Adler, J. E. (1994). Fallacies and alternative interpretations. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 271–282.
Google Scholar
Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental philosophy: An introduction. Cambridge: Polity.
Google Scholar
Alter, A. L., & Oppenheimer, D. M. (2009). Uniting the tribes of fluency to form a metacognitive nation. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 13, 219–235.
Google Scholar
Armstrong, R. A. (2014). When to use the Bonferroni correction. Ophthalmic and Psychological Optics, 34, 502–508.
Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. (1957). A plea for excuses. Proceeding s of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 1–30.
Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. (1962). Sense and sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. (1975). Sinn und Sinneserfahrung (E. Cassirer, Trans.). Stuttgart: Reclam.
Austin, J. L. (1984). Chikaku no Gengo: Sense to Sensibilia (N. Tanji & S. Moriya, Trans.). Tokyo: Keiso Shobo.
Ayer, A. J. (1940). Foundations of empirical knowledge. London: Macmillan.
Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. (1956/1990). The problem of knowledge. London: Penguin.
Ayer, A.J. (1981). Chishiki no Tetsugaku (K. Kamino, Trans.). Tokyo: Hakusuisha.
Ayer, A. J. (1991). Keikenteki Chishiki no Kiso (K. Kamino, T. Nakasai, & T. Nakatani, Trans.). Tokyo: Keiso Shobo.
Balota, D. A., & Lorch, R. F. (1986). Depth of automatic spreading activation: mediated by priming effects in pronunciation but not in lexical decision. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 12, 336–345.
Google Scholar
Barton, S. B., & Sanford, A. J. (1993). A case study of anomaly detection: Shallow semantic processing and cohesion establishment. Memory and Cognition, 21, 477–487.
Google Scholar
Baz, A. (2012). When words are called for: A defense of ordinary language philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Google Scholar
Baz, A. (2016). Ordinary language philosophy. In H. Cappelen, T. Szabo Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophical methodology (pp. 112–129). Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Baz, A. (2017). The crisis of method. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Bicknell, K., Elman, J. L., Hare, M., McRae, K., & Kutas, M. (2010). Effects of event knowledge in processing verbal arguments. Journal of Memory and Language, 63, 489–505.
Google Scholar
Bornkessel, I., McElree, B., Schlesewsky, M., & Friederici, A. D. (2004). Multi-dimensional contributions to garden path strength: Dissociating phrase structure from case marking. Journal of Memory and Language, 51, 495–522.
Google Scholar
Bortfeld, H., & McGlone, M. S. (2001). The continuum of metaphor processing. Metaphor and Symbol, 16, 75–86.
Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1923). Scientific thought. Repr. 2000. London: Routledge.
Brogaard, B. (2013). It’s not what it seems: a semantic account of ‘seems’ and seemings. Inquiry, 56, 210–239.
Google Scholar
Brogaard, B. (2014). The phenomenal use of ‘look’ and perceptual representation. Philosophy Compass, 9(7), 455–468.
Google Scholar
Cabin, R. J., & Mitchell, R. J. (2000). To Bonferroni or not to Bonferroni: When and how are the questions. Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America, 81, 246–248.
Google Scholar
Cappelen, H. (2012). Philosophy without intuitions. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Cavell, S. (1994). A pitch of philosophy: Autobiographical exercises. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving. Ithaca: Cornell UP.
Google Scholar
Chow, W., Smith, C., Lau, E., & Phillips, C. (2016). A ‘bag-of-arguments’ mechanism for initial verb predictions. Language, Cognition, and Neuroscience, 31, 577–596.
Google Scholar
Clark, A. (1996). Sensory qualities. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Cova, F. et al. (2018). Estimating the reproducibility of experimental philosophy.https://doi.org/10.17605/osf.io/sxdah.
Crane, T., & French, C. (2015). The problem of perception. In N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Summer 2015. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-problem/.
Dancy, J. (1985). Introduction to contemporary epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.
Google Scholar
De Neys, W. (2006). Automatic-heuristic and executive-analytic processing during reasoning: Chronometric and dual-task considerations. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 59, 1070–1100.
Google Scholar
De Neys, W., Schaeken, W., & D’Ydewalle, G. (2003). Inference suppression and semantic memory retrieval: Every counterexample counts. Memory and Cognition, 31, 581–595.
Google Scholar
De Neys, W., Cromheeke, S., & Osman, M. (2011). Biased but in doubt: Conflict and decision confidence. PLoS ONE. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0015954.
Article
Google Scholar
Deutsch, M. (2015). The myth of the intuitive. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Google Scholar
Eckman, F. R. (1977). Markedness and the contrastive analysis hypothesis. Language Learning, 27, 315–330.
Google Scholar
Elman, J. L. (2009). On the meaning of words and dinosaur bones: Lexical knowledge without a lexicon. Cognition, 33, 547–582.
Google Scholar
Erk, K. (2012). Vector space models of word meaning and phrase meaning: A survey. Language and Linguistics Compass, 6, 635–653.
Google Scholar
Farah, M. J., & McClelland, J. L. (1991). A computational model of semantic memory impairment: Modality specificity and emergent category specificity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 120, 339–357.
Google Scholar
Faust, M. E., & Gernsbacher, M. A. (1996). Cerebral mechanisms for suppression of inappropriate information during sentence comprehension. Brain and Language, 53, 234–259.
Google Scholar
Fein, O., Yeari, M., & Giora, R. (2015). On the priority of salience-based interpretations: The case of sarcastic irony. Intercultural Pragmatics, 12, 1–32.
Google Scholar
Ferguson, C. J. (2009). An effect size primer: A guide for clinicians and researchers. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice, 40, 532–538.
Google Scholar
Ferretti, T. R., Kutas, M., & McRae, K. (2007). Verb aspect and the activation of event knowledge. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 33, 182–196.
Google Scholar
Ferretti, T., McRae, K., & Hatherell, A. (2001). Integrating verbs, situation schemas, and thematic role concepts. Journal of Memory and Language, 44, 516–547.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E. (2011). Philosophical delusion and its therapy. Outline of a philosophical revolution. New York: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E. (2014a). Verbal fallacies and philosophical intuitions: The continuing relevance of ordinary language analysis. In B. Garvey (Ed.), J. L. Austin on language (pp. 124–140). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E. (2014b). Philosophical intuitions, heuristics, and metaphors. Synthese, 191, 569–606.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E. (2018a). Wittgensteinian ‘therapy’, experimental philosophy, and metaphilosophical naturalism. In K. Cahill & T. Raleigh (Eds.), Wittgenstein and naturalism (pp. 260–286). New York: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E. (2018b). Two analogy strategies: The cases of mind metaphors and introspection. Connection Science, 30, 211–243.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E., & Collins, J. (2015). Rationalism and naturalism in the age of experimental philosophy. In E. Fischer & J. Collins (Eds.), Experimental philosophy, rationalism and naturalism (pp. 3–33). London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E., & Engelhardt, P. E. (2016). Intuitions’ linguistic sources: Stereotypes, intuitions, and illusions. Mind and Language, 31, 67–103.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E., & Engelhardt, P. E. (2017). Stereotypical inferences: Philosophical relevance and psycholinguistic toolkit. Ratio, 30, 411–442.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E., & Engelhardt, P. E. (2019). Eyes as windows to minds: Psycholinguistics for experimental philosophy. In E. Fischer & M. Curtis (Eds.), Methodological advances in experimental philosophy (pp. 43–100). London: Bloomsbury.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E., & Engelhardt, P. E. (under review). Lingering stereotypes: Salience bias in philosophical arguments.
Fischer, E., Engelhardt, P. E., & Herbelot, A. (2015). Intuitions and illusions: From experiment and explanation to assessment. In E. Fischer & J. Collins (Eds.), Experimental philosophy, rationalism and naturalism (pp. 259–292). London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Fischer, E., Engelhardt, P. E., & Herbelot, A. (in prep). The expertise objection to experimental philosophy: A psycholinguistic perspective.
Fish, W. (2009). Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar
Fish, W. (2010). Philosophy of perception. London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Flickinger, D., Oepen, S., & Ytrestol, G. (2010). Wikiwoods: Syntacto-semantic annotation for the English Wikipedia. In N. Calzolari, K. Choukri, B. Maegaard, J. Mariani, J. Odijk, S. Piperidis, M. Rosner and D. Tapias (Eds.), Proceedings of the seventh international conference on language resources and evaluation (LREC2010) (pp. 1665–1671). Paris: European Language Resources Association.
Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
Google Scholar
Foss, D. J., & Speer, S. R. (1991). Global and local context effect in sentence processing. In R. R. Hoffman & D. S. Palermo (Eds.), Cognitive and the symbolic processes: Applied and ecological perspectives (pp. 115–139). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Google Scholar
Garrod, S., & Sanford, A. J. (1981). Bridging inferences and the extended domain of reference. In J. Long & A. Baddley (Eds.), Attention and performance IX (pp. 331–346). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Google Scholar
Garvey, B. (Ed.). (2014). J.L. Austin on Language. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Google Scholar
Genka, T. (2017). Chikaku to Handan no Kyoukaisen [The distinction between perception and cognition]. Tokyo: Keio University Press.
Google Scholar
Gerken, M., & Beebe, J. (2016). Knowledge in and out of contrast. Nous, 50, 133–164.
Google Scholar
Giora, R. (1997). Understanding figurative and literal language: The graded salience hypothesis. Cognitive Linguistics, 8, 183–206.
Google Scholar
Giora, R. (2003). On our mind. Salience, context, and figurative language. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Giora, R., & Fein, O. (1999). On understanding familiar and less-familiar figurative language. Journal of Pragmatics, 31, 1601–1618.
Google Scholar
Giora, R., Fein, O., Aschkenazi, K., & Alkabets-Zlozover, I. (2007a). Negation in context: A functional approach to suppression. Discourse Processes, 43, 153–172.
Google Scholar
Giora, R., Fein, O., Laadan, D., Wolfson, J., Zeituny, M., Kidron, R., et al. (2007b). Expecting irony: Context versus salience-based effects. Metaphor and Symbol, 22, 119–146.
Google Scholar
Giora, R., Raphaely, M., Fein, O., & Livnat, E. (2014). Resonating with contextually inappropriate interpretations: The case of irony. Cognitive Linguistics, 25, 443–455.
Google Scholar
Givoni, S., Giora, R., & Bergerbest, D. (2013). How speakers alert addressees to multiple meanings. Journal of Pragmatics, 48, 29–40.
Google Scholar
Goldberg, A. E. (2003). Constructions: A new theoretical approach to language. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 219–224.
Google Scholar
Goryo, K. (1987). Yomu toiu koto. (on reading). Tokyo: University of Tokyo Press.
Google Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 35, 121–152.
Google Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1989). Logic and conversation. In His: Studies in the ways of words (pp. 22-40). Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Grindrod, J., Andow, J., & Hansen, N. (2018). Third-person knowledge ascriptions: A crucial experiment for contextualism. Mind and Language. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12196.
Article
Google Scholar
Gustafsson, M., & Sørli, R. (2011). The philosophy of J.L. Austin. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Hampton, J. A., & Passanisi, A. (2016). When intensions do not map onto extensions: Individual differences in conceptualization. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 42, 505–523.
Google Scholar
Hanfling, O. (2000). Philosophy and ordinary language. London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Hansen, N. (2014). Contemporary ordinary language philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 9, 556–569.
Google Scholar
Hansen, N. (2017). Must we measure what we mean? Inquiry, 60, 785–815.
Google Scholar
Hansen, N. (2018). “Nobody would really talk that way!”: The critical project in contemporary ordinary language philosophy. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1812-x.
Article
Google Scholar
Hansen, N., & Chemla, E. (2013). Experimenting on contextualism. Mind and Language, 28, 286–321.
Google Scholar
Hansen, N., & Chemla, E. (2015). Linguistic experiments and ordinary language philosophy. Ratio, 28, 422–445.
Google Scholar
Hansen, N., Porter, J. D., & Francis, K. (under review). A corpus study of “know”: On the verification of philosophers’ frequency claims about language.
Hare, M., Jones, M., Thomson, C., Kelly, S., & McRae, K. (2009). Activating event knowledge. Cognition, 111, 151–167.
Google Scholar
Harmon-Vukić, M., Guéraud, S., Lassonde, K. A., & O’Brien, E. J. (2009). The activation and instantiation of instrumental inferences. Discourse Processes, 46, 467–490.
Google Scholar
Hawkins, J. A. (1994). A performance theory of order and constituency. Cambridge: CUP.
Google Scholar
Hawkins, J. A. (2004). Efficiency and complexity in grammars. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Horne, Z., & Livengood, J. (2017). Ordering effects, updating effects, and the spectre of global scepticism. Synthese, 194, 1189–1218.
Google Scholar
Horvath, J. (2010).
How (not) to react to
experimental philosophy.
Philosophical Psychology,
23, 447–480.
Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1739/1975). A treatise of human nature (revised by P.H. Nidditch). In L. A. Selby-Bigge (Ed.), 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Institute for Japanese Language and Linguistics and Lago Institute of Language. (2012). NINJAL-LWP for BCCWJNational (http://nlb.ninjal.ac.jp/).
Jackson, F. (1977). Perception. A representative theory. Cambridge: CUP.
Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. (1973). Attention and effort. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. London: Allen and Lane.
Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Frederick, S. (2002). Representativeness revisited: Attribute substitution in intuitive judgment. In T. Gilovich, et al. (Eds.), Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment (pp. 49–81). Cambridge: CUP.
Google Scholar
Kamas, E. N., Reder, L. M., & Ayers, M. S. (1996). Partial matching in the Moses illusion: Response bias not sensitivity. Memory and Cognition, 24, 687–699.
Google Scholar
Kamide, Y., Altmann, G. T. M., & Haywood, S. L. (2003). The time-course of prediction in incremental sentence processing: Evidence from anticipatory eye movements. Journal of Memory and Language, 49, 133–156.
Google Scholar
Kehler, A., Kertz, L., Rohde, H., & Elman, J. L. (2008). Coherence and co-reference revisited. Journal of Semantics, 25, 1–44.
Google Scholar
Kim, A. E., Oines, L. D., & Sikos, L. (2016). Prediction during sentence comprehension is more than a sum of lexical associations: The role of event knowledge. Language, Cognition, and Neuroscience, 31, 597–601.
Google Scholar
Kim, A. E., & Osterhout, L. (2005). The independence of combinatory semantic processing: Evidence from anticipatory eye-movements. Journal of Memory and Language, 52, 205–225.
Google Scholar
Klein, D. E., & Murphy, G. L. (2001). The representation of polysemous words. Journal of Memory and Language, 45, 259–282.
Google Scholar
Kutas, M., & Federmeier, K. T. (2000). Electrophysiology reveals semantic memory use in language comprehension. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 460–463.
Google Scholar
Kutas, M., & Federmeier, K. T. (2011). Thirty years and counting: Finding meaning in the N400 component of the event-related brain potential (ERP). Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 621–647.
Google Scholar
Laeng, B., Sirois, S., & Gredeback, G. (2012). Pupillometry: A window to the preconscious? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 18–27.
Google Scholar
Laugier, S. (2013). Why we need ordinary language philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Google Scholar
Leech, G., Rayson, P., & Wilson, A. (2001). Word frequencies in written and spoken English: Based on the British National Corpus. London: Longman.
Google Scholar
Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meanings. The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Google Scholar
Levy, B. J., & Anderson, M. C. (2002). Inhibitory processes and the control of memory retrieval. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, 299–305.
Google Scholar
Lewinski, M. (2012). The paradox of charity. Informal Logic, 32, 403–439.
Google Scholar
Loftus, E. F. (1973). Activation of semantic memory. The American Journal of Psychology, 86, 331–337.
Google Scholar
Lucas, M. (2000). Semantic priming without association: A meta-analytic review. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 7, 618–630.
Google Scholar
Lupker, S. J. (1984). Semantic priming without association: A second look. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 709–733.
Google Scholar
Machery, E. (2017). Philosophy within its proper bounds. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Mallon, R. (2016). Experimental philosophy. In H. Cappelen, T. Szabo Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophical methodology (pp. 410–433). Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Masuoka, T. (2002). Handan no modality [Modality of judgment]. Nihongogaku, 21(2), 6–16.
Google Scholar
Matsui, T. (2000). Linguistic encoding of the guarantee of relevance: Japanese sentence-final particle YO. In G. Anderson & T. Frethein (Eds.), Pragmatic Markers and propositional attitude (pp. 145–172). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Google Scholar
Matsuki, K., Chow, T., Hare, M., Elman, J. L., Scheepers, C., & McRae, K. (2011). Event-based plausibility immediately influences on-line language comprehension. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 37, 913–934.
Google Scholar
Maund, J. B. (1986). The phenomenal and other uses of ‘looks’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 170–180.
Google Scholar
McKoon, G., & Ratcliff, R. (1980). Priming in item recognition: The organization of propositions in memory for text. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 19, 369–386.
Google Scholar
McRae, K., Ferretti, T. R., & Amyote, I. (1997). Thematic roles as verb-specific concepts. Language and Cognitive Processes, 12, 137–176.
Google Scholar
McRae, K., Hare, M., Elman, J. L., & Ferretti, T. R. (2005). A basis for generating expectancies for verbs from nouns. Memory & Cognition, 33, 1174–1184.
Google Scholar
McRae, K., & Jones, M. (2013). Semantic memory. In D. Reisberg (Ed.), Oxford handbook of cognitive psychology. Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Mehler, J., Sebastian, N., Altmann, G., Dupoux, E., Christophe, A., & Pallier, C. (1993). Understanding compressed sentences: The role of rhythm and meaning. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 682, 272–282.
Google Scholar
Melinger, A., & Mauner, G. (1999). When are implicit agents encoded? Evidence from cross-modal priming. Brain and Language, 68, 185–191.
Google Scholar
Metusalem, R., Kutas, M., Urbach, T. P., Hare, M., McRae, K., & Elman, J. L. (2012). Generalized event knowledge activation during online sentence comprehension. Journal of Memory and Language, 66, 545–567.
Google Scholar
Minamide, K., & Nakamura, M. (Eds.). (2011). Genius Japanese–English dictionary (3rd ed.). Tokyo: Taishukan.
Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1918/19). Some judgments of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 19, 1–29.
Morewedge, C. K., & Kahneman, D. (2010). Associative processes in intuitive judgment. Trends in Cognitive Science, 14, 435–440.
Google Scholar
Morris, R. K. (1994). Lexical and message-level sentence context effects on fixation times in reading. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 20, 92–103.
Google Scholar
Murphy, T. (2014). Experimental philosophy 1935–1965. In J. Knobe, T. Lombrozo, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philosophy (Vol. 1, pp. 325–368). Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Nado, J. (2016).
Experimental
philosophy 2.0.
Thought, 5,
159–168.
Google Scholar
Naess, A. (1956). Logical equivalence, intentional isomorphism and synonymity as studied by questionnaires. Synthese, 10, 471–479.
Google Scholar
Naess, A. (1961). A study of “or”. Synthese, 13, 49–60.
Google Scholar
Nakagawa, S. (2004). A farewell to Bonferroni: The problems of low statistical power and publication bias. Behavioral Ecology, 15, 1044–1045.
Google Scholar
Neely, J. H., & Kahan, T. A. (2001). Is semantic activation automatic? A critical re-evaluation. In H. L. Roediger, J. S. Nairne, I. Neath, & A. M. Surprenant (Eds.), The nature of remembering (pp. 69–93). Washington, DC: APA.
Google Scholar
Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs, 41, 663–685.
Google Scholar
Nichols, S., & Pinillos, A. (2018). Skepticism and the acquisition of ‘knowledge’. Mind and Language. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12179.
Article
Google Scholar
Nobuhara, Y. (1999). Kokoro no Gendai Tetsugaku [Contemporary philosophy of mind]. Tokyo: Keiso Shobo.
Google Scholar
O’Brien, E. J., & Albrecht, J. E. (1992). Comprehension strategies in the development of a mental model. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 18, 777–784.
Google Scholar
Oden, G. C., & Spira, J. L. (1983). Influence of context on the activation and selection of ambiguous word senses. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 35A, 51–64.
Google Scholar
Oppenheimer, D. M. (2006). Consequences of erudite vernacular utilised irrespective of necessity: Problems with using long words needlessly. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 20, 139–156.
Google Scholar
Ortony, A. (1993). The role of similarity in similes and metaphors. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (2nd ed., pp. 342–356). Cambridge: CUP.
Google Scholar
Osterhout, L., Bersick, M., & McLaughlin, J. (1997). Brain potentials reflect violations of gender stereotypes. Memory & Cognition, 25, 273–285.
Google Scholar
Papineau, D. (2009). The poverty of analysis. Aristotelian Society Supplementary
Volumes, 83, 1–30.
Google Scholar
Park, H., & Reder, L. M. (2004). Moses illusion. In R. Pohl (Ed.), Cognitive illusions (pp. 275–291). New York: Psychology Press.
Google Scholar
Patson, N. D., & Warren, T. (2010). Eye movements to plausibility violations. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63, 1516–1532.
Google Scholar
Peleg, O., & Giora, R. (2011). Salient meanings: The whens and wheres. In K. M. Jaszczolt & K. Allan (Eds.), Salience and defaults in utterance processing (pp. 32–52). Berlin: de Gruyter.
Google Scholar
Pickering, M. J., & Garrod, S. (2013). An integrated theory of language production and comprehension. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 329–347.
Google Scholar
Pollock, J. L. (1986). Contemporary
theories of
knowledge.
Totowa, NJ:
Rowman and
Littlefield.
Google Scholar
Postal, P. (1973). On raising. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Google Scholar
Price, H. H. (1932). Perception. 2nd edn., repr.
1961. London: Methuen.
Rayner, K. (1998). Eye movements in reading and information processing: 20 years of research. Psychological Bulletin, 124, 372–422.
Google Scholar
Robinson, H. (2001). Perception. London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Rosnow, R. L., & Rosenthal, R. (2003). Effect sizes for experimenting psychologists. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 57, 221–237.
Google Scholar
Rumelhart, D. E. (1978). Schemata: The building blocks of cognition. In R. Spiro, B. Bruce, & W. Brewer (Eds.), Theoretical issues in reading comprehension. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1912/1980). The problems of philosophy, Oxford: OUP.
Russell, B. (1964). Tetsugaku Nyuumon in 1912 (Russell, Ed., H. Nakamura, Trans.). Tokyo: Shakaishisousha.
Russell, B. (1965). Tetsugaku Nyuumon in 1912 (Russell, Ed., K. Ikumatsu, Trans.). Tokyo: Kadokawa Shoten.
Russell, B. (1967). Probleme der Philosophie in 1912 (Russell, Ed., E. Bubser, Trans.). Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Russell, B. (2005). Tetsugaku Nyuumon in 1912 (Russell, Ed., N. Takamura, Trans.). Tokyo: Chikuma Shobo.
Sasanuma, S. (1980). Acquired dyslexia in Japanese: Clinical features and underlying mechanisms. In M. Coltheart, K. Patterson, & J. C. Marshall (Eds.), Deep dyslexia (pp. 48–90). London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Schaffer, J., & Knobe, J. (2012). Contrastive knowledge surveyed. Noûs, 46, 675–708.
Google Scholar
Scholze-Stubenrecht, W., & Sykes, J. B. (Eds.). (1999). Duden-Oxford, Großwörterbuch Englisch (2nd ed.). Mannheim: Dudenverlag.
Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1993). Metaphor. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (2nd ed., pp. 83–111). Cambridge: CUP.
Google Scholar
Searle, J. (2001). J.L. Austin. In A. Martinich & D. Sosa (Eds.), A companion to analytic philosophy (pp. 218–230). Oxford: Blackwell.
Google Scholar
Shattuck-Hufnagel, S., & Klatt, D. H. (1979). The limited use of distinctive features and markedness in speech production: Evidence from speech error data. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 41–55.
Google Scholar
Shynkaruk, J. M., & Thompson, V. A. (2006). Confidence and accuracy in deductive reasoning. Memory and Cognition, 34, 619–632.
Google Scholar
Simmons, J. P., & Nelson, L. D. (2006). Intuitive confidence: Choosing between intuitive and non-intuitive alternatives. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 409–428.
Google Scholar
Simpson, G. B., & Burgess, C. (1985). Activation and selection processes in the recognition of ambiguous words. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 11, 28–39.
Google Scholar
Smith, A. D. (2002). The problem of perception. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Google Scholar
Springer, O. (Ed.). (2000). Langenscheidts Enzyklopädisches Wörterbuch der englischen und deutschen Sprache: “Der Große Muret-Sanders“ (Vol. 2). Berlin: Langenscheidt.
Google Scholar
Staudacher, A. (2011). Das Problem der Wahrnehmung. Paderborn: Mentis.
Google Scholar
Stephens, G. J., Silber, L. J., & Hasson, U. (2010). Speaker-listener neural coupling underlies successful communication. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107, 14425–14430.
Google Scholar
Stich, S., & Tobia, K. (2016). Experimental philosophy and the philosophical tradition. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), Blackwell companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 5–21). Malden: Wiley Blackwell.
Google Scholar
Sturt, P. (2003). A new look at the syntax-discourse interface: The use of binding principles in sentence processing. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 32, 125–139.
Google Scholar
Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2016). The theory and practice of experimental philosophy. Peterborough: Broadview.
Google Scholar
Tanenhaus, M. K., & Carlson, G. N. (1989). Lexical structure and language comprehension. In W. Marslen-Wilson (Ed.), Lexical representation and process (pp. 529–561). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Google Scholar
Tanenhaus, M. K., Carlson, G. N., & Trueswell, J. T. (1989). The role of thematic structures in interpretation and parsing. Language and Cognitive Processes, 4, 211–234.
Google Scholar
Thagard, P., & Nisbett, R. E. (1983). Rationality and charity. Philosophy of Science, 50, 250–267.
Google Scholar
Thompson, V. A., Prowse Turner, J. A., & Pennycook, G. (2011). Intuition, reason, and metacognition. Cognitive Psychology, 63, 107–140.
Google Scholar
Till, R. E., Mross, E. F., & Kintsch, W. (1988). Time course of priming for associate and inference words in a discourse context. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behaviour, 16, 283–298.
Google Scholar
Traxler, M. J., Foss, D. J., Seely, R. E., & Morris, R. K. (2000). Priming in sentence processing: Intralexical spreading activation, schemas, and situation models. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 29, 581–595.
Google Scholar
Tsai, C. I., & Thomas, M. (2011). When does feeling of fluency matter? How abstract and concrete thinking influence fluency effects. Psychological Science, 22, 348–354.
Google Scholar
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1982). Judgments of and by representativeness. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. (1969). A symposium on Austin’s method. Part I. In K. T. Fann (Ed.), Symposium on J.L. Austin (pp. 76–86). London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Watanabe, T., Skrzypczak, E. R., & Snowden, P. (Eds.). (2003). Kenkyusha’s new Japanese-English dictionary (5th ed.). Tokyo: Kenkyusha.
Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. (2015). Humans as instruments, on the inevitability of experimental philosophy. In E. Fischer & J. Collins (Eds.), Experimental philosophy, rationalism, and naturalism (pp. 171–187). London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. (2016). Intuitions. In H. Cappelen, T. Szabo Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophical methodology (pp. 287–308). Oxford: OUP.
Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M. (2017). What is negative experimental philosophy good for? In G. D’Oro & S. Overgaard (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to philosophical methodology (pp. 161–183). Cambridge: CUP.
Google Scholar
Welke, T., Raisig, S., Nowack, K., Schaadt, G., Hagendorf, H., & van der Meer, E. (2015). Semantic priming of progression features in events. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 44, 201–214.
Google Scholar
Wheeldon, L. R., & Levelt, W. J. M. (1995). Monitoring the time course of phonological encoding. Journal of Memory and Language, 34, 311–334.
Google Scholar
Wiesing, L. (2002). Philosophie der Wahrnehmung. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a.M.
Google Scholar
Williams, M. (1996). Unnatural doubts. Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar
Williams, B. (2014). Essays and reviews: 1959–2002. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.
Google Scholar
Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Google Scholar
Wittgenstein (1933/2005). The big typescript TS 213 (Ed., C.G. Luckardt & M.A.E. Aue, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.