Skip to main content
Log in

Conceivability arguments for haecceitism

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to haecceitism, some maximal possibilities differ even while they are qualitatively indiscernible. Since haecceitism is a modal thesis, it is typically defended by appeal to conceivability arguments. These arguments require us to conceive of qualitatively indiscernible possibilities that differ only with respect to the identity of the individuals involved. This paper examines a series of conceivability arguments for haecceitism and a variety of anti-haecceitist responses. It concludes that there is no irresistible conceivability argument for haecceitism even while anti-haecceitist responses do come with certain notable commitments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The distinction between qualitative and non-qualitative possibilities is closely aligned with the de re/de dicto distinction. I leave open their precise relationship and focus on the former in what follows. For discussion, see Plantinga (1969) and Kaplan (1967).

  2. On the distinction between qualitative and non-qualitative properties, see Adams (1979) and Cowling (2015a). In what follows, I assume haecceities exist. Some views might draw the distinction between qualitative and non-qualitative possibilities without appeal to haecceities (e.g., by relying on some notion of individual-dependent possibilities).

  3. On maximal possibilities, see Stalnaker (1987).

  4. On some views, the relation of inclusion is entailment, since possibilities are identical with propositions. On a nearby view, inclusion is understood set-theoretically, since possibilities are just sets of propositions. In what follows, we can remain neutral between these frameworks, but, on ersatzism and its varieties, see Lewis (1986), Adams (1981), Forrest (1986), and Sider (2002).

  5. Possibility anti-haecceitists include Dasgupta (2009), Forbes (1985) and Robinson (1989), while possible world anti-haecceitism, introduced below, is more widespread and endorsed by Lewis (1986) and Sider (2002). In defining haecceitism and in presenting some of the arguments below, I follow Cowling (2015b) but go beyond that discussion to consider the merits of the relevant conceivability arguments for haecceitism as well as the space of anti-haecceitist responses.

  6. A few examples: on the role of haecceitism in the metaphysics of probability, see Kment (2012); on haecceitism, determinism, and the metaphysics of spacetime, see Melia (1999) and Russell (2014); on haecceitism and the metaphysics of content, see Stalnaker (2008).

  7. I leave open broader issues about the general taxonomy of arguments for haecceitism. For example, “Chisholm’s Paradox,” which is discussed but not endorsed in Chisholm (1967), might reasonably be counted as a conceivability argument. That said, its sorites-driven structure makes it worth treating as a somewhat separate case. For discussion, see Salmon (1986) and Lewis (1986, pp. 220–247). Since my focus will be on direct conceivability arguments, I leave open whether certain arguments that appeal to the nature of content, probability, or other notions are properly counted as conceivability arguments. See, e.g., Stalnaker (2008, pp. 69–71) and Kment (2012).

  8. While I draw on several of the arguments briefly mentioned in Cowling (2015b), this discussion also evaluates the merits of these arguments, the nature of imagination involved, and the prospects for a comprehensive anti-haecceitist response.

  9. On the Cartesian distinction between conceivability as a kind of pure understanding and imaginability as a sort of degenerate internal sense, see Gendler and Hawthorne (2002).

  10. On the various senses of imagination, see Ryle (1949) and Kind (2013). On the various senses of conceivability, see Chalmers (2002) and Yablo (1993).

  11. These rough distinctions follow those drawn in Chalmers (2002), but, unlike Chalmers, I leave aside issues regarding primary and secondary conceivability. These issues come into play in accounting for the singular content of our imaginings, but we can usefully hold the descriptivist/anti-descriptivist debate in check here.

  12. Thanks here to anonymous referee for a useful point of clarification.

  13. Lewis’ rejection of possible world haecceitism is a complicated matter and owes largely to his commitment to the supervenience of de re representation upon qualitative character. That said, since Lewis endorses possibility haecceitism, he allows that a given world represents a plurality of maximal possibilities that differ only haecceitistically from one another. Notably, such a view does not require possible world haecceitism. Additionally, Lewis is agnostic about whether there are qualitatively indiscernible worlds. On Lewisian haecceitism, see Cowling (2012), Fara (2009), Russell (2013), Skow (2009), and Sider (2002).

  14. I have in mind here modalists who reject possible worlds but hold that some total ways things could have been are distinct yet qualitatively indiscernible. On modalism, see Melia (2003).

  15. I assume duplicates share all of their intrinsic qualitative properties, while qualitatively indiscernible individuals share all of their intrinsic and extrinsic qualitative properties.

  16. Jubien (1993, pp. 41–42) considers a similar argument involving qualitatively indiscernible spheres swapping locations. Melia (2003, p. 162) also considers a similar argument, which involves a homogenous cylinder falling upon on a homogenous plane.

  17. For simplicity’s sake, I assume that maximal possibilities can “include” individuals by way of including the possibility that they exist.

  18. See Kripke (1980, pp. 103–104, 141–150). For Kripke, modal illusion occurs, roughly, when an individual imagines a “qualitatively identical epistemic situation” to her actual one, where the meanings of terms fixed by description pick out different individuals or properties than they actually do. The precise features of modal illusion are a matter of some controversy, but, as with the present notion of “modal delusion,” it shows a kind of epistemic insensitivity to singular content and the primary role that qualitative (or, as I discuss later, experiential content) plays in forming our modal beliefs. For discussion of “textbook Kripkeanism”, see Yablo (2005). For a dissenting interpretation, see Byrne (2006). See also Soames (2006), Gendler and Hawthorne (2002) on the nature of modal illusion.

  19. Haecceitists might object that anti-haecceitists violate plausible principles about plenitude. One such principle holds that, for any actual individual, there is a maximal possibility that contains only that individual. As a result, we should be able to “subtract” the rest of actuality and be left with different maximal possibilities—e.g., one involving Lois and another involving Lana. Against this response, anti-haecceitists can claim such principles are guides only to qualitative possibility and claim that, for any actual individual, there is indeed a maximal possibility that contains only a qualitative duplicate of that individual.

  20. On the nature and significance of the distinction between inside and outside imagination, see Kung (MS), Nichols (2008), Nagel (2003), Ninan (2008), and Peacocke (1985).

  21. A natural way to clarify the inside-outside distinction is to identify inside contents with sets of centered possible worlds and outside contents with sets of (uncentered) possible worlds. While this is a helpful heuristic, it is unavailable at the moment, since the question of haecceitism is closely connected with whether we need to model inside contents as sets of worlds or as sets of centered worlds. On centered worlds, see Liao (2012). On centered contents, see Stalnaker (2008).

  22. The connection between singular content and experiential content is a matter of no small controversy. On some views, sameness of experiential content will require sameness of singular content. Here, I assume that singular content can come apart from experiential content in various ways. I will also assume that experiential content is exhausted by qualitative content and, as such, our experiential content does not include the experience of haecceities or non-qualitative features. While contentious, our present project is to offer the best available defense of anti-haecceitism and, since these assumptions bolster the anti-haecceitist position, I take these assumptions to be dialectically appropriate here.

  23. In a world of one-way eternal recurrence, your doppelgangers are duplicates of you, but not qualitatively indiscernible from you, since you differ regarding your distance from the first epoch. We could equally well focus on a world of two-way recurrence where your doppelgangers are qualitatively indiscernible from you, but this would incur technicalities about naming epochs.

  24. A similar case might draw upon a revised version of the Two Gods case from Lewis (1979). But, where Lewis’ gods differ qualitatively, an analogue of the present cases requires the gods to be qualitatively indiscernible and to have qualitatively indiscernible experiences.

  25. Any argument that invokes inside imagination has a corresponding version that invokes outside imagination, but not conversely. Perhaps, however, one might accept the possibility of idealist worlds of “pure subjectivity” that have no imaginable general content and can therefore be imagined exclusively from the inside. But, then again, perhaps not. On idealism and inside imagination, see Peacocke (1985).

  26. Essentialists of an especially strict sort might deny that you could possibly inhabit eternal recurrence worlds in the first place. Such views will, of course, require strict and difficult to motivate constraints on essence, but faced with the lurking arbitrariness, they look more plausible here than elsewhere. On this point, thanks to an anonymous referee.

  27. Bricker (2007, p. 130).

  28. On the impossibility of imagining our own nonexistence from the inside, see Nichols (2007).

  29. As will be discussed below, there are competing views about the structure of the content of inside imagination. If we opt for a tripartite view, which distinguishes singular and experiential content as well as subject-centered content—i.e., whom one imagines being—this anti-haecceitist response to the Replacement Argument does presuppose that we can only imagine being ourselves. But, as I argue below, if we grant that we can imagine ourselves being some else altogether, anti-haecceitists can use the Modal Disassociation Strategy to undermine the Replacement Argument.

  30. Lewis (1986, p. 231). Skow (2009) uses a similar case to diagnose haecceitistic tendencies. Here, I assume our interest to be in possibilities that do not involve contingent identity, but, rather, Lewis “replacing” Fred altogether.

  31. One might worry here that, since the relevant inside arguments involve imaginings from one’s own perspective, such arguments can succeed only in establishing haecceitistic possibilities for one’s self and not for others. For haecceitists, the natural response is that, if haecceitistic possibilities of any sort can be established, we can reason, on the basis of the non-arbitrary nature of modality, to other comparable haecceitistic possibilities. Alternatively, as we’ll see below, haecceitists can endorse a view of imagination that allow us to inside imagine being other individuals altogether. If that’s right, then there is no barrier to inside imagining haecceitistic scenarios concerning other individuals (though, as we’ll also see, this view of imagination opens the door to a powerful anti-haecceitistic response). Thanks to an anonymous referee here.

  32. On the relevant forms of essentialism, see Kripke (1980) and Roca-Royes (2011).

  33. Lewis (1986, p. 231).

  34. See Adams (1979, p. 22). This presentation follows Cowling (2015b).

  35. One might reasonably worry about the kind and origin properties of individuals on Adams’ globes, but it’s not hard to fill out the details of the Global Destruction Argument to address these concerns (e.g., by locating these events on a single highly symmetric planet with common biological origins). Alternatively, we could consider an inside imagined version of a case owing to Melia (1999, p. 650): “We could imagine a collection of bald philosophers, sitting in a circle. It is a law that one of them will grow a single hair. But, by the symmetry of the situation, any of the philosophers could be the lucky one. Again, our intuition is that there are many qualitatively isomorphic but distinct possibilities...”

  36. On competing models of inside imagination and the distinction between imagining yourself being otherwise and imagining replacing someone altogether, see Kung (MS).

  37. If you take it to be metaphysically impossible that you have a twin, it will turn out that the present argument for haecceitistic possibilities gives a notable pride of place to those with actual biological twins.

  38. Russell (1912) defends a constraint on acquaintance and, in turn, propositional constituency that rules out individuals having other individuals—indeed, anything other than one’s self, sense data, or universals—as the contents of one’s thoughts. Such a constraint, applied to this tripartite view, would seem to require the fixed view in question. Here, I assume anti-haecceitists reject the constraint in question.

  39. The weight of skeptical worries in evaluating metaphysical theories is controversial. See Gendler and Hawthorne (2002, p. 365), Lewis (2009), and Schaffer (2005) for discussion.

  40. Anti-haecceitists of this sort take their inspiration from the assessment of Ramseyan Humility in Schaffer (2005), who holds Ramseyan Humility to be “external world skepticism writ small.”

  41. Mackie (2009) accepts haecceitism and endorses a minimal essentialism that admits certain extreme haecceitist possibilities but holds that individuals have certain metaphysical features like their ontological category essentially. Kripke (1980) seems to accept haecceitism along with origin essentialism.

  42. For those who find haecceitism more intuitively plausible than its property-theoretic analogue, quidditism, these findings offer a natural explanation of the difference in plausibility: the most compelling conceivability arguments for haecceitism are inside arguments, but no inside arguments can be offered in defense of quidditism, since only individuals but not properties can be imagined from the inside. On quidditism, see Black (2000) and Schaffer (2005).

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1979). Primitive thisness and primitive identity. Journal of Philosophy, 76, 5–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. M. (1981). Actualism and thisness. Synthese, 49, 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, R. (2000). Against quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 87–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (2007). Concrete possible worlds. In T. Sider, et al. (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (2008). Concrete possible worlds. In D. Zimmerman, T. Sider & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics (pp. 111–134). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Byrne, A. (2006). Possibility and imagination. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 125–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1967). Identity through possible worlds. Nous, 1, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowling, S. (2012). Haecceitism for modal realists. Erkenntnis, 77(3), 399–417.

  • Cowling, S. (2015a). Non-qualitative properties. Erkenntnis, 80(2), 275–301.

  • Cowling, S. (2015b). Haecceitism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/haecceitism/.

  • Dasgupta, S. (2009). Individuals: An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 35–67.

  • Fara, D. G. (2009). Dear haecceitism. Erkenntnis, 70, 285–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (1985). The metaphysics of modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1986). Ways a world could be. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 15–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S., & Hawthorne, J. (Eds.). (2002). Conceivability and possibility. Oxford University Press.

  • Jubien, M. (1993). Ontology, modality, and the fallacy of reference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1967). Transworld heir lines. In M. Loux (Ed.), The possible and the actual. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2013). The heterogeneity of imagination. Erkenntnis, 78, 141–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kment, B. (2012). Haecceitism, chance, and counterfactuals. Philosophical Review, 121, 573–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (MS). Imagining, inside and out.

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review, 88, 513–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–222). MIT Press.

  • Liao, S.-Y. (2012). What are centered worlds? Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 294–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, P. (2009). How things might have been. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (1999). Holes, haecceitism, and two conceptions of determinism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 639–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2003). Modality. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2003). The psychophysical nexus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2007). Imagination and immortality. Synthese, 159, 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2008). Imagination and the I. Mind and Language, 23, 518–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ninan, D. (2008). Imagination, content, and the self. M.I.T., Ph.D. dissertation.

  • Peacocke, C. (1985). Imagination, experience, and possibility. In J. Foster & H. Robinson (Eds.), Essays on Berkeley. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1969). De dicto et de re. Nous, 3, 235–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. (1989). Matter, motion and Humean supervenience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 67, 394–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roca-Royes, S. (2011). Essential properties and individual essences. Philosophy Compass, 6, 75–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Barnes & Noble Books.

  • Russell, J. (2013). Possible worlds and the objective world. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 389–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. (2014). On where things could be. Philosophy of Science, 81(1), 60–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1986). Modal paradox: Parts and counterparts, points and counterpoints. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 11, 75–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Quiddistic knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 123, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2002). The ersatz pluriverse. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 279–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2009). Haecceitism, anti-haecceitism, and possible worlds. Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 98–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2006). Kripke, the necessary a posteriori, and the two dimensionalist heresy. In M. Garcia-Carpintero & J. Macia (Eds.), The two-dimensional framework: Foundations and applications (pp. 272–292). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1987). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2008). Our knowledge of the internal world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, D. (1996). Self to self. Philosophical Review, 105, 39–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2005). No fool’s gold. In M. Garcia-Carpintero & J. Macia (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sam Cowling.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cowling, S. Conceivability arguments for haecceitism. Synthese 194, 4171–4190 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1136-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1136-7

Keywords

Navigation