, which probably follows from RV above, and does not seem to distinguish signals from other causes.

  11. This suggests that the notion of a ‘signal’ is vague, in the sense that it has borderline cases. In general, I think we should expect that to be true for most biological categories (Godfrey-Smith 2009).

  12. As a reviewer suggested, the notion of a ‘nearly complete’ mechanism plays an important role here. I explained above some aspects that are relevant for understanding this notion (e.g. it comes in degrees, some aspects might be more important than others,…), and I hope that future work will allow me to specify this notion in more detail.

  13. These experiments are also used to draw conclusions about the cognitive mechanisms involved in signal perception (i.e. to investigate whether it involves cognitive representations or not; see e.g. Kalkman 2017; Zuberbühler 1999).

  14. I will interpret ‘information’ as ‘semantic information’ (i.e. semantic content), not as Shannon information.

  15. An additional reason for thinking that this analysis challenges the traditional attribution of informational content to the túngara’s frog’s signals is that, on this analysis, it is not obvious that the receiver has a signal-specific response. In any event, my goal here is to provide one reason why the manipulationist framework is in tension with an informational one, but this is compatible with other ways of framing the debate. I would like to thank a reviewer for pressing me on this issue.

  16. It should be mentioned that there are certain formal properties of the signal that can explain behaviour without compromising its status as a minimal cause. For instance, when complex signals exhibit some form of systematicity or compositionality, the action might depend on some formal properties. I hope the discussion in the main text illustrates the kind of intrinsic properties that are in tension with the state’s being a minimal cause (e.g. its being an enabling cause).

  17. Interestingly, those who endorse a representational/informational paradigm reply that their approach enables theorists to apply the same mathematical models across taxa and modalities, whereas manipulationists hold that this position has contributed to neglecting the study of signal design (Seyfarth et al. 2010; Rendall et al. 2009; Stegmann 2013: p. 21). This is precisely what we should expect if we assume that signals are minimal causes: to the extent that a signal is representational, its format is much less explanatory. For this reason, a representational/informational perspective facilitates a more widespread use of similar models and tends to pay less attention to the signal’s formal properties.

References

  • Abrams, M. (2005). Teleosemantics without natural selection. Biology and Philosophy, 20(1), 97–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman, J. D. (2000). Abiotic pollen and pollination: Ecological, functional, and evolutionary perspectives. Plant Systematics and Evolution, 222(1–4), 167–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of mind. New York: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Artiga, M. (2014). Signaling without cooperation. Biology and Philosophy, 29, 357–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baluska, F., Mancuso, S., & Volkmann, S. (Eds.). (2006). Communication in plants. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baluska, F., & Ninkovic, V. (Eds.). (2010). Plant communication form an ecological perspective. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradbury, J., & Vehrencamp, S. (1998). Principles of animal communication. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butlin, P. (forthcoming). Representation and the active consumer. Synthese.

  • Calcott, B., Griffiths, P., & Pocheville, A. (forthcoming). Signals that make a difference. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Cheney, D., & Seyfarth, R. (1988). Assessment of meaning and the detection of unreliable signals by vervet monkeys. Animal Behavior, 36(2), 477–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheney, D., & Seyfarth, R. (1990). How monkeys see the world. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cheney, D., & Seyfarth, R. (2007). Baboon metaphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coppola, M., Cascone, P., Madonna, V., Di Lelio, I., Esposito, F., Avitabile, C., et al. (2017). Plant-to-plant communication triggered by systemin primes anti-herbivore resistance in tomato. Scientific Reports, 7, 15522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corrado, G., Sasso, R., Pasquariello, M., Iodice, L., Carretta, A., Cascone, P., et al. (2007). Systemin regulates both systemic and volatile signaling in tomato plants. Journal of Chemical Ecology, 33, 669–681.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R., & Krebs, J. (1978). Animal signals: Information or manipulation. In J. Krebs & A. Davies (Eds.), Behavioral ecology: An evolutionary approach. Amsterdam: Blackwell Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, F. (1982). Chimpanzee politics: Power and sex among apes. Baltimore: John Hopkins University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diggle, S., et al. (2007). Evolutionary Theory of bacterial quorum sensing: When a signal not a signal? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 362, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Ch., & Evans, L. (1999). Chicken food calls are functionally referential. Animal Behavior, 58(2), 307–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Ch., & Evans, L. (2007). Representational signalling in birds. Biology Letters, 3(1), 8–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frick, R., Bich, L., & Moreno, A. (2019). An organisational approach to biological communication. Acta Biotheoretica, 67(2), 103–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J., & Barrett, S. (2009). Wind of change: New insights on the ecology and evolution of pollination and mating in wind-pollinated plants. Annals of Botany, 103(9), 1515–1527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2013). The functional sense of mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 80(3), 317–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 64, 605–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. S. (2017). New mechanical philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2013). Information and influence in sender–receiver models. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory. Information and influence (p. 2013). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P., & Martinez, M. (2013). Communication and common interest. PLoS Computational Biology, 9(11), e1003282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hasson, O. (1994). Cheating signals. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 167(3), 223–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalkman, D. (2017). Information, influence, and the causal-explanatory role of content in understanding receiver responses. Biology and Philosophy, 32(6), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalkman, D. (2019). New problems for defining animal communication in informational terms. Synthese, 196(8), 3319–3336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karakashian, S. J., Gyger, M., & Marler, P. (1988). Audience effects on alarm calling in chickens (Gallus gallus). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 102(2), 129–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macedonia, J., & Evans, Ch. (1993). Variation among mammalian alarm call systems and the problem of meaning in animal signals. Ethology, 93, 177–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maier, J. (2014). Abilities. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/abilities/.

  • Manser, M., & Fletcher, B. M. (2001). The information that receivers extract from alarm calls in suricates. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences., 268(1484), 2485–2491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal signals. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. New York: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, S., Morgan, D., Lonsdorf, E., Mundry, R., & Sanz, C. (2016). Tool transfers are a form of teaching among chimpanzees. Scientific Reports, 6, 34783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2012). Teleological theories of mental content. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/content-teleological.

  • Otte, D. (1974). Effects and functions in the evolution of signaling systems. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 5, 385–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D., & McDonald, G. (2006). Teleosemantics. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Planer, R., & Kalkman, D. (2019). Arbitrary signals and cognitive complexity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 78, 233–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rendall, D., & Owren, M. (2013). Communication without meaning or information: Abandoning language-based and informational constructs in animal communication theory. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory: Information and influence (pp. 151–182). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rendall, D., Owren, M., & Ryan, M. (2009). What do animal signals mean? Animal Behavior, 78, 233–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, L., Stewart, L., & Kaplan, G. (2018). Food calls in common marmosets, Callithrix jacchus, and evidence that one is functionally referential. Animals, 8(7), 99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, C. (2000). The systemin signaling pathway: Differential activation of plant defensive genes. Biopchimica et Biophysica Acta., 1477, 112–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, M. (2013). The importance of integrative biology to sexual selection and communication. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory: Information and influence (pp. 233–256). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Saussure, F. (1916). Cours de linguistique générale. Paris: Payot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2013a). Animal communication as information-mediated influence. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory: Information and influence (pp. 63–88). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2013b). Rethinking functional reference. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 1006–1018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A., & Clay, Z. (2015). Contextually variable signals can be functionally referential. Animal Behaviour, 100, e1–e8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schorkopf, D. L., Jarau, S., & Francke, W. (2007). Spitting out information: Trigona bees deposit saliva to signal resource locations. Proceedings of the Royal Society: Biological Sciences, 274(1611), 895–898.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips, T. C. (2008). Defining biological information. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 21, 387–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searcy, W., & Novicky, S. (2005). The evolution of animal communication. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth, R., & Cheney, D. (2017). The origin of meaning in animal signals. Animal Behavior, 124, 339–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth, R., Cheney, D., Bergmann, T., Fischer, J., Zuberbühler, K., & Hammerschmidt, K. (2010). The central importance of information in studies of animal communication. Animal Behavior, 80(1), 3–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth, R., Cheney, D., & Marler, P. (1980). Monkey responses to three different alarm calls: Evidence of predator classification and semantic communication. Science, 210(4471), 801–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2018). Representations in cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. (2010). Cognition, evolution and behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. J. (1991). Animal communication and the study of cognition. In C. A. Ristau & D. R. Griffin (Eds.), Cognitive ethology: The minds of animals: Essays in honor of Donald R. Griffin (pp. 209–230). Hillsdale, N.J: L. Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. (2004). The abritrariness of the genetic code. Biology and Philosophy, 19(2), 205–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. (2009). A consumer-based teleosemantics for animal signals. Philosophy of Science, 76, 864–875.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. (2013). Animal communication theory: Information and influence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Struhsaker, T. T. (1967). Auditory communication among vervet monkeys (Cercopithecus aethiops). In S. A. Altmann (Ed.), Social communication among primates (pp. 281–324). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ueda, H., Kikuta, Y., & Matsuda, K. (2012). Plant communication. Plant signaling and behavior, 7(2), 222–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, L., Einig, E., Almeida-Trapp, M., Albert, M., Fliegmann, J., Mithöfer, A., et al. (2018). The systemin receptor SYR1 enhances resistence of tomato against herbivorous insects. Nature Plants, 4, 152–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, B., & Fisher, J. (2012). Functionally referential signals: A promising paradigm whose time has passed. Evolutionary Anthropology, 21(5), 195–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, B., & Fisher, J. (2015). The blurred boundaries of functional reference: a response to Scarantino & Clay. Animal Behaviour, 100, e9–e13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiley, R. H. (1994). Errors, exaggeration, and deception in animal communication, ch. 7. In L. Real (Ed.), Behavioral mechanisms in ecology (pp. 157–189). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley, R. (2013). Communication as a transfer of information: Measurement, mechanism and meaning. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory. Information and influence (p. 2013). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. (1975). Sociobiology: the New Synthesis. Harvard University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causality in biology: Stability, specificity and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, A., & Zahavi, A. (1997). The handicap principle: A missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuberbühler, K. (1999). Referential labelling in Diana monkeys. Animal Behavior, 59(5), 917–927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zuberbühler, K. (2000). Predator-specific alarm calls in campbell’s monkeys, Cercopithecus campbelli. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 50(5), 414–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuberbühler, K., Cheney, D., & Seyfarth, R. (1999). Conceptual semantics in a nonhuman primate. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 113(1), 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Leonardo Bich, Mihnea Capraru, Marta Campdelacreu, Sabrina Engesser, Samir Okasha, Javier González de Prado Salas, Kirsty Graham, John Horden, Manolo Martínez, Richard Moore, Saúl Pérez, Aida Roige, Miguel Ángel Sebastián, Nicholas Shea, Dan Zeman and the audiences at the VII SEFA Conference, the Seminario de Filosofía de la Mente at the Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas at the Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, the ISCHPSSB 2019 Conference at the University of Oslo and the 1st Varieties of Information Workshop on Animal Communication at the University of Barcelona. Financial support was provided by the Ministerio de Economía y Competitivdad through the projects ‘La Complejidad de la Percepción: un enfoque multidimensional’ (FFI2014-51811-P) and ‘Varieties of Information’ (PGC2018-101425-B-I00).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Artiga.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Artiga, M. Signals are minimal causes. Synthese 198, 8581–8599 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02589-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02589-0

Keywords

Navigation