Skip to main content
Log in

Conditional desirability: comments on Richard Bradley’s decision theory with a human face

  • Decision-making and hypothetical reasoning
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Richard Bradley’s landmark book Decision Theory with a Human Face makes seminal contributions to nearly every major area of decision theory, as well as most areas of formal epistemology and many areas of semantics. In addition to sketching Bradley’s distinctive semantics for conditional beliefs and desires, I will explain his theory of conditional desire, focusing particularly on his claim that we should not desire events, either positively or negatively, under the supposition that they will occur. I shall argue, to the contrary, that permitting non-trivial desirabilities for events whose occurrence is known or assumed is both more intuitively plausible and more theoretically fruitful than Bradley’s approach. In the course of the discussion I will contrast Bradley’s broadly evidentialist picture of decision theory with my own more orthodox causal approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bradley also discusses interventional supposition, which is used in causal modeling in the tradition of Spirtes, et al. (2000) and Pearl (2000). I think interventional supposition is a subspecies of subjunctive supposition. See Joyce (2010) for details.

  2. More specifically, we make sure that one proposition X is more likely than another Y under the supposition of A only if A & X is unconditionally more probable than A & Y.

  3. I will be sloppy with use/mention. Here each potential antecedent An is a sentence that is associated with a proposition [An] ⊆ W. Also, in Bradley’s theory one can suppose arbitrary prospects, but for simplicity, I will consider only supposed propositions.

  4. The content of a sentence is the set of all atomic prospects at which it is true.

  5. Readers interested in non-uniqueness are referred to Joyce (1999, pp. 122–145) and Bradley (2017, pp. 84–88) for relevant discussion.

  6. This is not Bradley’s example. In his example the relevant proposition is I am isolated, and the assumption is that any news I receive would convince me that I am not isolated. I find this example needlessly vague owing to the difficulty in explaining what it is to be “isolated”.

  7. Readers may convince themselves that this defines a probability over worlds in An that satisfies both Certainty and Anchoring.

  8. For simplicity, I will confine my attention to the desirabilities of propositions. All of what I say here could be said for more general prospects.

  9. This equation captures the idea, defended in Joyce (1999, p. 178) that all value is news value assessed from a particular epistemic perspective.

  10. For Certainty, use the equivalence of An *→ (ω & An) and An *→ ω.

  11. Vn*(X) = Σω un(ω)·P *n (ω | X) = Σω kn·(u(ω) · P *n (ω | X) – Jn*(⊤*)) = kn·(Jn*(X) − Jn*(⊤*)).

  12. Both causal and evidential decision theorists can agree to this, though they will advocate different sorts of supposition. For the causalist it will be counterfactual/interventionist supposition, for the evidentialist it will be indicative/evidential supposition.

  13. Since I am a causal decision theorist, I endorse this rule with counterfactual/interventional supposition. Were I an evidentialist, I would endorse it with indicative/evidential supposition.

  14. I am simplifying Bradley’s notation somewhat.

  15. The penultimate identity holds because P(An) = 1, and ultimate one holds via modus ponens.

  16. For simplicity I am going to assume that both α and β are ranked above the initial status quo. If they were ranked below ⊤*, then their cost would be negative, i.e., one would be paid to accept their truth.

  17. A similar argument shows that you will do the same if “<” is replaced by “>”.

References

  • Adams, E. (1975). The logic of conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armendt, B. (1988). Conditional preference and causal expected utility. In W. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change and statistics (pp. 3–24). London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1988). Farewell to the phlogiston theory of conditionals. Mind, 97, 509–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. (2017). Decision theory with a human face. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1983/1965). The Logic of decision, 2nd revised edition. University of Chicago Press: Chicago.

  • Joyce, J. M. (1999). The foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. M. (2010). Causal reasoning and backtracking. Philosophical Studies, 147, 139–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1976). The probability of conditionals and conditional probabilities. The Philosophical Review, 85(3), 297–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. (1931). General propositions and causality. In R. B. Braithwaite (Ed.), The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays [by F. P. Ramsey]. London: London Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. N. (2000). Causation, prediction, and search. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weirich, P. (1980). Conditional utility and its place in decision theory. Journal of Philosophy, 77(11), 702–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James M. Joyce.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I would like to thank Jason Mckenzie Alexander, Richard Bradley, Jason Konek, Christian List, Sarah Moss, Orri Stefánsson, and Brian Weatherson for useful input on the content of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Joyce, J.M. Conditional desirability: comments on Richard Bradley’s decision theory with a human face. Synthese 198, 8413–8431 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02579-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02579-2

Keywords

Navigation