Skip to main content
Log in

Conservative translations of four-valued logics in modal logic

  • S.I.: Varieties of Entailment
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Following a proposal by Kooi and Tamminga, we introduce a conservative translation manual for every four-valued truth-functional propositional logic into a modal logic. However, the application of this translation does not preserve the intuitive reading of the truth-values for every four-valued logic. In order to solve this problem, we modify the translation manual and prove its conservativity by exploiting the method of generalized truth-values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The idea of exploiting the method of generalized truth-values firstly appeared in Kubyshkina (2017), but no technical details were provided.

  2. For more details on the distinction between designated truth values for the premises and for the conclusion see Cobreros et al. (2012).

  3. In this sense, LRA is a logic of generalized truth values.

  4. For instance, if one considers that the weakest system that is suitable for knowledge representation should be the system T, with \(K\phi \rightarrow \phi \) as the characteristic axiom, the following property can be imposed on the frames: if \(X \in N_{w}\), then \(w \in X\). It is not difficult to see that this property will not change the structure of the conservativity proof that follows. Moreover, having this property the definition of the translations T1 and F1 can be simplified: T1(p) can be defined as Kp, and F1(p) can be defined as \(K \lnot p\).

  5. \(\mathfrak {X}(\varGamma ) \models _{M}^{w} \mathfrak {Y}(\phi )\) is an abbreviation for ‘if \(M, w \models _{M} \mathfrak {X}(\psi )\) for all \(\psi \in \varGamma \), then \(M, w \models _{M} \mathfrak {Y}(\phi )\)’.

  6. One can keep \(\emptyset \) without altering the proofs that follow. To do so, it suffices to define all the logical operators in a way that they do not distinguish the \(\emptyset \) and \(\{F1\}\) values. For example, if a formula \(\phi \) takes value \(\{F1\}\) and \(\lnot _{4} \phi \) takes value \(\{T1\}\), and if a formula \(\psi \) takes value \(\emptyset \), then \(\lnot \psi \) takes value \(\{T1\}\).

  7. It is not difficult to see, that an order \(x \le y \Leftrightarrow x = x \wedge y\) and a linear lattice of truth-values can be defined for LRA.

  8. The functions \(v^{4}_{1}(\phi ),\ldots ,v^{4}_{n}(\phi )\) are possible \(v^{4}\) valuations of \(\phi \). Keeping in mind the Lemma 6, where each valuation was associated with a 4-w-equivalent world, the use of the subscripts 1, ..., n facilitates notationally the association of the valuations \(v^{4}_{1}(\phi ),\ldots ,v^{4}_{n}(\phi )\) with their 4-w-equivalent worlds \(w_{1}\), ..., \(w_{n}\) respectively.

References

  • Belnap, N. D. (1977a). How a computer should think. In G. Ryle (Ed.), Contemporary aspects of philosophy (pp. 30–55). Stocksfield: Oriel Press Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. D. (1977b). A useful four-valued logic. Modern uses of multiple-valued logic, volume 2 of the series Episteme (pp. 5–37).

  • Cobreros, P., Égré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1976). Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and ‘coupled trees’. Philosophical Studies, 29, 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kooi, B., & Tamminga, A. (2013). Three-valued logics in modal logic. Studia Logica, 101, 1061–1072.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kubyshkina, E. (2017). Ignorance without K(nowledge). Logica Yearbook, 2016, 109–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kubyshkina, E., & Zaitsev, D. V. (2016). Rational agency from a truth-functional perspective. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 25, 499–520.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odintsov, S. P., & Wansing, H. (2015). The logic of generalized truth values and the logic of bilattices. Studia Logica, 103(1), 91–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., Dunn, J. M., & Takenaka, T. (2001). The trilatice of constructive truth values. Journal of Logic and Computation, 11, 761–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2005). Some useful 16-valued logics: How a computer network should think. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34(2), 121–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2006). Hyper-contradictions, generalized truth-values and logics of truth and falsehood. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 15(4), 403–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2011). Truth and falsehood. An inquiry into generalized logical values. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for helpful comments and suggestions by two anonymous referees of Synthese. Thanks are also due to Paul Egré, Andreas Herzig, Mattia Petrolo, Nicholas J. J. Smith and Allard Tamminga for their feedbacks on previous drafts of some of this material.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ekaterina Kubyshkina.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kubyshkina, E. Conservative translations of four-valued logics in modal logic. Synthese 198 (Suppl 22), 5555–5571 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02139-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02139-3

Keywords

Navigation